Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-18T21:56:12.041Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Encapsulation and subjectivity from the standpoint of viewpoint theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 March 2022

Ezequiel Morsella
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, San Francisco State University, San Francisco, CA94132-4168, USA. Morsella@sfsu.eduhttps://faculty.sfsu.edu/~morsella/ Department of Neurology, University of California, San Francisco, San Francisco, CA94158, USA
Anthony G. Velasquez
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, San Francisco State University, San Francisco, CA94132-4168, USA. agvelasquez9@gmail.com; jyankulo@mail.sfsu.edu; a_li@ucsb.edu
Jessica K. Yankulova
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, San Francisco State University, San Francisco, CA94132-4168, USA. agvelasquez9@gmail.com; jyankulo@mail.sfsu.edu; a_li@ucsb.edu
Yanming Li
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, San Francisco State University, San Francisco, CA94132-4168, USA. agvelasquez9@gmail.com; jyankulo@mail.sfsu.edu; a_li@ucsb.edu
Adam Gazzaley
Affiliation:
Department of Neurology, Department of Psychiatry, and Department of Physiology, University of California, San Francisco, San Francisco, CA94158, USA. adam.gazzaley@ucsf.eduhttps://neuroscape.ucsf.edu/profile/adam-gazzaley/

Abstract

The groundbreaking, viewpoint theory of Merker et al. explains several properties of the conscious field, including why the observer cannot directly apprehend itself. We propose that viewpoint theory might also provide a progressive, constitutive marker of consciousness and shed light on why most of the contents of consciousness are encapsulated.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Block, N. (1995). On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 18, 227287.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Firestone, C., & Scholl, B. J. (2016). Cognition does not affect perception: Evaluating the evidence for “top-down” effects (Target article). Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 39, 177.10.1017/S0140525X15000965CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGurk, H., & MacDonald, J. (1976). Hearing lips and seeing voices. Nature, 264, 746748.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Morsella, E. (2005). The function of phenomenal states: Supramodular interaction theory. Psychological Review, 112, 10001021.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Morsella, E., Godwin, C. A., Jantz, T. K., Krieger, S. C., & Gazzaley, A. (2016). Homing in on consciousness in the nervous system: An action-based synthesis. Behavioral and Brain Sciences (Target Article), 39, 117.10.1017/S0140525X15000643CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83, 435450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1984). Computation and cognition: Toward a foundation for cognitive science. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Schopenhauer, A. (1818/1819). The world as will and representation (vol. 1). Dover. (Original work published in 1818).Google Scholar