Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-qxdb6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T18:36:13.673Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Person

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Alan Gabbey
Affiliation:
Barnard College, Columbia University
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

The term persona appears only once in the original Latin text of the Meditations, in the Fourth Meditation (AT VII 61, CSM II 43). There Descartes employs the term to mean “one's role in life,” deriving from persona in the original theatrical sense of “a mask,” as in the early Private Thoughts (AT X 213, CSMK I 2). Nowhere in the Meditations and Objections and Replies, or elsewhere in the published writings, does Descartes explain his conception of personhood or address the problem of “personal identity” that has exercised philosophers since Locke. It is all the more important therefore to determine what he took a “person” to be.

One suggestion that many commentators find appealing is that a Cartesian person is a mind or soul and thus that personal identity consists in sameness of soul (see, e.g., Thiel 2011, 270). In the Second Replies, on the question of whether God could be a deceiver, Descartes notes that in the Meditations he “had a special obligation” to talk about God in a philosophical way, “since there my supposition was that no other human beings were yet known to me, and moreover I was considering myself not as consisting of mind and body but solely as a mind” (AT VII 142–43, CSM II 102). The Meditations are primarily those of a res cogitans, not of a Cartesian human being, whose nature emerges in a letter to Mesland (February 9, 1645). When we talk about a human body, we do not mean just a determinate part of matter with a determinate size, but that part as united to the soul (l’âme). We believe that we have had the same body since infancy, despite its lifelong changes in quantity, shape, and composition. Our body is the same numerically (idem numero) because it is informed [informé] by the same soul (AT IV 166–67, CSMK 243). So is a Cartesian person a human being instead?

A human being, qua substantial union of a body and a mind, is still not a rounded person, because persons have moral and social commitments. Even in the Passions of the Soul (1649), Descartes explains that his purpose is “not to explain the passions as an orator, nor even as a moral philosopher, but solely as a physicist [physicien]” (AT XI 326, CSM I 7).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Holbrook, Daniel. 1992. “Descartes on Persons,” Personalist Forum 8 (suppl.): 9–14.Google Scholar
McCann, Edwin. 1986. “Cartesian Selves and Lockean Substances,” The Monist 69: 458–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miles, Murray. 1983. “Psycho-Physical Union: The Problem of the Person in Descartes,” Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review 22: 23–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thiel, Udo. 2011. The Early Modern Subject: Self-Consciousness and Personal Identity from Descartes to Hume. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Person
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.196
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Person
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.196
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Person
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.196
Available formats
×