Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-x4r87 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T03:59:29.328Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Mode

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Geoffrey Gorham
Affiliation:
Macalester College
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

Descartes inherited from the Aristotelian tradition a model of reality comprising substances and affections or modes that inhere in substances. But he reduced the kinds of substance to just two and made the inherence relation strong enough to block what he considered the ontological excesses of Scholasticism. In a general sense, modes are the various ways of qualifying or conceiving of substances. We can speak or conceive of the duration, number, or shape of a given object; so all of these are its modes. In a more precise sense, only those features of an object that admit of variation are modes. In this sense, shape is a mode while duration and number are classified as “attributes” since a thing can change its shape but cannot cease to endure (or become more or fewer) without ceasing to exist (AT VIIIA 30, CSM I 214). And since God is absolutely immutable, he has no modes, only attributes (AT VIIIA 26, CSM I 211). Order, duration, and number may be termed “generic attributes” since they “extend to all classes of things” (AT VIIIA 23, CSM I 208). But there are also two “principal attributes,”thought and extension, which bifurcate the world of substance into two natural kinds: minds and bodies. The principal attributes have their characteristic modes: minds change as thought takes on various perceptions and volitions; bodies change as extension takes on various shapes and motions. And these modes account for everything we perceive in things: “Each substance has one principal property which constitutes its nature and essence, and to which all its other properties are referred” (AT VIIIA 25, CSM I 210).

Descartes would dismiss the question whether modes properly pertain to a substance or to its principal attribute since there is merely a conceptual, rather than a real or modal, distinction between a substance and its attributes (see distinction [real, modal, and rational]). That is, “we are unable to form a clear and distinct idea of the substance if we exclude from it the attribute in question” (AT VIIIA 30, CSM I 214). In reality, the principal attributes thought and extension just are minds and bodies: “They must be considered as thinking substance itself and extended substance itself, that is as mind and body” (AT VIIIA 30–31, CSM I 215). There is also merely a conceptual distinction among the various attributes of a single substance.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Leibniz, Gottfried. 1989. Philosophical Essays, ed. Ariew, R. and Garber, D.. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Newton, Isaac. 2004. Philosophical Writings, ed. Janiak, A.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Garber, Daniel. 1992. Descartes’ Metaphysical Physics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Nolan, Lawrence. 1997. “Reductionism and Nominalism in Descartes's Theory of Attributes,” Topoi 16: 129–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Secada, Jorge. 2000. Cartesian Metaphysics: The Scholastic Origins of Modern Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Mode
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.178
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Mode
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.178
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Mode
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.178
Available formats
×