Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-vfjqv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T12:23:32.352Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

10 - Is It Possible to Scientifically Reconstruct the History of Life on Earth?

The Biological Sciences and Deep Time

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 September 2020

Kostas Kampourakis
Affiliation:
Université de Genève
Tobias Uller
Affiliation:
Lunds Universitet, Sweden
Get access

Summary

The data-based study of long past events and processes is common throughout the sciences. Some examples are the astrophysical hypotheses that the universe began with a cosmic explosion (“big bang”), which is supported by measurements of the cosmic microwave background radiation pervading the modern universe; the hypothesis that the end-Cretaceous mass extinction was caused by a meteorite impact, which is supported by an iridium anomaly and large quantities of shocked quartz in K-Pg (Cretaceous-Paleogene) boundary sediments; and the hypothesis that all life on Earth shares a common ancestor, which is supported by analyses of shared segments of ribosomal RNA found in contemporary organisms. My interest in the methodology of the historical sciences and how it differs from that of stereotypical or “classical” (as I later dubbed it) experimental science was first piqued in the 1990s by the writings of so-called “scientific [more accurately, biblical] creationists.” Scientific creationists and their successors, members of the “Intelligent Design Network,”1 extol classical experimental research (the testing of hypotheses under controlled laboratory conditions) as the paradigm of good science, contending that historical scientific research is inferior because it uses “a form of abductive reasoning that produces competing historical hypotheses, that lead to an inference to the best current explanation rather than to an explanation that is logically compelled by experimental confirmation.”2 Proponents of intelligent design are not alone, however, in denigrating the work of historical scientists. Articulating a view held by a surprising number of experimentalists, Henry Gee, at the time a senior editor of Nature, declared that no science can be historical because conjectures about the past cannot be tested by means of controlled laboratory experiments (Gee 1999).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2020

