Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wzw2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-02T21:33:31.484Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Meditation 2 - On the concept of law

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

Friedrich Kratochwil
Affiliation:
European University Institute, Florence
Get access

Summary

Introduction

That nations dwell in anarchy has been the mainstay lore of realists of different stripes. Yet even Hobbes realized that things are not that simple. He distinguished the “misery” of the state of nature among individuals from that which prevails among “persons of sovereign authority.” Contrary to the necessity of transcending the war of all against all, states can counteract the dangers that arise in the case of individual vulnerability. They can organize police forces and a military, and contract alliances, thereby providing at least a modicum of security. Moreover, through establishing a public order, states create incentives for the development of a “commodious living” that comes to a naught when no sovereign keeps all of his subjects “in awe.”

Those realists, who were not captured by certain “assumptions” by which the homo politicus has to maximize power analogous to the homo economicus’ amassing of revenue, but who were more historically inclined, as they were interested in the actual functioning of the (European) state system, paid close attention to the conventions and institutions facilitating the relations among “persons of sovereign authority.” Thus the institution of treaty making (bilaterally or in congresses), of the acquisition of titles and their transfers, and the attempts to regulate the use of force (ius ad bellum and in bello) emerged quickly as core concerns for a systematic analysis. Hume had already considered these norms and institutions as fundamental in the sense that without the establishment of certain normative expectations in regard to those concerns, no social system can reproduce itself.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Status of Law in World Society
Meditations on the Role and Rule of Law
, pp. 50 - 74
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan, ed. by C. B. Macpherson (London: Penguin, 1985), Chapter 13, at 188Google Scholar
Morgenthau, Hans, Politics Among Nations, 4th edition (New York: Knopf, 1967), 6th principle of realism, at 11Google Scholar
Bull, Hedley, The Anarchical Society (New York: Columbia University Press, 1970), Chapter 2Google Scholar
Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature, Book II, section “On Morals,” in Gree, Thomas H. and Grose, Thomas H. (eds.), The Philosophical Works (Aalen: Scientia 1886, reprinted 1964)Google Scholar
Dunne, Tim, “The English School,” in Reus-Smit, Christian and Snidal, Duncan (eds.), The Oxford Handbook on International Relations (Oxford University Press, 2008), 267–85Google Scholar
Bull, Hedley, Kingsbury, Benedict and Roberts, Adam (eds.), Hugo Grotius and International Relations (Oxford: Clarendon, 1992)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wight, Martin, Systems of States (Leicester University Press, 1977)Google Scholar
Reus-Smit, Christian, “Constitutional Structure of International Society and the Nature of Fundamental Institutions,” International Organization, vol. 51, no. 4 (1997), 555–89CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buzan, Barry, From International to World Society? English School Theory and the Social Structure of Globalization (Cambridge University Press, 2004)Google Scholar
Friedmann, Wolfgang, The Changing Structure of International Law (New York: Columbia University Press, 1964)Google Scholar
Kelsen, Hans, Principles of International Law (New York: Holt, 1966)Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A., The Concept of Law (New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1961), 224Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton University Press, 1979)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Philosophical Investigations, transl. by Elisabeth Anscombe (New York: Macmillan, 1953), para. 66Google Scholar
Adler, Emanuel and Pouliot, Vincent (eds.), International Practices (Cambridge University Press, 2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, H. L. A., “Definition and Theory in Jurisprudence,” Law Quarterly Review, vol. 70 (1954), 37–60Google Scholar
Brunée, Jutta and Toope, Stephen “Interactional International Law and the Practice of Legality,” in Adler, Emmanuel and Pouliot, Vincent (eds.), International Practices (Cambridge University Press, 2011), 108–36, at 109CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brunée, Jutta and Toope, Stephen, Legitimacy and Legality in International Law: an Interactional Account (Cambridge University Press, 2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, Saul, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982)Google Scholar
Polanyi, Michael, Personal Knowledge (University of Chicago Press, 1958)Google Scholar
Leitner, Brian, “American Legal Realism,” in Golding, Martin and Edmunson, William (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory (Oxford: Blackwell, 2003), 50–62Google Scholar
Derrida, Jacques, “Force of Law,” Cardozo Law Review, vol. 11 (1989–1990), 920–1045, at 939–41Google Scholar
