Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-25wd4 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T10:12:26.674Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

11 - What Is the Basis of Biological Classification?

The Search for Natural Systems

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 September 2020

Kostas Kampourakis
Affiliation:
Université de Genève
Tobias Uller
Affiliation:
Lunds Universitet, Sweden
Get access

Summary

Life on Earth is astonishingly diverse. Biologists have so far discovered, named, and described approximately 1.9 million species of organisms (Ruggiero et al. 2015). But on most counts, this is only a very small part of the actual diversity of life on our planet. According to one estimate, there currently exist around 8.7 million (give or take 1.3 million) species of eukaryotic organisms (Mora et al. 2011) – not even counting bacteria and other prokaryotes, which make up by far the largest part of the biomass. Other estimates put the total number of extant species anywhere between 2 million and 1 trillion, with a recent rough estimate being 1–6 billion species (Larsen et al. 2017). But life on Earth is not only extremely diverse when it comes to organismal diversity. Biologists also talk about biodiversity in terms of genetic diversity (e.g., the genetic variation within a particular species, such as the variation of alleles within the human genome, or the genetic variation that exists in a particular local population), ecosystem diversity (the variety of ecosystems found in a particular geographic region, or on the planet as a whole), and the variety of trophic groups in a particular region, as well as other types of diversity (Faith 2016).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2020

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Agassiz, L. (2004 [1859]). Essay on Classification. Lurie, E., (ed.). Mineola, NY: Dover Publications.Google Scholar
Ainsworth, T. (2016). “Form vs. Matter.” In Zalta, E. N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/form-matter/Google Scholar
Balme, D. M. (1987). Aristotle’s Use of Division and Differentiae. In Gotthelf, A. & Lennox, J. G., (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology, pp. 6989. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bird, A. & Tobin, E. (2018): “Natural Kinds.” In: Zalta, E. N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/natural-kinds/Google Scholar
Boudry, M., Blanke, S., & Braeckman, J. (2010): How Not to Attack Intelligent Design Creationism: Philosophical Misconceptions about Methodological Naturalism. Foundations of Science 15(3): 227244.Google Scholar
Bunge, M. (1977). Treatise on Basic Philosophy, Vol. 3 – Ontology I: The Furniture of the World. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Draper, P. (2005). God, Science and Naturalism. In Wainwright, W. J. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Religion, pp. 272303. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ereshefsky, M. (2001). The Poverty of the Linnaean Hierarchy: A Philosophical Study of Biological Taxonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Faith, D. P. (2016). “Biodiversity.” In Zalta, E. N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2016 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2016/entries/biodiversity/Google Scholar
Grene, M. & Depew, D. (2004). The Philosophy of Biology: An Episodic History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Griffiths, P. E. & Stotz, K. (2006). Genes in the Postgenomic Era. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 27(6): 499521.Google Scholar
Griffiths, P. E. & Stotz, K. (2013). Genetics and Philosophy: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamilton, A. (ed.) (2014). The Evolution of Phylogenetic Systematics, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Hawley, K. & Bird, A. (2011). What Are Natural Kinds? Philosophical Perspectives 25: 205221.Google Scholar
Johannsen, W. (1909). Elemente der exakten Erblichkeitslehre (deutsche wesentlich erweiterte Ausgabe in fünfundzwanzig Vorlesungen). Jena: Verlag von Gustav Fischer.Google Scholar
Kendig, C. E. (ed.) (2016). Natural Kinds and Classification in Scientific Practice. London & New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Koslicki, K. (2008). Natural Kinds and Natural Kind Terms. Philosophy Compass 3(4): 789802.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Larsen, B. B., Miller, E. C., Rhodes, M.K., & Wiens, J. J. (2017). Inordinate Fondness Multiplied and Redistributed: The Number of Species on Earth and the New Pie of Life. Quarterly Review of Biology 92(3): 229265.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lherminer, P. & Solignac, M. (2000). L’espèce: Définitions d’auteurs’, Comptes Rendus de l’Académie des Sciences de Paris, Sciences de la Vie 323: 153165.Google Scholar
Maclaurin, J. & Sterelny, K. (2008). What Is Biodiversity? Chicago & London: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Mayden, R. L. (1997). A Hierarchy of Species Concepts: The Denouement in the Saga of the Species Problem. In Claridge, M. F., Dawah, H. A., & Wilson, M. R. (eds.), Species: The Units of Biodiversity, pp. 381424. London: Chapman and Hall.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. (2004). What Makes Biology Unique? Considerations on the Autonomy of a Scientific Discipline. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mora, C., Tittensor, D. P., Adl, S., Simpson, A. G. B., & Worm, B. (2011). How Many Species Are There on Earth and in the Ocean? PLoS Biology 9: e1001127.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
O’Grady, P. M. & DeSalle, R. (2018). Phylogeny of the Genus Drosophila. Genetics 209(1): 112.Google Scholar
Reydon, T. A. C. (2004). Why Does the Species Problem Still Persist? BioEssays 26: 300305.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Reydon, T. A. C. (2005). On the Nature of the Species Problem and the Four Meanings of “Species.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 36(1): 135158.Google Scholar
Reydon, T. A. C. (2009). Gene Names as Proper Names of Individuals: An Assessment. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60(2): 409432.Google Scholar
Reydon, T. A. C. (2013). Classifying Life, Reconstructing History and Teaching Diversity: Philosophical Issues in the Teaching of Biological Systematics and Biodiversity. Science & Education 22(2): 189220.Google Scholar
Reydon, T. A. C. (2014). Metaphysical and Epistemological Approaches to Developing a Theory of Artifact Kinds. In Franssen, M. P. M, Kroes, P., Reydon, T. A. C., & Vermaas, P. E. (eds). Artefact Kinds: Ontology and the Human-Made World, pp. 125144. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Reydon, T. A. C. & Kunz, W. (2019): “Species as Natural Entities, Instrumental Units, and Ranked Taxa: New Perspectives on the Grouping and Ranking Problems.” Biological Journal of the Linnean Society 126(4): 632636.Google Scholar
Richards, R. A. (2010). The Species Problem: A Philosophical Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ruggiero, M. A., Gordon, D. P., Orrell, T. M., et al. (2015). A Higher Level Classification of All Living Organisms. PLoS ONE 10: e0119248.Google ScholarPubMed
Sober, E. (2011). Why Methodological Naturalism? In Auletta, G., Leclerc, M., & Martínez, R. A. (eds.), Biological Evolution: Facts and Theories, pp. 359378. Rome: Gregorian & Biblical Press.Google Scholar
Walsh, D. (2006). Evolutionary Essentialism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57(2): 425448.Google Scholar
Waters, C. K. (1994). Genes Made Molecular. Philosophy of Science 61(2): 163185.Google Scholar
Waters, C. K. (2007). Causes That Make a Difference. Journal of Philosophy 104(11): 551579.Google Scholar
Waters, C. K. (2017). No General Structure. In Slater, M. H. & Yudell, Z. (eds.), Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Science: New Essays, pp. 81107. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wheeler, Q. D., Knapp, S., Stevenson, D. W., et al. (2012). Mapping the Biosphere: Exploring Species to Understand the Origin, Organization and Sustainability of Biodiversity. Systematics and Biodiversity 10(1): 120.Google Scholar
Wheeler, Q. D. & Meier, R. (eds.) (2000). Species Concepts and Phylogenetic Theory. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Wilkins, J. S. (2009). Defining Species: A Sourcebook from Antiquity to Today. New York: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Zachos, F. (2016). Species Concepts in Biology: Historical Development, Theoretical Foundations, and Practical Relevance. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×