Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c47g7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T22:34:21.186Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Cosmology

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Carla Rita Palmerino
Affiliation:
Radboud Universiteit Nijmegen
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

Descartes was putting the finishing touches on The World when, in the fall of 1633, he heard about the condemnation of Galileo. As a consequence, he decided not to publish his treatise, as the hypothesis of the earth's motion could not be removed from it “without rendering the whole work defective” (AT I 271, CSMK 41) (see earth, motion of the). Although The World appeared only posthumously, Descartes did reveal his cosmological views in his Principles of Philosophy (1644). In the third part of that work, which deals with the “visible universe,” he argued that Copernicus's theory not only explains phenomena much better than Ptolemy's but is also “a little simpler and clearer” than Tycho's (AT VIIIA 85, CSM I 250). Descartes adopted two strategies to protect himself against the risk of legal attack by either the Catholic or the Protestant church. The first consists in maintaining that strictly speaking the earth does not move (AT VIIIA 90, CSM I 252). Planets are in fact carried around by a vortex of subtle matter circling the sun, which means that they remain at rest in the surrounding medium (Garber 1992, 181–88). Second, Descartes resorted to “the standard subterfuge for astronomers and natural philosophers seeking to avoid trouble,” namely that of presenting his cosmological theory as a mere hypothesis (Finocchiaro 2005, 50–51). In spite of these prudential measures, Descartes was, however, regarded by contemporary readers as a “realist Copernican.” As shown by Schuster, the Principles offer a descriptive-explanatory narrative unifying his theories of vortices, magnetism, sunspots, stellar novae, and newly discovered variable stars, along with a theory of planet formation from dead, sunspot-encrusted stars. This tour de force amounts to the most daring and radical statement of a multistellar Copernican system to that date (Schuster 2013, 543–86).

Both in The World and in the Principles, Descartes puts forward a fictional account of the genesis of the universe, which he integrates with graphical representations of the solar system and with analogical explanations of the behavior of planets, stars, and comets. Chapter 6 of The World narrates how God initially divided matter into parts of different size and shape and caused them to move “in accordance with the ordinary laws of nature.”

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aiton, E. J. 1972. The Vortex Theory of Planetary Motions. London: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Gaukroger, Stephen. 2002. Descartes’ System of Natural Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garber, Daniel. 1992. Descartes’ Metaphysical Physics.Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, Maurice. 2005. Retrying Galileo, 1633–1992.Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Palmerino, Carla Rita. 2007. “Bodies in Water like Planets in the Skies: Uses and Abuses of Analogical Reasoning in the Study of Planetary Motion,” in Mechanics and Cosmology in the Medieval and Early Modern Period, ed. Camerota, M., Bucciantini, M., and Roux, S.. Florence: Olschki, 145–68.Google Scholar
Schuster, John. 2013. Descartes-Agonistes: Physico-mathematics, Method & Corpuscular-Mechanism, 1618–33.Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Cosmology
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.071
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Cosmology
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.071
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Cosmology
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.071
Available formats
×