Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-ndw9j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-18T08:40:27.171Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Understanding institutions: replies to Aoki, Binmore, Hodgson, Searle, Smith, and Sugden

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 March 2015

FRANK HINDRIKS
Affiliation:
Faculty of Philosophy, University of Groningen, Groningen, the Netherlands
FRANCESCO GUALA*
Affiliation:
Department of Economics, Management and Quantitative Studies, Università degli Studi di Milano, Italy

Abstract

Our goal is to develop a theory that combines the best insights of philosophical and scientific theories of institutions. We are not committed a priori to save the commonsense notion of institution, or the thesis of human exceptionalism. We think that human cognition is important, but we do not claim that common knowledge or collective intentions are necessary for coordination. Like most of our commentators, we believe that there is continuity between simple rules of precedence and sophisticated institutions like property, marriage, or money. Finally, we argue that a satisfactory account of institutions must be compatible with different theories of normativity, specifying the social and psychological mechanisms that make it possible to override selfish desires.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Millennium Economics Ltd 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aoki, M. (2015), ‘Why is the Equilibrium Notion Essential for a Unified Institutional Theory? A Friendly Remark on the Article by Hindriks and Guala’, Journal of Institutional Economics, published online. doi: 10.1017/S1744137415000090.Google Scholar
Bicchieri, C. (2006), The Grammar of Society, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Binmore, K. (2010), ‘Do Conventions Need to Be Common Knowledge?’, Topoi, 27: 1727.Google Scholar
Binmore, K. (2014), ‘Institutions, Rules and Equilibria: A Commentary’, Journal of Institutional Economics, published online. doi: 10.1017/S1744137414000599.Google Scholar
Broome, J. (2013), Rationality Through Reasoning, Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Frank, R. (1987), Passions Within Reason, New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. (1990), Wise Choices, Apt Feelings, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, M. (1989), On Social Facts, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Guala, F. and Hindriks, F. (2014), ‘A Unified Social Ontology’, Philosophical Quarterly, doi: 10.1093/pq/pqu072.Google Scholar
Guala, F. and Mittone, L. (2010), ‘How History and Conventions Create Norms: An Experimental Study’, Journal of Economic Psychology, 31: 749756.Google Scholar
Hakli, R., Miller, K., and Tuomela, R. (2010), ‘Two Kinds of We-Reasoning’, Economics and Philosophy, 26: 291320.Google Scholar
Hindriks, F. (2013), ‘Collective Acceptance and the Is-Ought Argument’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 16: 465480.Google Scholar
Hindriks, F. and Guala, F. (2014), ‘Institutions, Rules, and Equilibria: A Unified Theory’, Journal of Institutional Economics, published online, doi: 10.1017/S1744137414000496.Google Scholar
Hodgson, G. M. (2006), ‘What Are Institutions?’, Journal of Economic Issues, 15: 123.Google Scholar
Hodgson, G. M. (2015), ‘Much of the “Economics of Property Rights” Devalues Property and Legal Rights’, Journal of Institutional Economics, published online. doi:10.1017/S1744137415000028.Google Scholar
Hodgson, T., Guala, F., Miller, T., and Summers, I. (2012), ‘Limbic and Prefrontal Activity during Conformity and Violation of Norms in a Coordination Game’, Journal of Neuroscience, Psychology, and Economics, 5, 117.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. (1969), Convention: A Philosophical Study, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
MacCormick, N. (1998), ‘Norms, Institutions, and Institutional Facts’, Law and Philosophy, 17: 301345.Google Scholar
Nichols, S. (2004), Norms with Feelings, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. (1999), ‘Explaining Normativity: On Rationality and the Justification of Reason’, Ratio, 12: 354379.Google Scholar
Searle, J. R. (2010), Making the Social World, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Searle, J. R. (2015), ‘On Status Functions and Institutional Facts: Reply to Hindriks and Guala’, Journal of Institutional Economics, published online. doi: 10.1017/S1744137414000629.Google Scholar
Skorupski, J. (2010), The Domain of Reason, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, V. L. (2015), ‘Conduct, Rules and the Origins of Institutions’, Journal of Institutional Economics, published online. doi: 10.1017/S1744137414000605.Google Scholar
Sugden, R. (1998), ‘Normative Expectations: The Simultaneous Evolution of Institutions and Norms’, in Ben-Ner, A. and Putterman, L. (eds.), Economics, Values, and Organization, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 73100.Google Scholar
Sugden, R. (2015), ‘On “common sense ontology”: A Comment on the Paper by Frank Hindriks and Francesco Guala’, Journal of Institutional Economics, published online. doi: 10.1017/S174413741500003X.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tuomela, R. (1985), A Theory of Social Action, Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar