Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-x4r87 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T07:15:36.785Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Rarefaction and Condensation

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Carla Rita Palmerino
Affiliation:
Radboud Universiteit Nijmegen
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

Whereas most seventeenth-century atomists accounted for rarefaction in terms of the intrusion of tiny void spaces within the particles of a body, Descartes devised an explanation that was in agreement with his plenist physics. Some letters to Mersenne, written between 1629 and 1630, bear witness to this attempt. In the first of them, dated October 8, 1629, Descartes praises the explanation of rarefaction provided by a certain doctor, most probably Sebastian Basso, although, he adds, “I do not explain the ether as he does” (AT I 25). While Basso believed that rarefaction was caused by a separate ethereal substance entering the pores of material bodies, Descartes argued in a subsequent letter that the corpuscles that cause rarefaction “are of the same substance of visible and tangible bodies.” These corpuscles must not be regarded as atoms but as “an extremely fluid and subtle substance” (AT I 140, CSM I 22). Contrary to Basso's ether, Descartes’ subtle matter is transmutable into the other elements, from which it differs only for the size and shape of its particles (Ariew 2011).

In another letter to Mersenne, dated February 25, 1630, Descartes explains rarefaction and condensation by using the example of a sponge that expands upon absorbing water and contracts upon being squeezed (AT I 119). This analogy reappears in Descartes’ works. In chapter 5 of The World, one reads that material bodies are, properly speaking, composed only of the third element, although they also contain particles of the other two elements. These bodies can be compared to a sponge, the pores of which “are always full of air or water or some similar fluid,” which, however, do not “enter into its composition” (AT X 31, G 21).

The analogy of a sponge is invoked in the Principles of Philosophy II.6 to explain that rarefaction involves a change of shape of a body's particles but not an increase in its extension:

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anstey, Peter. 2000. “Descartes’ Cardiology and Its Reception in English Physiology,” in Descartes’ Natural Philosophy, ed. Gaukroger, S., Schuster, J., and Sutton, J.. London: Routledge, 420–43.Google Scholar
Ariew, Roger. 2011. Descartes among the Scholastics. Leiden: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Basso, Sebastian. 1649. Philosophiae Naturalis adversus Aristotelem.Geneva: P. de la Rouvière.Google Scholar
Des Chene, Dennis. 1996. Physiologia: Natural Philosophy in Late Aristotelian and Cartesian Thought.Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Miles, Murray. 1983. “Condensation and Rarefaction in Descartes’ Analysis of Matter,” Nature and System 5, 169–80.Google Scholar
Suárez, Francisco. 1856–66. Opera omnia, 28 vols. Paris: Ludovicum Vivès.Google Scholar
Van Ruler, J. A. 1995. The Crisis of Causality: Voetius and Descartes on God, Nature and Change.Brill: Leiden.Google Scholar
Woolhouse, Roger. 1993. Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz: The Concept of Substance in Seventeenth Century Metaphysics.London: Routledge.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×