Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-8zxtt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T15:23:50.475Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Arguing For Eliminativism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

José Luis Bermúdez
Affiliation:
Washington University in St. Louis
Brian L. Keeley
Affiliation:
Pitzer College, Claremont
Get access

Summary

I am sure I am not alone in reporting that the greater exposure I have to experimental work in scientific psychology and neuroscience the less value there seems to be in our commonsense psychological framework of belief, desire, and the other propositional attitudes. Commonsense psychological concepts hardly feature at all in cognitive science and cognitive neuroscience. Theorists in these areas either eschew psychological vocabulary altogether or appeal to shadowy neologisms such as “cognize” or “encode.” It is often difficult to see where the points of contact are between the serious scientific study of the mind and the apparent platitudes that philosophers tend to take as their starting point. And even when one can see where the points of contact are, scientific psychology and commonsense psychology are often in tension with each other. Many areas of scientific psychology place serious pressure on our image of ourselves as rational, consistent agents with stable character traits. Yet this image of ourselves is at the heart of commonsense psychology. Commonsense psychology tells one story about the “springs of action” – about how and why we behave the way we do – while the story (or rather, stories) told by scientific psychology and cognitive neuroscience seem completely different and in many ways incompatible with a commonsense understanding of human behavior.

In the face of all this some philosophers, most prominently of course Paul Churchland, have argued for a wholesale rejection of our commonsense ways of thinking about the mind.

Type
Chapter
Information
Paul Churchland , pp. 32 - 65
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Amazeen, E. L., & Turvey, M. T. (1996). “Weight perception and the haptic size-weight illusion are functions of the inertia tensor.” Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 22: 213–32.Google ScholarPubMed
Axelrod, R. (1984). The Evolution of Cooperation. Harmondsworth, Penguin.Google Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. (2005). “The domain of folk psychology.” In Hear, A. O' (Ed.), Mind and Persons. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. (2005). Philosophy of Psychology: A Contemporary Introduction. London, RoutledgeGoogle Scholar
Boghossian, P. (1990). “The status of content.” The Philosophical Review 99: 157–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carello, C., & Turvey, M. T. (2004). “Physics and psychology of the muscle sense.” Current Directions in Psychological Science 13: 25–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1981). “Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes.” Journal of Philosophy 78: 67–90.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1989). “Folk psychology and the explanation of human behavior.” Philosophical Perspectives 3: 225–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1992). “Activation vectors vs. propositional attitudes: How the brain represents reality.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52: 419–524.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1998). “Conceptual similarity across sensory and neural diversity: The Fodor/Lepore challenge answered.” Journal of Philosophy 65: 5–32.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M., & Churchland, P. S. (1998). On the Contrary: Critical Essays, 1987–1997. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. S., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1992). The Computational Brain. Cambridge,MA, MIT Press/Bradford Books.Google Scholar
Cohen, A., & Feintuch, U. (2002). “The dimensional-action system: A distinct visual system.” In Prinz, W. and Hommel, B. (Eds.), Common Mechanisms in Perception and Action: Attention and Performance XIX. Oxford, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, A., & Shoup, R. (1997). “Perceptual dimensional constraints on response selection processes.” Cognitive Psychology 32: 128–81CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Darley, J. M., & Batson, D. (1973). “From Jerusalem to Jericho: A study of situational and dispositional variables in helping behavior.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 27: 100–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, M. K., Stone, T. (eds.) (1995). Folk Psychology: The Theory of Mind Debate, Oxford, BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Doris, J. (2002). Lack of Character. New York, Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J., & Pylyshyn, Z. (1988). “Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis.” Cognition 28: 3–71CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Isen, A. M., & Levin, P. A. (1972). “Effect of feeling good on helping: Cookies and kindness.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 21: 384–8CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Laakso, Aarre , & Cottrell, Garrison W . (1998). How can I know what You think?: Assessing representational similarity in neural systems. Proceedings of the Twentieth Annual Cognitive Science Conference, Madison, WI. Mahwah, NJ, Lawrence ErlbaumGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1994). “Reduction of mind.” In Guttenplan, S. (Ed.), Companion to the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford, Blackwell.Google Scholar
Matthews, K. E., & Canon, L. K. (1975). Environmental noise level as a determinant of helping behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 32: 571–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maynard, Smith J. (1982). Evolution and the Theory of Games. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (1995). The Visual Brain in Action. Oxford, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
P. Pettit (1991). “Decision theory as folk psychology.” In Bacharach, M. & Hurley, S. (eds.), Foundations of Decision Theory. Oxford, BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Sejnowski, T. J., & Rosenberg, C. (1987). “Parallel networks that learn to pronounce English text.” Complex Systems 1:145–68Google Scholar
Skyrms, B . (1996). The Evolution of the Social Contract, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smolensky, P. (1988). “On the proper treatment of connectionism.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11(1): 1–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turvey, M. T. (1996). Dynamic touch. American Psychologist 51: 1134–51CrossRef
Ungerleider, L. G., & Mishkin, M. (1982). Two cortical visual systems. In Ingle, D. J., Goodale, M. A. & Mansfield, R. J. W. (Eds). Analysis of Visual Behavior. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×