Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-22dnz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T23:35:09.724Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Physico-Mathematics

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

John A. Schuster
Affiliation:
University of Sydney
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

In November 1618, Descartes, then twenty-two, met and worked for two months with Isaac Beeckman, a Dutch scholar seven years his senior. Beeckman was one of the first supporters of a corpuscular-mechanical approach to natural philosophy. However, it was not simply corpuscular mechanism that Beeckman advocated to Descartes. He also interested Descartes in what they called “physico-mathematics.” In late 1618, Beeckman (1939–53, I:244) wrote, “There are very few physico-mathematicians,” adding, “(Descartes) says he has never met anyone other than me who pursues enquiry the way I do, combining Physics and Mathematics in an exact way; and I have never spoken with anyone other than him who does the same.” They were partly right. While there were not many physico-mathematicians, there were of course others, such as Kepler, Galileo, and certain leading Jesuit mathematicians, who were trying to merge mathematics and natural philosophy (Dear 1995, 168–79).

Physico-mathematics, in Descartes’ view, deals with the way the traditional mixed mathematical disciplines, such as hydrostatics, statics, geometrical optics, geometrical astronomy, and harmonics, were conceived to relate to the discipline of natural philosophy. In Aristotelianism, the mixed mathematical sciences were interpreted as intermediate between natural philosophy and mathematics and subordinate to them. Natural philosophical explanations were couched in terms of matterand cause, something mathematics could not offer, according to most Aristotelians. In the mixed mathematical sciences, mathematics was used not in an explanatory way, but instrumentally for problem solving and practical aims. For example, in geometrical optics, one represented light as light rays. This might be useful but does not facilitate answering the underlying natural philosophical questions: “the physical nature of light” and “the causes of optical phenomena.” In contrast, physico-mathematics involved a commitment to revising radically the Aristotelian view of the mixed mathematical sciences, which were to become more intimately related to natural philosophical issues of matter and cause. Paradoxically, the issue was not mathematization. The mixed mathematical sciences, which were already mathematical, were to become more “physicalized,” more closely integrated into whichever brand of natural philosophy an aspiring physico-mathematician endorsed.

Three of Descartes’ exercises in physico-mathematics survive. The most important is his attempt, at Beeckman's urging, to supply a corpuscular-mechanical explanation for the hydrostatic paradox, which had been rigorously derived in mixed mathematical fashion by Simon Stevin (AT X 67–74, 228; Gaukroger and Schuster 2002).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Beeckman, Isaac. 1939–53. Journal tenu par Isaac Beeckman de 1604 à 1634, 4 vols., ed. de Waard, C.. The Hague: Nijhof.Google Scholar
Dear, Peter. 1995. Discipline and Experience. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaukroger, Stephen, and Schuster, J. A.. 2002. “The Hydrostatic Paradox and the Origins of Cartesian Dynamics,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 33: 535–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jullien, Vincent, and Charrak, A.. 2002. Ce que dit Descartes touchant la chute des graves: De 1618 à 1646, étude d'un indicateur de la philosophie naturelle cartésienne. Villeneuve d'Ascq (Nord): Presses Universitaires du Septentrion.Google Scholar
Schuster, John A. 2000. “Descartes opticien: The Construction of the Law of Refraction and the Manufacture of Its Physical Rationales,” in Descartes’ Natural Philosophy, ed. Gaukroger, S., Schuster, J., and Sutton, J.London: Routledge, 258–312.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Physico-Mathematics
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.199
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Physico-Mathematics
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.199
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Physico-Mathematics
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.199
Available formats
×