Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-7nlkj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-05T03:56:45.686Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

39 - Rights, natural rights, and the philosophy of law

from X - Politics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Get access

Summary

Rights derived from above: John of Salisbury

In the period from John of Salisbury to Richard Hooker and Francisco Suárez the concept of a right and the theory of natural rights emerged from a religious view of society with which the subsequent politics of rights has more or less willingly dispensed. At the outset sacral kingship and, more convincingly, the authority of the Church, especially the papacy, claimed divine warrant and support. At the same time those who wished to resist their superiors could usually allege violation of mutual obligation, or failure to conform to the requirements of rulership, and Christian impulses to condemn, flee, or find a radical alternative to ordinary worldly life were always active.

John of Salisbury's Policraticus, although a highly personal work, shows important aspects of the original view. John regards rights (iura) as the vital means which an ideal court (an Areopagus) would give each class or profession in a community as required to perform its proper functions (Policr. I.3) – functions in an organic social whole, which has as its soul the priesthood and whose princely head of government is an earthly image of the divine majesty. John draws his organic model for society from classical sources but adapts it to medieval Christian needs by making the sacerdotal soul a distinct class, of which the prince is in some sense a minister. In the same way, he takes over the Roman jurists' impersonal definition of fairness or equity as a rational equilibration of disparate things with respect to the same laws (iura), bestowing on each what is his own, but identifies such aequitas with the justice of God, to which rulers are emphatically subordinate.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy
From the Rediscovery of Aristotle to the Disintegration of Scholasticism, 1100–1600
, pp. 738 - 756
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1982

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bucher, Eugen (1965). Das subjektive Recht als Normsetzungsbefugnis, J. C. B. MohrGoogle Scholar
Cargill Thompson, W. D. J. (1972). ‘The philosopher of the “politic society”: Richard Hooker as a political thinker’ in Hill, W. Speed (ed.) Studies in Richard Hooker: Essays Preliminary to an Edition of his Works, Case Western Reserve UniversityGoogle Scholar
Gewirth, Alan (1951). Marsilius of Padua and Medieval Political Philosophy, Vol. 1 of Marsilius of Padua: The Defender of Peace (Records of Civilization, Sources and Studies, 46), Columbia University PressGoogle Scholar
Hooker, Richard (1977–81). Of the Laws of Ecclesiastical Polity in Hill, W. Speed (ed.) The Folger Library Edition of the Works of Richard Hooker (3 vols.), Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
John, Wyclif (1885–1904). De Ciuili Dominio (4 vols.), Trübner (Reprinted Johnson Reprint Co. 1966)Google Scholar
Kantorowicz, E. H. (1957). The King's Two Bodies. A Study in Mediaeval Political Theology, Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Kasper, Franz (1967). Das subjektive Recht–Begriffsbildung und Bedeutungsmehrheit (Freiburger Rechts- und Staatswissenschaftliche Abhandlungen, 25). Muller, C. F.Google Scholar
Lagarde, G. (1956–70). La naissance de l'esprit laíque au déclin du moyen âge (3rd ed.), E. NauwelaertsGoogle Scholar
Lewis, Ewart (1963). ‘The “positivism” of Marsiglio of Padua’, Speculum 38:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mcgrade, A. S. (1963). ‘The coherence of Hooker's Polity: the books on power’, Journal of the History of Ideas 24:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mcgrade, A. S. (1974). The Political Thought of William of Ockham. Personal and Institutional Principles (Cambridge Studies in Medieval Life and Thought, third series, 7), Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mcgrade, A. S. (1978). ‘Repentance and Spiritual Power: Book VI of Richard Hooker's Of the Laws of Ecclesiastical Polity’, Journal of Ecclesiastical History 29:CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miethke, J. (1969). Ockhams Weg zur Sozialphibsophie, De GruyterCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Munz, Peter (1952). The Place of Hooker in the History of Thought, Routledge & Kegan PaulGoogle Scholar
Rubenstein, Nicolai (1965). ‘Marsilius of Padua and Italian political thought of his time’ in Hale, J. R., Highfield, J. R. L., and Smalley, B. (eds.) Europe in the Late Middle Ages, Northwestern University PressGoogle Scholar
Skinner, Quentin (1978). The Foundations of Modern Political Thought. Vol. 1: The Renaissance. Vol. 2: The Age of Reformation, Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Tierney, Brian (1954). ‘Ockham, the conciliar theory and the canonists’, The Journal of the History of Ideas 15:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tierney, Brian (1955a). ‘Grosseteste and the theory of papal sovereignty’, Journal of Ecclesiastical History 6:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tierney, Brian (1955b). Foundations of the Conciliar Theory, Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Tierney, Brian (1966). ‘Medieval canon law and western constitutionalism’, The Catholic Historical Review 52:.Google Scholar
Tierney, Brian (1975). ‘“Divided sovereignty” at Constance: a problem of medieval and early modern political theory’, Annuarium Historiae Conciliorum 7:.Google Scholar
Ullmann, W. (1966a). The Individual and Society in the Middle Ages, Johns Hopkins University PressGoogle Scholar
Ullmann, W. (1966b). Principles of Government and Politics in the Middle Ages (2nd edn.), MethuenGoogle Scholar
Ullmann, W. (1970). The Growth of Papal Government in the Middle Ages (4th edn.), MethuenGoogle Scholar
Villey, M. (1964). ‘La genèse du droit subjectif chez Guillaume d'Occam’, Archives de philosophie du droit 9:.Google Scholar
William, Ockham (1494). Dialogus in Ockham, William, vol. IGoogle Scholar
William, Ockham (1963–74). Opus nonaginta dierum, chapters 1–6 ed. Offler, H. S. (1974), Guillelmi de Ockham Opera Politica, 1 (rev. edn.), Manchester University Press; chapters 7–124 ed. Bennett, R. F. and Offler, H. S. (1963), Guillelmi de Ockham Opera Politica, 2, Manchester University PressGoogle Scholar
William, Ockham (1974b). Octo quaestiones de potestate papae, ed. Offler, H. S., Guillelmi de Ockham Opera>politica, 1 (rev. edn.), Manchester University PressGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×