Turner, Stephen, The Social Theory of Practices: Tradition, Tacit Knowledge, and Presuppositions (University of Chicago Press, 1994)Google Scholar
Kratochwil, Friedrich and Ruggie, John, “The State of the Art on the Art of the State,” International Organization, vol. 40 (Fall 1986), 753–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sharrock, Wes and Dennis, Alex, “That We Obey Rules Blindly Does Not Mean that We Are Blindly Subservient to Rules,” Theory, Culture and Society, vol. 25 no. 2 (2008), 33–50, at 35CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, John, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. by Kenneth Winkler (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1996), Book IIGoogle Scholar
Patterson, Dennis, “The Poverty of Interpretive Universalism: Toward the Reconstruction of Legal Theory,” Texas Law Review, vol. 72 (1993), 1–56 at 54fGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, MA:Harvard, 1977), Chapter 4Google Scholar
Simmons, N. E., “Imperial Visions and Mundane Practices,” Cambridge Law Journal, vol. 46 (Nov 1987), 465–88CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koskenniemi, Marti, From Apology to Utopia (Cambridge University Press, 2005), 67Google Scholar
Lyotard, Jean François, “Sensus Communis,” in Benjamin, Andrew (ed.), Judging Lyotard (London: Routledge, 1992), 1–25Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine, The Sources of Normativity (Cambridge University Press, 1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ferrara, Alessandro, Justice and Judgement (London: Sage, 1999)Google Scholar
Habermas, Juergen, Theorie des Kommunikativen Handelns (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1981)Google Scholar
Chayes, Abram and Chayes, Antonia Handler, The New Sovereignty: Compliance with International Regulatory Agreements (Princeton University Press, 1995)Google Scholar
Kaul, Inge, et al., Providing Public Goods (New York: Oxford, 2003)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldsmith, Jack and Posner, Eric A, The Limits of International Law (Oxford University Press, 2005), 15Google Scholar
McDougall, Myres and Lasswell, Harold, “The Identification and Appraisal of Diverse Systems of Public Order,” in Falk, Richard and Mendlovitz, Saul (eds.), The Strategy of World Order, vol. II, International Law (New York: World Law Fund, 1966), 45–74, at 54Google Scholar
Herodot, , Histories, vol. III, trans. by Godley, A. D., Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1938), book V, para. 95, p. 117Google Scholar
Weber, Max: “Of Law and in Economy and Society,” in Rheinstein, Max and Weber, Max, Of Law in Economy and Society (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1954)Google Scholar
Rosen, Lawrence, “Equity and Discretion in Islamic Law,” in Rosen, Lawrence, The Justice of Islam (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, Joseph, The Authority of Law (Oxford: Clarendon, 1997), 113Google Scholar
Aristotle, , The Art of Rhetoric (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1956)Google Scholar
Maitland, Fredrick, “Why the History of English Law is not Written,” in The Collected Papers of Fredrick Maitland, 3 vols., ed. by H. A. L. Fisher (Cambridge University Press, 1911), vol. I, p. 491Google Scholar
Butterfield, Herbert, The Whig Interpretation of History (New York: Norton, 1965)Google Scholar
Duby, Georges, Le Dimanche de Bouvines (Paris: Gallimard, 1973)Google Scholar
Krygier, Martin, “Law as a Tradition,” Law and Philosophy, vol. 5 no. 2 (1986), 237–62, at 251CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weiler, J. H. H., “The Geology of International Law: Governance, Democracy and Legitimacy,” Zeitschrift für ausländisches öffentliches Recht und Vöelkerrecht, vol. 64 (2004), 547–62Google Scholar
Gadamer, Hands Georg, Truth and Method, 2nd edn. (London: Sheed and Ward, 1979), p. 263fGoogle Scholar
Kennedy, David, “Primitive Legal Scholarship,” Harvard International Law Journal, vol. 27, no. 1 (1986), 1–98Google Scholar
Waltz, Kenneth, Theory of International Politics (Reading, MA: Addison Wesley, 1979)Google Scholar
Austin, John, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, ed. by Wilfrid E. Rumble (Cambridge University Press (1832) 1995), 141–3 and 254–64CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldsmith, Jack and Levinson, Daryl, “Law for States: International Law, Constitutional Law, Public Law,” Harvard Law Review, vol. 122 (May 2009), 1791–868, at 1803Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • On the concept of law
  • Friedrich Kratochwil, European University Institute, Florence
  • Book: The Status of Law in World Society
  • Online publication: 05 June 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139583930.006
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • On the concept of law
  • Friedrich Kratochwil, European University Institute, Florence
  • Book: The Status of Law in World Society
  • Online publication: 05 June 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139583930.006
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • On the concept of law
  • Friedrich Kratochwil, European University Institute, Florence
  • Book: The Status of Law in World Society
  • Online publication: 05 June 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139583930.006
Available formats
×