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Cech, T. R. (1989). “Self‐Splicing and Enzymatic Activity of an Intervening Sequence RNA from Tetrahymena” – Nobel Lecture, NobelPrize.org. Nobel Media AB 2018. www.nobelprize.org/prizes/chemistry/1989/cech/lectureGoogle Scholar
Cleland, C. E. (2001). Historical Science, Experimental Science, and the Scientific Method. Geology 29(1): 987990.2.0.CO;2>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cleland, C. E. (2002). Methodological and Epistemic Differences between Historical Science and Experimental Science. Philosophy of Science 69(3): 474496.Google Scholar
Cleland, C. E. (2011). Prediction and Explanation in Historical Natural Science. British Journal of Philosophy of Science 62(3): 551582.Google Scholar
Cleland, C. E. (2013). “Common Cause Explanation and the Search for a Smoking Gun.” In Baker, V. (ed.), 125th Anniversary Volume of the Geological Society of American: Rethinking the Fabric of Geology, pp. 1–9.Google Scholar
Cleland, C. E. & Brindell, S. (2013). Science and the Messy, Uncontrollable World of Nature. In Pigliucci, M. & Boudry, M. (eds.), Reconsidering the Demarcation Problem: Philosophy of Pseudoscience, pp. 183202. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Crick, F. (1958). On Protein Synthesis. Symp. Soc. Exp. Biol. 12: 138167.Google Scholar
Currie, A. (2018). Rock, Bone, and Ruin: An Optimist’s Guide to the Historical Sciences. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
DePalma, R. A., Smit, J., Burnham, D. A., Kuiper, K., Manning, P. L., Oleinik, A., Larson, P., Maurrasse, F. J., Vellekoop, J., Richards, M. A., Gurche, L., & Alvarez, W. (2019). A Seismically Induced Onshore Surge Deposit at the KPg Boundary, North Dakota. PNAS 116(17): 81908199.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Franklin, A. (1990). Experiment: Right or Wrong. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gee, H. (1999). In Search of Deep Time. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, C. (1945). Studies in the Logic of Confirmaton. Mind 54(213): 126.Google Scholar
Henderson, L. (2019). “The Problem of Induction.” In E. N. Zalta, ed., (spring 2019 edition), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/induction-problemGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1991). Counterfactual Dependence and Time’s Arrow. In Jackson, F., (ed.), Conditionals, pp. 4675. Oxford: Oxford University Press,Google Scholar
Mitchell, S. D. (2002). Ceteris Paribus – An Inadequate Representation for Biological Contingency. Erkenntnis 57(3): 329350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Petersen, S. V., Dutton, A., & Lohmann, K. C. (2016). End-Cretaceous Extinction in Antarctica Linked to Both Deccan Volcanism and Meteorite Impact via Climate Change. Nat. Commun 7: 12079. doi: 10.1038/ncomms12079CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Popper, K. (1963). Conjectures and Refutations. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Powell, J. L. (1998). Night Comes to the Cretaceous. San Diego, New York, and London: Harcourt Brace & Company.Google Scholar
Preston, D. (2019). “The Day the Dinosaurs Died.” The New Yorker, April issue. www.newyorker.com/magazine/2019/04/08/the-day-the-dinosaurs-diedGoogle Scholar
Punekar, J., Mateo, P., & Keller, G. (2014). “Effects of Deccan Volcanism on Paleoenvironment and Planktic Foraminifera: A Global Survey.” The Geological Society of American, Special Paper 505.Google Scholar
Raup, D. M. & Sepkoski, J. J. Jr. (1984). Periodicity of Extinctions in the Geologic Past. PNAS 81(3): 801805.Google Scholar
Sakamoto, M., Benon, M. J., & Venditti, C. (2016). Dinosaurs in Decline Tens of Millions of Years before Their Final Extinction. PNAS 113(18): 50365040.Google Scholar
Schoene, B. Eddy, M. P., Samperton, K. M., Keller, C. B., Keller, G., Adatte, T., & Khadri, S. F. R. (2019). U-Pb Constraints on Pulsed Eruption of the Deccan Traps across the End-Cretaceous Mass Extinction. Science 363(6429): 862866.Google Scholar
Schulte, P., Alegret, L., Arenillas, I., Arz, J. A., Barton, P. J., Brown, P. R., Bralower, T. J., Christeson, G. L, Claeys, P., Cockell, C. S., Collins, G. S., Deutsch, A., Goldin, T. J. Goto, K., Grajales-Nishimura, J. M., Grieve, R. A, Gulick, S. P., Johnson, K. R., Kiessling, W., Koeberl, C., Kring, D. A., MacLeod, K. G., Matsui, T., Melosh, J., Montanari, A., Morgan, J. V., Neal, C. R., Nichols, D. J., Norris, R. D., Pierazzo, E., Ravizza, G., Rebolledo-Vieyra, M., Reimold, W. U., Robin, E., Salge, T., Speijer, R. P., Sweet, A. R., Urrutia-Fucugauchi, J., Vajda, V., Whalen, M. T., & Willumsen, P. S. (2010). The Chicxulub Asteroid Impact and Mass Extinction at the Cretaceous-Paleogene Boundary. Science 327(5970): 12141218.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Smithwick, F. M., Nicholls, R., Cuthill, I. C., & Venther, J. (2017). Countershading and Stripes in the Theropod Dinosaur Sinosauropteryx Reveal Heterogeneous Habitats in the Early Cretaceous Jehol Biota. Current Biology 27(21): 33373342. e2. doi: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2017.09.032Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1988). Reconstructing the Past. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sprain, C. J., Renne, P. R., Anderkluysen, L., Pande, K., Self, S., & Mittal, T. (2019). The Eruptive Tempo of Deccan Volcanism in Relation to the Cretaceous-Paleogene Boundary. Science 363(6429): 866870.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steinle, F. (1997). New Fields: Exploratory Uses of Experiment. Philosophy of Science 64 (Supplement): S65S74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steinle, F. (2002). Experiments in History and Philosophy of Science. Perspectives on Science 10(4): 408432.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turner, D. (2007). Making Prehistory: Historical Science and the Scientific Realism Debate. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yang, Z., Chen, F., Alvarado, J. B., & Benner, S. A. (2011). Amplification, Mutation, and Sequencing of a Six Letter Synthetic Genetic System. J. Am. Chem. Soc. 133(38): 1510515112.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×