Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-vfjqv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T20:13:09.095Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

3 - Intrinsic Values and Biocentrism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 July 2009

Sahotra Sarkar
Affiliation:
University of Texas, Austin
Get access

Summary

Why conserve biodiversity? This normative question has traditionally been part of the core of environmental ethics. In most of the discussions in the earlier chapters of this book – though not in Chapter 2, § 2.1 – we have simply assumed that we should attempt to conserve biodiversity. We attribute value to biodiversity, preferring its presence to its absence. But what is the source of this value? Why should we conserve biodiversity? We must be able to answer these questions if we are to have any confidence that we do not attribute value to biodiversity merely out of tradition, prejudice, or (what is much more plausible) fashion: biodiversity conservation is at present very fashionable in rich Northern societies. Moreover, answering these questions explicitly and convincingly is important above and beyond our having rational justification for attributing value to biodiversity. It has practical consequences, because arguments for biodiversity conservation must be made and evaluated in the political arena where decisions about the future of our biological heritage are made.

In that political arena, not everyone attributes value to biodiversity, or at least not to the same extent that biodiversity conservationists do. Among those who do not attribute value to biodiversity to the same extent that conservationists do are the owners and shareholders of the Japanese timber companies that have devastated Southeast Asian rainforests and are now moving to the neotropics; the ranchers who are trying to convert Amazonia into pasture; the loggers in the U.S. Pacific Northwest; and, perhaps most importantly, the owners and shareholders of the multinational oil companies that are now prospecting in many places around the world, including the Alaskan tundra and neotropical rainforests (for instance, in the western Amazon).

Type
Chapter
Information
Biodiversity and Environmental Philosophy
An Introduction
, pp. 45 - 74
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×