Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-xfwgj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-07T08:27:13.527Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

17 - A Reasonable Thing That Just Might Work

from Part III - Nonlocality: Illusion or Reality?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 September 2016

Daniel Rohrlich
Affiliation:
Ben-Gurion University of the Negev
Shan Gao
Affiliation:
Chinese Academy of Sciences, Beijing
Get access

Summary

Abstract

In 1964, John Bell proved that quantum mechanics is “unreasonable” (to use Einstein's term): there are nonlocal bipartite quantum correlations. But they are not the most nonlocal bipartite correlations consistent with relativistic causality (“no superluminal signalling”); maximally nonlocal “superquantum” (or “PR-box”) correlations are also consistent with relativistic causality. I show that – unlike quantum correlations – these correlations do not have a classical limit consistent with relativistic causality. The generalization of this result to all stronger-than-quantum nonlocal correlations is a derivation of Tsirelson's bound – a theorem of quantum mechanics – from the three axioms of relativistic causality, nonlocality, and the existence of a classical limit. But is it reasonable to derive (a part of) quantum mechanics from the unreasonable axiom of nonlocality?! I consider replacing the nonlocality axiom with an equivalent axiom that even Bell and Einstein might have considered reasonable: an axiom of local retrocausality.

In 1964, John Bell [1] proved that quantum mechanics is “unreasonable,” as defined by Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen [2] in 1935: “No reasonable definition of reality could be expected to permit this.” “This” (i.e., violation of “Einstein separability,” to use a technical term, or “spooky action at a distance,” as Einstein put it) turns out to be endemic to quantum mechanics. For example, pairs of photons measured at spacelike separations may yield nonlocal quantum correlations, i.e., correlations that cannot be traced to any data or “programs” the photons carry with them. As Bell [3] put it 20 years later, “For me, it is so reasonable to assume that the photons in those experiments carry with them programs, which have been correlated in advance, telling them how to behave. This is so rational that I think that when Einstein saw that, and the others refused to see it, he was the rational man. The other people, although history has justified them, were burying their heads in the sand. I feel that Einstein's intellectual superiority over Bohr, in this instance, was enormous; a vast gulf between the man who saw clearly what was needed, and the obscurantist. So for me, it is a pity that Einstein's idea doesn't work. The reasonable thing just doesn't work.”

Type
Chapter
Information
Quantum Nonlocality and Reality
50 Years of Bell's Theorem
, pp. 295 - 304
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2016

