Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-lj6df Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T14:22:05.819Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Towards an Expanded Epistemology for Approximations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Jeffry L. Ramsey*
Affiliation:
Rice University

Extract

Since “one can seldom directly deduce from a speculation consequences that are even in principle testable,” a scientist must “articulate” a theory, mathematically altering a given speculation to bring it “into greater resonance with the world” (Hacking 1983, p. 214). When confronted with computational difficulties caused by analytically intractable equations, imprecise specifications of initial conditions, or the absence of required auxiliary theories, scientists commonly articulate a theory by applying approximations and idealizations to the theoretical equations they have at hand. Recognizing this, the following question immediately arises for both the scientist and the philosopher of science, “How does one judge the quality of a particular approximation? I.e., when is a given approximation valid?“

Type
Part IV. Issues in Methodology
Copyright
Copyright © 1992 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

Much of this paper is based on material in my dissertation (Ramsey 1990a). Many thanks to Bill Wimsatt, R. Stephen Berry, and Dan Garber for helpful criticism and comments on the dissertation.

References

Aronson, J. (1990), “Verisimilitude and Type Hierarchies”, Philosophical Topics 18:5-28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balzer, W., Ulises-Moulines, C, and Sneed, J. (1987), An Architectonic for Science: The Structuralist Program. Boston: D.Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boltzmann, L. (1898), Vorlesungen ueber Gastheorie. Leipzig: J.A. Barth.Google Scholar
Boltzmann, L. (1964), Lectures on Gas Theory, (trans.) S.G. Brush. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1983), How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feynman, R. (1967), The Character of Physical Law. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Giere, R. (1988), Constructing Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. (1983), Representing and Intervening. New York: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511814563CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laymon, R. (1983), “Newton's Demonstration of Universal Gravitation and Philosophical Theories of Confirmation”, in Testing Scientific Theories Earman, J. (ed.). Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, volume X. Minneapolis: Minnesota University Press, pp. 179-199.Google Scholar
Laymon, R. (1984), “The Path from Data to Theory”, in Scientific Realism, Leplin, J. (ed). Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 108-123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laymon, R. (1987), “Using Scott Domains to Explicate the Notions of Approximate and Idealized Data”, Philosophy of Science 54:194-221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laymon, R.(1989), “Cartwright and the Lying Laws of Physics”, Journal of Philosophy 86: 353-372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, E. (1988), The Structure and Confirmation of Evolutionary Theory. New York: Greenwood Press.Google Scholar
Niinuluoto, I. (1986), “Theories, Approximations and Idealizations”, in Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science VII, Barcan Marcus, R. , et al. (ed.). Amsterdam: North Holland, pp. 255-289.Google Scholar
Ramsey, J. (1990a), “Meta-Stable States: The Justification of Approximative Procedures in Chemical Kinetics, 1923-1947”, unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, Committee on the Conceptual Foundations of Science, University of Chicago, May 1990.Google Scholar
Ramsey, J.(1990b), “Beyond Numerical and Causal Accuracy: Expanding the Set of Justificational Criteria”, PSA 1990, volume 1, Forbes, M. and Fine, A. (eds.). East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 485-499.Google Scholar
Redhead, M.L.G. (1975), “Symmetry in Intertheory Relations”, Synthese 32:77-112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Teller, P. (1983), “The Projection Postulate as a Fortuitous Approximation”, Philosophy of Science 50:413-431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Truesdell, C. (1984), An Idiot's Fugitive Essays on Science: Methods, Criticism, Training, Circumstances. New York: Springer-Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar