Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-ph5wq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-29T08:41:33.426Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A bottom-up approach to foundations of mathematics

from Part I - Invited Papers

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 March 2017

Pavel Pudlák
Affiliation:
Mathematical Institute Academy of Sciences
Petr Hájek
Affiliation:
Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic, Prague
Get access

Summary

Introduction

There are two basic properties of a logical system: consistency and completeness. These two properties are important for systems used for particular special purposes (say, in artificial intelligence), as well as for systems proposed as foundations of the all of mathematics. Therefore, any systematic study of the foundations of mathematics should address questions of consistency and completeness. Gödel's theorems provide negative information about both: any reasonable sufficiently strong theory is unable to demonstrate its own consistency and any such system is incomplete.

There has been impressive success in proving independence results for set theory. Cohen's forcing method and its boolean valued version was applied to solve the continuum problem and to prove a lot of other sentences to be independent of set theory. This may give the impression that logic is doing very well in studying the independence phenomenon which is only partly true. The known independent sentences in set theory express statements about infinite sets. The type of the infiniteness in these independence results is, in a sense, of higher order than in classical mathematics. For instance, the continuum hypothesis talks about the cardinality of the set of real numbers, which is in any case uncountable. While most of classical mathematics is about real numbers, almost everything there can be encoded using only a countable number of elements, hence can be expressed as a statement about natural numbers. As an example, consider a continuous real function. Clearly, such a function is described by its values on rationals, thus statements about continuous functions can be written as arithmetical formulas. For arithmetical formulas, current methods of logic almost completely fail. An exception are Paris-Harrington type independence results (28). Still it is true that no problem from classical mathematics (i.e. number theory, algebra, calculus) was proved independent from a logical theory before it had actually been solved. Furthermore, it seems that even the most difficult classical results in number theory and finite combinatorics can be proved in Peano arithmetic, a theory which is much weaker than Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory.

Therefore one of the principal goals of mathematical logic should be development of new techniques for proving independence.

Type
Chapter
Information
Gödel '96
Logical Foundations of Mathematics, Computer Science and Physics - Kurt Gödel's Legacy
, pp. 81 - 97
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2017

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ackermann, Wilhelm, [1940] Zur Widerspruchsfreiheit der Zahlentheorie. Mathematische Annalen 117 (1940), 162–194.Google Scholar
Benacerraf, Paul, and Putnam, Hilary (eds.), [1983] Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings. 2d ed. Cambridge University Press.
Bernays, Paul, [1935] Sur le platonisme dans les mathématiques. L'ensiegnement mathématique 34, 52–69. English translation in [Benacerraf and Putnam 1983].Google Scholar
Boolos, George, [1971] The iterative conception of set. The Journal of Philosophy 68, 215–231. Reprinted in [Benacerraf and Putnam 1983].Google Scholar
Butts, Robert E., and Hintikka, Jaakko (eds.), [1977] Logic, Foundations of Mathematics, and Computability Theory. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Cantor, Georg, [1932] Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen undphilosophischen Inhalts. Edited by Zermelo, Ernst. Berlin: Springer.
Clote, Peter, and Krajíček, Jan (eds.), [1993] Arithmetic, Proof Theory and Computational Complexity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Edelman, Gerald M., [1992] Bright Air, Brilliant Fire. New York: Basic Books.
Gödel, Kurt, [*1951] Some basic theorems of the foundations of mathematics and their applications. 25th Josiah Willard Gibbs Lecture, American Mathematical Society. In [Gödel 1995], pp. 304–323.
Gödel, Kurt, [*1953/9] Is mathematics syntax of language? Versions III and V in [Gödel 1995], pp. 334–362.
Gödel, Kurt, [1972a] Some remarks on the undecidability results. In [Gödel 1990], pp. 305–306.
Gödel, Kurt, [1990] Collected Works, volume II: Publications 1938–74. Edited by Feferman, Solomon, Dawson, John W. Jr., Moore, Gregory H., Solovay, Robert M., and van Heijenoort, Jean. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gödel, Kurt, [1995] Collected Works, volume III: Unpublished Essays and Lectures. Edited by Feferman, Solomon, Dawson, John W. Jr., Goldfarb, Warren, Parsons, Charles, and Solovay, Robert M.. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.
S. C., Kleene, [1952] Introduction to Metamathematics. New York: Van Nostrand. Also Amsterdam: North-Holland and Groningen: Noordhoff.
Kreisel, G., [1951] On the interpretation of non-finitist proofs, part I. The Journal of Symbolic Logic 16, 241–267.Google Scholar
Lucas, J. R., [1961] Minds, machines, and Gödel. Philosophy 36, 112–127.
Myrvold, Wayne C., [1995] Computability in quantum mechanics. In De-Pauli-Schimanovich, W. et al. (eds.), The Foundational Debate, pp. 33–46. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Parsons, Charles, [1977] What is the iterative conception of set? In [Butts and Hintikka 1977], pp. 335–367. Reprinted in [Parsons 1983] and [Benacerraf and Putnam 1983]. Cited according to the reprint in [Parsons 1983].
Parsons, Charles, [1983] Mathematics in Philosophy: Selected Essays. Ithaca, N. Y.: Cornell University Press.
Parsons, Charles, [1995] Structuralism and the concept of set. In Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter et al. (eds.), Modality, Morality, and Belief: Essays in honor of Ruth Barcan Marcus, pp. 74–92. Cambridge University Press.
Parsons, Charles, [1995a] Quine and Gödel on analyticity. In Leonardi, Paolo and Santambrogio, Marco (eds.), On Quine: New Essays, pp. 297–313. Cambridge University Press.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, [1956] Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics. Edited by Anscombe, G. E. M., Rhees, R., and von Wright, G. H.. With a translation by Anscombe, G. E. M.. Oxford: Blackwell.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×