Article contents
In Search of a First-Person Plural, Second-Best Theory of Constitutional Interpretation
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 06 March 2019
Extract
The purpose of this paper is not to argue for a particular approach to constitutional interpretation, but to map the domain thereof and clarify the requirements that an adequate theory of the subject must meet. A comprehensive constitutional theory has to address both how and by whom a given constitution should be interpreted. While everyone admits that these two issues are not entirely unrelated, many constitutional theorists presume that a theory of constitutional interpretation can usefully insulate these two questions. The argument is that once we have answered the question of who will interpret the constitution and we have made a decision on institutional design, we can then focus our efforts on the proper method of interpretation. Although I do not deny that the two questions can be analytically separated, my contention is that a theory of constitutional interpretation focusing only on the how question is wholly inadequate.
- Type
- Part A: Political Theory and Constitutional Reasoning
- Information
- German Law Journal , Volume 14 , Issue 8: Special Issue - Constitutional Reasoning , 01 August 2013 , pp. 1077 - 1107
- Copyright
- Copyright © 2013 by German Law Journal GbR
References
1 See, e.g., Sotirios A. Barber & James E. Fleming, Constitutional Interpretation: The Basic Questions xv–xvi (2007); Dworkin, Ronald, Law's Empire 370 (1986) [hereinafter Law's Empire].Google Scholar
2 Ronald Dworkin, , Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution 1–38 (1997) [hereinafter Freedom's Law].Google Scholar
3 Id. Google Scholar
4 For an account of these theories as attempts to put forward amoral methods of interpretation, see Barber & Fleming, supra note 1, at 65.Google Scholar
5 Scalia, Antonin, Originalism: The Lesser Evil, 57 U. Cin. L. Rev. 849, 864 (1989).Google Scholar
6 Bork, Robert H., The Tempting of America: The Political Seduction of the Law 146 (First Touchstone ed. 1991).Google Scholar
7 Kyllo v. United States, 533 U.S. 27 (2001).Google Scholar
8 See, e.g., Keith E. Whittington, The New Originalism, 2 Geo.J.L. & Pub.Pol'y 599, 611 (2004) (“[O]riginalists should explicitly admit: interpretation requires judgment. It is not a mechanical process, and interpretive results cannot be rigidly determined.”).Google Scholar
9 For a criticism of this argument, see Andrew B. Coan, Irrelevance of Writtenness in Constitutional Interpretation, 158 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1025 (2010).Google Scholar
10 See Whittington, , supra note 8, at 612. But see Bork, supra note 6 at 177; Scalia, supra note 5 at 862.Google Scholar
11 Thayer, James B., The Origin and Scope of the American Doctrine of Constitutional Law, 7 Harv. L. Rev. 129 (1893).Google Scholar
12 Dworkin, Freedom's Law, supra note 2, at 2.Google Scholar
13 Id. Google Scholar
14 Id. at 10.Google Scholar
15 Rawls, John, Political Liberalism 54–58 (1993).Google Scholar
16 This distinction is similar to the one made by Jeremy Waldron between first-order and second-order values; but, because this terminology could be confused with the first-best/second-best distinction that is central to section B. III., I use different terminology to avoid confusion. See Jeremy Waldron, Law and Disagreement 196 (1999).Google Scholar
17 Dworkin, , Law's Empire, supra note 1, at 370.Google Scholar
18 Id. Google Scholar
19 Thayer, , supra note 11.Google Scholar
20 See Sunstein, Cass R., Foreword: Leaving Things Undecided, 110 Harv. L. Rev. 4 (1996) [hereinafter Leaving Things Undecided]; Cass R. Sunstein, Burkean Minimalism, 105 Mich.L. Rev. 353 (2006) [hereinafter Burkean Minimalism]; Cass R. Sunstein, Second-Order Perfectionism, 75 Fordham L. Rev. 2867 (2007) [hereinafter Second-Order].Google Scholar
21 See Sunstein, , Leaving Things Undecided, supra note 20, at 15–25.Google Scholar
22 Joseph, Raz, Practical Reason and Norms 35–48 (1990).Google Scholar
23 See Barber & Fleming, supra note 1, at 29.Google Scholar
24 Dworkin, , Law's Empire, supra note 1.Google Scholar
25 Dworkin, Ronald, Equality, Democracy, and Constitution: We the People in Court, 28 Alta. L. Rev. 324 (1990); Dworkin, Ronald, The Partnership Conception of Democracy, 86 Calif. L. Rev. 453 (1998); Dworkin, , Freedom's Law, supra note 2.Google Scholar
26 Dworkin, Ronald, The Forum of Principle, 56 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 469 (1981).Google Scholar
27 See Primus, Richard A., When Should Original Meanings Matter, 107 Mich. L. Rev. 165 (2008).Google Scholar