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

[1] J.S., Bell, On the Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen paradox, Physics 1, 195 (1964).Google Scholar
[2] A., Einstein, B., Podolsky and N., Rosen, Can quantum-mechanical description of reality be considered complete? Phys. Rev. 47, 777 (1935);Google Scholar
see also N., Bohr, Can quantummechanical description of reality be considered complete? Phys. Rev. 48, 696 (1935).Google Scholar
[3] J., Bernstein, Quantum Profiles (Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press), 1991, p. 84.
[4] I., Newton, letter to R., Bentley, 25 February 1693, in The Correspondence of Isaac Newton, Vol. III, ed. H.W., Turnbull (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press), 1961, pp. 253–6, cf. p. 254; punctuation and spelling edited.
[5] J.F., Clauser, M.A., Horne, A., Shimony and R.A., Holt, Proposed experiment to test local hidden-variable theories, Phys. Rev. Lett. 23, 880 (1969).Google Scholar
[6] B.S., Tsirelson (Cirel'son), Quantum generalizations of Bell's inequality, Lett. Math. Phys. 4, 93 (1980).Google Scholar
[7] S., Popescu and D., Rohrlich, Quantum nonlocality as an axiom, Found. Phys. 24, 379 (1994).Google Scholar
[8] L., Khalfin and B., Tsirelson, Quantum and quasi-classical analogs of Bell inequalities, in P., Lahti et al. (eds.), Symposium on the Foundations of Modern Physics ‘85 (Singapore: World Scientific), 1985, p. 441;
P., Rastall, Locality, Bell's theorem, and quantum mechanics, Found. Phys. 15, 963 (1985);Google Scholar
G., Krenn and K., Svozil, Strongerthan- quantum correlations, Found. Phys. 28, 971 (1998).Google Scholar
[9] D., Rohrlich, PR-box correlations have no classical limit, in D.C., Struppa and J.M., Tollaksen (eds.), Quantum Theory: A Two-Time Success Story [Yakir Aharonov Festschrift], (Milan: Springer), 2013, pp. 205–11.
[10] D. Rohrlich, Stronger-than-quantum bipartite correlations violate relativistic causality in the classical limit, arXiv:1408.3125. See also N. Gisin, Quantum measurement of spins and magnets, and the classical limit of PR-boxes, arXiv:1407.8122.
[11] W. van, Dam, Nonlocality and Communication Complexity (Ph.D. thesis), Oxford University (2000); Implausible consequences of superstrong nonlocality, quantph/0501159 (2005); D. Dieks, Inequalities that test locality in quantum mechanics, Phys. Rev. A 66, 062104 (2002); H. Buhrman and S. Massar, Causality and Tsirelson's bounds, Phys. Rev. A 72, 052103 (2005); J. Barrett and S. Pironio, Popescu–Rohrlich 304 A Reasonable Thing That Just Might Work correlations as a unit of nonlocality, Phys. Rev. Lett. 95, 140401 (2005); G. Brassard, H. Buhrman, N. Linden, A.A. Methot, A. Tapp and F. Unger, Limit on nonlocality in any world in which communication complexity is not trivial, Phys. Rev. Lett. 96, 250401 (2006); J. Barrett, Information processing in generalized probabilistic theories, Phys. Rev. A 75, 032304 (2007); D. Gross, M. Muller, R. Colbeck and O.O. Dahlsten, All reversible dynamics in maximally nonlocal theories are trivial, Phys. Rev. Lett. 104, 080402 (2010).
[12] M., Pawłowski et al., Information causality as a physical principle, Nature 461, 1101 (2009).Google Scholar
[13] M., Navascues and H., Wunderlich, A glance beyond the quantum model, Proc. R. Soc. A 466, 881 (2010).Google Scholar
[14] N., Brunner and P., Skrzypczyk, Nonlocality distillation and postquantum theories with trivial communication complexity, Phys. Rev. Lett. 102, 160403 (2009).Google Scholar
[15] H., Price, Time's Arrow and Archimedes' Point: New Directions for the Physics of Time (New York: Oxford Univ. Press), 1996; P.W. Evans, H. Price and K.B. Wharton, New slant on the EPR–Bell experiment, Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 64, 297 (2013); H. Price and K. Wharton, Dispelling the quantum spooks – A clue the A. Einstein missed?, arXiv:1307.7744v1.
[16] Y., Aharonov, P.G., Bergmann and J.L., Lebowitz, Time symmetry in the quantum process of measurement, Phys. Rev. 134 (1964), B1410. See also Y. Aharonov and D. Rohrlich, op. cit., Chap. 10.Google Scholar
[17] D.M., Greenberger, M., Horne and A., Zeilinger, Going beyond Bell's theorem, in M., Kafatos (ed.), Bell's Theorem, Quantum Theory, and Conceptions of the Universe [Proceedings of the Fall Workshop, Fairfax, Virginia, October 1988], (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic), 1989, pp. 69–72.
[18] J., Grunhaus, S., Popescu and D., Rohrlich, Jamming nonlocal quantum correlations, Phys. Rev. A 53 (1996) 3781; D. Rohrlich, Three attempts at two axioms for quantum mechanics, in Y. Ben-Menahem and M. Hemmo (eds.), (The Frontiers Collection) Probability in Physics (Berlin: Springer), 2012, pp. 187–200. The latter paper notes that jamming arises in quantum mechanics, contrary to what the former paper assumes.Google Scholar
[19] Y., Aharonov and D., Rohrlich, op. cit., Sect. 18.2.
[20] Y., Aharonov and L., Vaidman, The two-state vector formalism: An updated review, in J.G., Muga, R.S., Mayato and I., Egusquiza (eds.), Time in Quantum Mechanics, Vol. 1 [Lecture Notes in Physics 734], 2nd ed. (Berlin: Springer), 2008, pp. 399–447. See also Y. Aharonov and D. Rohrlich, op. cit., Chap. 18.
[21] Y., Aharonov, D.Z., Albert and L., Vaidman, How the result of a measurement of a component of the spin of a spin- 1 2 particle can turn out to be 100, Phys. Rev. Lett. 60, 1351 (1988); see also Y. Aharonov and D. Rohrlich, op. cit., Chaps. 16–17.Google Scholar
[22] N., Argaman, Bell's theorem and the causal arrow of time, Am. J. Phys. 78, 1007 (2010).Google Scholar
[23] J., Bernstein, op. cit., pp. 66–67.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×