Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-vfjqv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T15:42:42.976Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Imagination

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Dennis L. Sepper
Affiliation:
University of Dallas
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

From the beginning of Descartes’ intellectual career, imagination played a major role in his writings, even when he took pains to point out its limitations and pathologies. This role is more central and apparent to those who have available the entire oeuvre than to his contemporaries. But even contemporary scholarly evaluations are often unduly influenced by the assumption that, in showing imagination's weakness, the Meditations establishes its cognitive insignificance. This assumption can lead to overlooking the fundamental importance of imagination in Descartes’ philosophy.

Although the history of imagination is complex, one can nevertheless identify several intellectual streams influencing the early seventeenth century. Medical, Aristotelian, Platonic, and Stoic traditions agreed in conceiving imagination as a medial psychophysiological power: located midway between the deliverances of the external senses and intellectual conception, in terms of both psychology and physiology (see anatomy and physiology). Humanists regarded it as crucial for adapting knowledge to circumstances; in rhetorical theory, it was decisive for discovering topics and putting them in order. In the mathematical sciences (especially geometry), it played an important role in the transition between thinking natural things in place and thinking mathematical objects in abstract space. Already in late antiquity the greatest Platonist philosopher of mathematics, Proclus, had argued that mathematics required intellectual imagination (Nikulin 2002 and Rabouin 2009).

Descartes was introduced to the Aristotelian conception of imagination by his Jesuit teachers at the Collège Henri IV de La Flèche. Aristotle had argued that in animals the external senses were united in common sensation, and that the sensible forms appearing there (called phantasms or images) could be psychophysiologically preserved and reactivated. Moreover, in human beings, there was no thinking without such phantasms. Muslim philosopher-physicians like ibn Rushd (Averroës) and ibn Sina (Avicenna) and their European Scholastic followers developed from these indications rigorous accounts of the complex activity (physiological as well as psychological) of images in an expanded realm of internal sensation. This activity began in higher animals with common sensation's presentation of a world of sensory appearances; proceeded to the memorative and imaginative powers that retain, reproduce, and recombine the phantasms; and advanced to the instinctive assessment of these representations as noxious or advantageous to the animal, assessments that led to purposive behavior.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bitbol-Hespériès, Annie. 2000. “Descartes face à la mélancolie de la princesse Elisabeth,” in Une philosophie dans l'histoire, hommages à Raymond Klibansky, ed. Melkevik, B. and Narbonne, J.-M.. Québec: Presses de l'Université de Laval, 229–50.Google Scholar
Harvey, E. R. 1975. The Inward Wits: Psychological Theory in the Middle Ages and the Renaissance. London: Warburg Institute.Google Scholar
Nikulin, Dmitri. 2002. Matter, Imagination and Geometry: Ontology, Natural Philosophy and Mathematics in Plotinus, Proclus and Descartes. Burlington, VT: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Nolan, Lawrence. 2005. “The Role of the Imagination in Rationalist Philosophies of Mathematics,” in A Companion to Rationalism, ed. Nelson, A.. Oxford: Blackwell, 224–49.Google Scholar
Rabouin, David. 2009. Mathesis Universalis: L'idée de ‘mathématique universelle’ d'Aristote à Descartes. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sepper, Dennis L. 1996. Descartes's Imagination. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Imagination
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.140
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Imagination
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.140
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Imagination
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.140
Available formats
×