28 Id. at 172.Google Scholar
29 See Sunstein, Cass R. & Vermeule, Adrian, Interpretation and Institutions, 101 Mich. L. Rev. 885 (2003).Google Scholar
30 See Vermeule, Adrian, Judging Under Uncertainty: An Institutional Theory of Legal Interpretation 63–85 (2006); Sunstein, & Vermeule, , supra note 29, at 886.Google Scholar
31 Sunstein, & Vermeule, , supra note 29, at 914–15.Google Scholar
32 Vermeule, , supra note 30, at 13.Google Scholar
33 Vermeule, , supra note30, at 2; Sunstein & Vermeule, supra note 29, at 915–19.Google Scholar
34 Sunstein, Cass R., Five Theses on Originalism, 19 Harv. J. L. & Pub. Pol'y 311, 311 (1996).Google Scholar
35 Vermeule, , supra note 30, at 45.Google Scholar
36 Id. at 237.Google Scholar
37 Id. at 3.Google Scholar
38 Vermeule, Adrian, Law and the Limits of Reason 8 (2009); Waldron, Jeremy, The Core of the Case Against Judicial Review, 115 Yale L. J. 1346, 1373–74 (2006).Google Scholar
39 Vermeule, , supra note 30, at 5.Google Scholar
40 Waldron, , supra note 38, at 1372–73.Google Scholar
41 Vermeule, , supra note 30, at 3.Google Scholar
42 See Ackerman, Bruce, We the People: Foundations (1993).Google Scholar
43 Id. at 6–16.Google Scholar
44 Id. at 12.Google Scholar
45 For Ackerman's hypothetical case about the anti-establishment clause, see id. at 14.Google Scholar
46 Id. at 15.Google Scholar
47 Id. at 14Google Scholar
48 Id. at 14–15.Google Scholar
49 Id. Google Scholar
50 I remain agnostic on the question of whether the text should impose an absolute limit on interpretation. One could argue that the very concept of constitutional interpretation makes sense only if the text draws the outer limits of possible interpretations. Others hold the opinion that while the text is important, it does not impose absolute limits on interpretation. For a conventionalist explanation of the importance of the text, see David A. Strauss, Common Law Constitutional Interpretation, 63 U. Chi. L. Rev. 877, 906–25 (1996).Google Scholar
51 For a sophisticated defense of procedural democracy, see Richard Bellamy, Political Constitutionalism: A Republican Defence of the Constitutionality of Democracy (2007).Google Scholar
52 Vermeule, , supra note 30, at 4. Though, I should emphasize that Vermeule does not defend formalism on procedural grounds.Google Scholar
53 Bork, , supra note 6, at 146.Google Scholar
54 See, e.g., Whittington, supra note 8, at 609 (“Others are clear that a commitment to originalism is distinct from a commitment to judicial deference and that originalism may often require the active exercise of the power of judicial review in order to keep faith with the principled commitments of the founding. The new originalism does not require judges to get out of the way of legislatures. It requires judges to uphold the original Constitution—nothing more, but also nothing less.”).Google Scholar
55 Primus, , supra note 27, at 188.Google Scholar
56 I will set aside the possibility that originalism is conceptually incoherent. For a general overview of the debate, see Daniel A. Farber, The Originalism Debate: A Guide for the Perplexed, 49 Ohio St. L. J. 1085 (1989).Google Scholar
57 Primus, , supra note 27, at 192–202.Google Scholar
58 Id. at 195–99.Google Scholar
59 Dworkin, Ronald, Taking Rights Seriously 135 (1977).Google Scholar
60 Vermeule, , supra note 38, at 70.Google Scholar
61 Id. at 92.Google Scholar
62 Id. at 82.Google Scholar
63 Myers v. United States, 272 U.S. 52 (1926).Google Scholar
64 Scalia, , supra note 5, at 852.Google Scholar
65 Vermeule, , supra note 30, at 16, 27–29, 242–43.Google Scholar
66 Dworkin, , Freedom's Law, supra note 2, at 7.Google Scholar
67 Vermeule, , supra note 30, at 1.Google Scholar
68 Id. at 150.Google Scholar
69 Vermeule, , supra note 38, at 90.Google Scholar
70 Vermeule, , supra note 30, at 265.Google Scholar
71 For such a position, see Bellamy, supra note 51, at 98.Google Scholar
72 Although Vermeule tackles the allocation of burden of proof, his account remains within the consequentialist paradigm, and does not give weight to process-related reasons. See Vermeule, supra note 30, at 153–54, 169–71.Google Scholar
73 Rawls, , supra note 15, at 139–40.Google Scholar
74 Gaus, Gerald F., Contemporary Theories of Liberalism: Public Reason as a Post-Enlightenment Project 214 (2003).Google Scholar
75 Rawls, , supra note 15, at 12.Google Scholar
76 For the idea that the task of government is to keep track of our publicly justified principles, see Gerald F. Gaus, Justificatory Liberalism: An Essay on Epistemology and Political Theory 184–91 (1996).Google Scholar
77 Rawls, , supra note 15, at 54–58.Google Scholar
78 Gaus, See,supra note 76, at 230.Google Scholar
- 2
- Cited by