Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-45l2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T13:38:25.484Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Vortex

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

John A. Schuster
Affiliation:
University of Sydney
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

The theory of vortical celestial mechanics, as presented in the Principles of Philosophy and The World, is the “engine room” of Descartes’ system of natural philosophy. Descartes starts his vortex theory with an “indefinitely” large chunk of divinely created matter or extension in which there are no void spaces whatsoever. When God injects motion into this extension, it is shattered into microparticles, and myriads of “circular” displacements ensue, forming gigantic whirlpools or vortices. This process eventually produces three species of corpuscle, or elements, along with the birth of stars and planets. The third element forms all solid and liquid bodies on all planets throughout the cosmos, including the earth. Interspersed in the pores of such planetary bodies are the spherical particles of the second element. The second element also makes up the bulk of every vortex, while the spaces between these spherical particles are filled by the first element, which also constitutes the stars, including our sun.

The key to Descartes’ celestial mechanics is his concept of the “massiveness” or “solidity” of a planet, meaning its aggregate volume to surface ratio, which is indicative of its ability to retain acquired motion or to resist the impact of other bodies. The particles of the second element making up a vortex also vary in volume to surface ratio with distance from the central star, as gathered from Descartes’ stipulations concerning the variation of the size (and speed) of the second-element particles with distance from the central star (Figure 32). Note also the important inflection point in the size and speed curves at radius K (Schuster 2005, 49). A planet is locked into an orbit at a radial distance at which its centrifugal tendency, related to its aggregate solidity, is balanced by the counter force arising from the centrifugal tendency of the second-element particles composing the vortex in the vicinity of the planet – that tendency similarly depending on the volume to surface ratio of the those particular particles.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aiton, Eric J. 1972. The Vortex Theory of Planetary Motion. London: Macdonald.Google Scholar
Gaukroger, Stephen. 2002. Descartes’ System of Natural Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaukroger, Stephen. 2000. “The Foundational Role of Hydrostatics and Statics in Descartes’ Natural Philosophy,” in Descartes’ Natural Philosophy, ed. Gaukroger, S., Schuster, J., and Sutton, J.. London: Routledge, 60–80.Google Scholar
Gaukroger, Stephen, and Schuster, John A.. 2002. “The Hydrostatic Paradox and the Origins of Cartesian Dynamics,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 33: 535–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schuster, John A. 2005. “Waterworld: Descartes’ Vortical Celestial Mechanics – A Gambit in the Natural Philosophical Contest of the Early Seventeenth Century,” in The Science of Nature in the Seventeenth Century: Patterns of Change in Early Modern Natural Philosophy, ed. Anstey, P. and Schuster, J. A.. Dordrecht: Kluwer/Springer, 35–79.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Vortex
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.258
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Vortex
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.258
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Vortex
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.258
Available formats
×