Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-lj6df Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T16:37:58.910Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Definition

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

One basic enterprise in philosophy going back to the ancient Greeks is to answer the question, What is it? It is reasonable to construe the answers to such questions as definitions, or what are nowadays called “real definitions,” since they typically go beyond the mere meanings of words and aim to specify the essences of things. Who, having read Plato's dialogues, can forget Socrates’ quest for definitions of things like “knowledge,” “justice,” or “virtue”? Aristotle and his Scholastic heirs continued and further developed this tradition. Aristotle distinguished different types of definitions, but definitions in the primary sense represent the essences of species. One defines an essence in terms of a genus and a differentia, as in the case of the species man, defined as rational animal. Since, on Aristotle's view, essences constitute the first principles of the sciences, definitions play a key role in his epistemology and in syllogistic reasoning, which is intended in part to systematize our knowledge of the natural world (see syllogism).

Descartes is very suspicious of this entire tradition, expressing three related criticisms of philosophical definitions: they obscure concepts that are already clear and distinct, tend to be vacuous, and fail to advance our knowledge. Concerning the first, he writes in the Principles I.10: “I have often noticed that philosophers make the mistake of employing logical definitions in an attempt to explain what was already very simple and self-evident; the result is that they only make matters more obscure” (AT VIIIA 8, CSM I 296; cf. AT III 597, CSMK 139). It helps to remember that for Descartes our simple ideas are innate. These include the ideas of thought, existence, and certainty, which one must grasp first in order to appreciate the force of the cogito. Elsewhere he notes that in order to understand these and other such concepts, we do not “have to rack our brains trying to find the ‘proximate genus’ and ‘essential differentia’ which go to make their true definition. We can leave that to someone who wants … to debate in the Schools.” All one must do is look within one's own mind. It is a mistake to “try to define what should only be conceived” (AT X 523–24, CSM II 417).

Descartes states his second criticism by mocking what he takes to be Aristotle's definition of motion: “A man who walks across a room shows much better what motion is than a man who says ‘It is the actuality of a potential being in so far as it is potential’” (AT III 597, CSMK 139). Definitions tend to be devoid of content, a jumble of words used without meaning.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Curley, Edwin. 1986. “Analysis in the Meditations: The Quest for Clear and Distinct Ideas,” in Essays on Descartes’ Meditations, ed. Rorty, A.. Los Angeles: University of California Press, 153–76.Google Scholar
Deslauriers, Marguerite. 2007. Aristotle on Definition. Boston: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Definition
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.076
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Definition
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.076
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Definition
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.076
Available formats
×