Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-zzh7m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T14:41:14.577Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Locke, John (1632–1704)

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Walter Ott
Affiliation:
University of Virginia
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

Locke was born in 1632 in Somerset, England, to a Protestant landowner. At the age of fifteen, he enrolled in the Westminster School before going on to Christ Church, Oxford. In 1666 he met Anthony Ashley Cooper (the future Earl of Shaftesbury), who was to become his patron and whom Locke was to serve as secretary for much of his life. Locke shared the political vicissitudes of Shaftesbury's career and fled to the Netherlands in 1683, fearful of being charged with treason. After the Glorious Revolution, Locke returned to England; from 1692 until his death, he resided with Sir Francis and Lady Masham, the daughter of Ralph Cudworth.

Locke's main metaphysical and epistemological work is the mammoth An Essay concerning Human Understanding, which he published in 1689 and revised five times before his death. Although Locke rarely mentions Descartes by name in the Essay, much of that work can profitably be read as a running battle with him. Many of Descartes’ key positions – on innate ideas, the essence and immateriality of the soul, the nature of body as extension – come under attack.

Locke rejects Descartes’ doctrine of innate ideas. If the doctrine means that we have ideas before we are aware of them, it is self-contradictory, for no idea can be in the mind without our being aware of it. If, as Descartes sometimes suggests, it means only that we have a capacity or disposition to form certain ideas, then it is trivially true of all ideas (I.ii.5). Nor does Locke have any use for the Cartesian intellect. In the Sixth Meditation, Descartes uses the example of a chiliagon to show that we have a capacity for forming ideas that outstrips our ability to generate images. The idea of the chiliagon must then come from the intellect. Against this, Locke argues that, while we have no idea of the figure of the chiliagon, we can reason about its properties by attending to the idea of the number of its sides (II.xxix.13).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Locke, John. 2002. Selected Correspondence, ed. Goldie, M.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Locke, John. 1975. An Essay concerning Human Understanding, ed. Nidditch, P.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Locke, John. 1812. The Works of John Locke, 11th ed., 10 vols. London: Otridgeet al.Google Scholar
Ayers, Michael. 1991. Locke: Epistemology and Ontology. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. Jonathan. 2005. Locke. London: Routledge.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Locke, John (1632–1704)
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.160
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Locke, John (1632–1704)
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.160
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Locke, John (1632–1704)
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.160
Available formats
×