Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-5g6vh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T17:23:58.269Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Thought

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Lilli Alanen
Affiliation:
Uppsala universitet
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

While examining his nature in the Second Meditation, Descartes famously finds that he is “in the strict sense only a thing that thinks” (res cogitans), that thought is inseparable from him, and that the nature of his self or mind (or soul) consists in thinking alone (AT VII 27, CSM II 189). In the new, broad sense of the term here introduced, thinking covers not only functions traditionally attributed to mind, intellect, or reason, such as judging, understanding, conceiving, and reasoning, but any kind of cognitive and conative act, like doubting, affirming, denying, willing, and not willing, as well as imagining and having sensory perceptions (AT VII 28, CSM II 19). In addition to those of the rational soul, all of the functions of what in the Aristotelian tradition were attributed to the animal and sensitive soul are attributed to the mind in a new, broad sense and treated as different kinds or modes of thought. The traditional architecture of mind and cognition has been, it seems, reversed. Instead of serving as the foundation required for the intellect to do its work of abstraction and understanding, sensory perception, although also requiring bodily organs, now depends on the mind and its capacity to think and understand.

One can roughly distinguish two main strands for later theorizing about mind and thought that can be traced to the Meditations and are likely to color one's understanding of the notion of thought defining the being discovered in the Second Meditation. One grows out of the empiricist tradition and emphasizes consciousness as distinctive for or even identical with thought or mind. The focus here, using a recent slogan, is on what the mind is, and on what a particular thought is ( or feels) like, as opposed to what the mind does or how it acts and operates (Chalmers 1996, Brandom 2002). The second strand with roots in the Aristotelian-Scholastic tradition focuses on what mind does and sees the exercise of its various intellectual capacities and the standards governing them as essential to thought. It lives on from Descartes to Kant and beyond to those who take their inspiration from Kant rather than from the British empiricists in their accounts of cognition and the relation between thought and the world.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alanen, Lilli. 2003. Descartes's Concept of Mind.Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Baker, Gordon, and Morris, Katherine. 1996. Descartes's Dualism. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Brandom, Robert. 2002. Tales of the Mighty Dead: Historical Essays in the Metaphysics of Intentionality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Broughton, Janet. 2008. “Self-Knowledge,” in A Companion to Descartes, ed. Broughton, J. and Carriero, J.. Oxford: Blackwell, 179–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carriero, John. 2009. Between Two Worlds: A Reading of Descartes's Meditations. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, David. 1996. The Conscious Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hatfield, Gary. 2003. Descartes and the Meditations.London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kenny, Anthony. 1968. Descartes: A Study of His Philosophy.New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Kenny, Anthony. 1966. “Cartesian Privacy,” in Wittgenstein: The Philosophical Investigations, ed. Pitcher, G.. London: Macmillan, 352–70.Google Scholar
Lähteenmäki, Vili. 2007. “Orders of Consciousness and Forms of Reflexivity in Descartes,” in Consciousness: From Perception to Reflection in the History of Philosophy, ed. Heinämäki, S., Lähteenmäki, V. and Remes, P.. Dordrecht: Springer,177–201.Google Scholar
Rodis-Lewis, Geneviève. 1950. Le problème de l'inconscient et le cartésianisme. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.Google Scholar
Rozemond, Marleen. 2006. “The Nature of the Mind,” in The Blackwell Guide to Descartes’ Meditations, ed. Gaukroger, S.. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 48–66.Google Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert. 1949. The Concept of Mind.London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Wilson, Margaret. 1978. Descartes. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Thought
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.243
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Thought
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.243
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Thought
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.243
Available formats
×