Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-75dct Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-01T14:50:49.180Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

50 - The rise of probabilistic thinking

from 11 - Philosophy and the exact sciences

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Jan Von Plato
Affiliation:
University of Helsinki
Thomas Baldwin
Affiliation:
University of York
Get access

Summary

PROBABILITY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY SCIENCE

Variation was considered, well into the second half of the nineteenth century, to be deviation from an ideal value. This is clear in the ‘social physics’ of Adolphe Quetelet, where the ideal was represented by the notion of ‘average man’. In astronomical observation, the model behind this line of thought, there is supposed to be a true value in an observation, from which the actual value deviates through the presence of small erratic causes. In mathematical error theory, one could show that numerous small and mutually independent errors produce the familiar bell-shaped normal curve around a true value. But if observations contain a systematic error, this can be identified and its effect eliminated. All sorts of data regarding society were collected into public state records (whence comes the term statistics), showing remarkable statistical stability from year to year. Such stability, as in criminal records, was explained as the very nearly deterministic result of the sum of a great number of free individual acts (see Krüger et al. 1987 for studies of these developments).

Around 1860, the physicist James Clerk Maxwell theoretically determined a normal Gaussian distribution law for the velocities of gas molecules. This discovery later led to statistical mechanics in the work of Ludwig Boltzmann and Josiah Willard Gibbs. Here there was no true unknown value, but genuine variation not reducible to effects of external errors. The world view of classical physics held that all motions of matter follow the deterministic laws of Newtonian mechanics. It was therefore argued, throughout the second half of the nineteenth century, and well into the twentieth, that there is an inherent contradiction in the foundations of statistical physics.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2003

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

de Finetti, B. (1931). ‘Sul significato soggettivo della probabilità’ (‘On the Subjective Significance of Probability’), Fundamenta Mathematicae, vol. XVII.Google Scholar
de Finetti, B. (1937). ‘La Prévision: ses lois logiques, ses sources subjectives’, Annales de l'Institut Henri Poincaré, 7. Trans. 1964, ‘Foresight: Its Logical Laws, Its Subjective Sources’ in Kyburg, H. and Smokler, H. (eds.), Studies in Subjective Probability, New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Exner, F. (1919). Vorlesungen über die physikalischen Grundlagen der Naturwissenschaften (Introduction to the Physical Foundations of the Natural Sciences), Vienna: Franz Deuticke.Google Scholar
Feller, W. (1968). An Introduction to Probability Theory and Its Applications, vol. I, New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Heidelberger, M. (1987). ‘Fechner’s Indeterminism: From Freedom to Laws of Chance’ in Krüger, 1987, vol. I.Google Scholar
Hilbert, D. (1899). Grundlagen der Geometrie, Leipzig: Teubner.Google Scholar
Howson, C. and Urbach, P. (1989). Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach, La Salle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Jeffreys, H. (1939). Theory of Probability, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kolmogorov, A. (1933). Grundbegriffe der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung, Berlin: Springer–Verlag. Trans. 1950 Morrison, N., Foundations of the Theory of Probability, New York: Chelsea.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krüger, L.et al. (1987). The Probabilistic Revolution, 2 vols., Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Maxwell, J. C. (1873). ‘Does the Progress of Physical Science Tend to Give Any Advantage to the Opinion of Necessity (or Determinism) over that of the Contingency of Events and the Freedom of the Will’ in Campbell, L. and Garnett, W. 1882, The Life of James Clerk Maxwell, London.Google Scholar
Poincaré, H. (1912). Calcul des probabilités (The Probability Calculus), 2nd edn, Paris: Gauthier Villars.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. (1931). ‘The Foundations of Mathematics and other Logical Essays, ed. Braithwaite, R., London: Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. (1915). Der Begriff der Wahrscheinlichkeit für die mathematische Darstellung der Wirklichkeit (The Concept of Probability for the Mathematical Representation of Reality), Leipzig: Barth.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. (1935). Wahrscheinlichkeitslehre, Leiden: Sijthoff’s. Trans. 1949 Hutton, E. and Reichenbach, M., The Theory of Probability, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
van Brakel, J. (1985). ‘The Possible Influence of the Discovery of Radio-active Decay on the Concept of Physical Probability’, Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
von Kries, J. (1886). Die Principien der Wahrscheinlichkeits-Rechnung (The Principles of Probability), Freiburg: J. C. B. Mohr.Google Scholar
von Mises, R. (1928). Wahrscheinlichkeit, Statistik und Wahrheit, Vienna: Springer-Verlag. Trans. 1957 Bernstein, J. and Newton, R. G., Probability, Statistics, and Truth, New York: Dover.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
von Plato, J. (1994). Creating Modern Probability: Its Mathematics, Physics and Philosophy in Historical Perspective, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×