Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-788cddb947-w95db Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-12T13:50:11.557Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Civility and Formality

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2014

Austin Sarat
Affiliation:
Amherst College, Massachusetts
Get access

Summary

Incivility is like injustice in Amartya Sen’s account: it is easier to identify clear cases of injustice than to say what justice consists in, and likewise it is easier to identify conduct as uncivil, that is, as an instance of incivility, than to say what civility actually is. Moreover, just as Sen maintained that “we can have a strong sense of injustice on many different grounds, and yet not agree on one particular ground as being the dominant reason for the diagnosis of injustice,” so equally we can identify incivility (in the words of one law review article) as “hostility, combativeness, rude behavior, insults, threats, or demeaning conduct or words,” without being able to say which of these – the rudeness, the hostility, the insults – is key to the diagnosis.

Maybe that doesn’t matter much for the codes that many jurisdictions and bar associations are having to set up to combat incivility among American attorneys. There seems no reason why such codes can’t just consist of a list of prohibitions, such as:

Never, without good cause, attribute to other counsel bad motives or improprieties.... Never engage in conduct that brings disorder or disruption to the courtroom.

Or, if they want to forsake the via negativa, they can add affirmative admonitions, such as “always uphold the dignity of the court” and “be punctual and prepared for all court appearances,” without having to prioritize the items on the list or privilege any one element as the essence of civility. And there may be philosophical reasons behind this approach. Both civility and its opposite may be family resemblance terms, which cannot be defined in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions. Some scholars have suggested that we can’t say much more about incivility than (like Justice Potter Stewart on “hard-core pornography”) we know it when we see it, though they reassure us that “there is sufficient consensus on the meaning of political incivility ... that promoting political-civility norms is reasonable and practical.”

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Sen, Amartya, The Idea of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2011), 2.
Grenardo, David A., “Making Civility Mandatory: Moving from Aspired to Required,” Cardozo Public Law, Policy and Ethics Journal 11 (2013): 239–311,Google Scholar
Sarat, Austin, “Enactments of Professionalism: A Study of Judges’ and Lawyers’ Accounts of Ethics and Civility in Litigation,” Fordham Law Review 67 (1998): 809–35.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Philosophical Investigations, 4th ed., ed. Hacker, P. M. S. and Schulte, Joachim (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009), 64
Massaro, Toni M. and Stryker, Robin, “Freedom of Speech, Liberal Democracy, and Emerging Evidence on Civility and Effective Democratic Engagement,” Arizona Law Review 54 (2012): 375–441,Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy, The Harm of Hate Speech (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2012), 236–7.
Post, Robert C., “Racist Speech, Democracy, and the First Amendment,” William and Mary Law Review 32 (1991): 267–327Google Scholar
Whitman, James, “Enforcing Civility and Respect: Three Societies,” Yale Law Journal 109 (2000): 1279–1398,Google Scholar
Day, Terri and Bradford, Erin, “Civility in Government Meetings: Balancing First Amendment, Reputational Interests, and Efficiency,” First Amendment Law Review 10 (2011): 57–98,Google Scholar
Oliver, Joan Duncan, The Meaning of Nice: How Compassion and Civility Can Change Your Life and the World (New York: Berkley Books, 2012)
Bills, Bronson D., “To Be or Not to Be: Civility and the Young Lawyer,” Connecticut Public Interest Law Journal 5 (2005): 31–40Google Scholar
Kekes, John, “Civility and Society,” History of Philosophy Quarterly 1 (1984): 429–43Google Scholar
Smith, Adam, The Wealth of Nations, ed. Cannan, Edwin (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976), 17
Waldron, Jeremy, “When Justice Replaces Affection: The Need for Rights,” Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 11 (1988): 625–47;Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy, Liberal Rights: Collected Papers 1981–1991 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993)
Krygier, Martin, “Wherefore Art Thou, Civility?Australian Quarterly 70 (1998): 38–42.Google Scholar
Greer, Germaine, “Romeo and Juliet,” in Shakespeare in Perspective: Volume 1, ed. Sales, Roger (London: BBC Books, 1892), 18–26, 22–3.
Weinrib, Ernest, The Idea of Private Law, Revised edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012) and his article “Formalism,” in A Companion to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory, ed. Dennis Patterson, (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 327–37
Ignatieff, Michael, The Needs of Strangers (London: Chatto and Windus, 1984), 9–10.
Williams, Patricia, The Alchemy of Race and Rights: Diary of a Law Professor (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992), 146.
Aristotle, , The Politics, ed. Sinclair, T. A. (London: Penguin Books, 1992), 59–60
Waldron, Jeremy, “The Wisdom of the Multitude: Some Reflections on Book 3, Chapter 11 of Aristotle’s Politics,” Political Theory 23 (1995): 563–84,Google Scholar
Arendt, , in The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958), 52,
Waldron, Jeremy, “Arendt’s Constitutional Politics,” in The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt, ed. Villa, Dana (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 201–19, 205.
Aristotle, , The Art of Rhetoric, ed. Lawson-Tancred, Hugh (London: Penguin Books, 1991), 145
Zagacki, Kenneth S. and Boleyn-Fitzgerald, Patrick A., “Rhetoric and Anger,” Philosophy and Rhetoric 39 (2006): 290–309.Google Scholar
Orbach, Barak, “On Hubris, Civility, and Incivility,” Arizona Law Review 54 (2012): 443–56,Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy, Law and Disagreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 111–13.
Kronman, Anthony T., “Civility,” Cumberland Law Review 26 (1995): 727–49,Google Scholar
Rawls, John, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), 58.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×