Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-x4r87 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T16:48:57.028Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Explanation

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Alan Gabbey
Affiliation:
Barnard College, Columbia University
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

Descartes’ views on explanation are best approached against the background of traditional and contemporary views on the topic. There are no entries on explanatio or explicatio in the philosophical dictionaries of the early modern period. Normally Scholastic writers talked not about explanations of natural phenomena but about their demonstrations, by way of syllogisms yielding apodictic knowledge of causal dependence (Jardine 1976; Dear 1995, 26–30). By contrast, the etymology of explanation and explication (in English, Latin, and French) reveals related senses of clarifying, removing ambiguities, and making intelligible that do not implicate the notion of demonstration. This range of senses is in Cicero, who refers to physics as explicatio naturae, a label borrowed for the same purpose by some writers in the early modern period. Explicationes appear in Scholastic manuals as commentaries or philosophical explications de texte, not typically as causal accounts of natural phenomena. A Scholastic demonstration is an explicatio to the extent that it interprets and clarifies phenomena in a certain way; an explanation in the new physics is a demonstration to the extent that it yields causal knowledge, whether or not it be scientia strictly understood. Yet demonstration and explanation remain different notions, and the differences between them spotlight important contrasts between Peripatetic physics and the new mechanical philosophies. Proponents of these new philosophies sought mechanical explanations of all kinds of properties, including those manifesting the supposed forms and qualities that for the Scholastics were matters of definition and of specification of essences (see form, substantial and quality, real).

Many proponents of the new natural philosophy, including Descartes, retained the ideal of constructing explanations that would count as scientia, especially when the problem could be mathematized and the solution derived from assured principles. But they also appreciated the difficulties in constructing unqualified scientiae of nature, notably of the biological world (Fouke 1989). Claims to apodictic security became less characteristic of the new mechanical philosophies, where the terms explanation and explication multiplied in tandem with increasing concerns about whether causal intelligibility could ever be strictly demonstrative. Explanations became common coin in the sciences, with demonstrations remaining common coin in mathematics, pure and mixed, though in the latter, unqualified demonstrability depended on the likelihood of causal demonstrations within the physical world. In the empirical sciences, other explanatory values began to displace strict demonstrability, such as intelligibility, simplicity and minimalization of theoretical principles, unification of laws, and high informational content.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Buchwald, Jed Z. 2008. “Descartes's Experimental Journey past the Prism and through the Invisible World to the Rainbow,” Annals of Science 65: 1–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, Desmond M. 1992. “Descartes’ Philosophy of Science and the Scientific Revolution,” in The Cambridge Companion to Descartes, ed. Cottingham, J.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 258–85.Google Scholar
Clarke, Desmond M. 1982. Descartes’ Philosophy of Science. Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Dear, Peter. 1995. Discipline & Experience: The Mathematical Way in the Scientific Revolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fouke, Daniel. 1989. “Mechanical and ‘Organical’ Models in Seventeenth-Century Explanations of Biological Reproduction,” Science in Context 3: 365–81.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gabbey, Alan. 2001. “Mechanical Philosophies and Their Explanations,” in Late Medieval and Early Modern Corpuscular Matter Theories, ed. Lüthy, C., Murdoch, J. E., and Newman, W.. Leiden: Brill, 1:441–65.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl. 1965. Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York: Free Press (Collier Macmillan).Google Scholar
Jardine, Nicholas. 1976. “Galileo's Road to Truth and the Demonstrative Regress,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 7: 277–318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nadler, Steven. 1998. “Doctrines of Explanation in Late Scholasticism and in the Mechanical Philosophy,” in The Cambridge History of Seventeenth-Century Philosophy, 2 vols., ed. Garber, D. and Ayers, M.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1:513–52.Google Scholar
Schuster, John. 2000. “Descartes Opticien: The Construction of the Law of Refraction and the Manufacture of Its Physical Rationales, 1618–29,” in Descartes’ Natural Philosophy, ed. Gaukroger, S.,Schuster, J., and Sutton, J.. London: Routledge,258–312.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Explanation
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.100
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Explanation
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.100
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Explanation
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.100
Available formats
×