Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-vsgnj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-16T23:44:46.358Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

12 - Cosmology

from PART IV - PHYSICS AND METAPHYSICS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

David Furley
Affiliation:
Princeton University
Keimpe Algra
Affiliation:
Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands
Jonathan Barnes
Affiliation:
Université de Genève
Jaap Mansfeld
Affiliation:
Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands
Malcolm Schofield
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
Get access

Summary

Introduction: the fourth-century legacy

By the time of the death of Aristotle, there was some measure of agreement among educated Greeks about the nature of the cosmos. The word cosmos itself soon acquired a canonical meaning. Aristotle used it in its wider sense to mean ‘good order’ or ‘elegance’, but in the context of the study of the natural world he used it as a synonym for ouranos, thinking particularly of the heavens and their orderly movements. But the word was defined by the Stoic Chrysippus as a ‘system of heaven and earth and the natures contained in these’ (Ar. Did. fr. 31 ap. Stob. I.184.8–10), and this is a definition that reappears, sometimes with small variations, fairly frequently. It is repeated by the Peripatetic author of the treatise On the Cosmos attributed to Aristotle (391b9). The Epicurean definition was not significantly different (Ep. Epistula ad Pythoclem 88).

From the start this definition marks a difference between the classical use of the word and our own in the twentieth century. The ancient use of the word leaves open the possibility that the cosmos in which we live is only a part of the universe. A cosmos is a limited system, bounded on its periphery by the heavens: what lay beyond the heavens of our cosmos, if anything, was open to debate. This chapter will therefore be careful to preserve the distinction between the cosmos and the universe.

Aristotle had already provided arguments to show that the earth does not move and occupies a position at the centre of the cosmos (In Aristotelis De caelo commentaria II. 14).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Algra, K. A. (1988) ‘The early Stoics on the immobility and coherence of the cosmos’, Phronesis 33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Algra, K. A. (1992) ‘“Place”, in context: on Theophrastus fr. 21 and 22 Wimmer’, in Fortenbaugh, et al. (1992).Google Scholar
Algra, K. A. (1993) ‘Posidonius' conception of the extra-cosmic void: the evidence and the arguments’, Mnemosyne 46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Algra, K. A. (1995) Concepts of Space in Greek Thought, PhA 65 (Leiden).Google Scholar
Asmis, E. (1984) Epicurus' Scientific Method, Cornell studies in classical philology 42 (Ithaca/London).Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (1989a) ‘The size of the sun in antiquity’, ACD 25.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (1978) ‘La doctrine du retour éternel’, in Brunschwig, (1978a).Google Scholar
Bodnár, I. (1992) ‘Anaximander on the stability of the earth’, Phronesis 37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clay, D. (1983a) Lucretius and Epicurus (Ithaca, New York/London).Google Scholar
Cohen, M. R. & Drabkin, I. E., edd. (1966) A Source Book in Greek Science (Cambridge, Mass.; 1st edn New York 1948).Google Scholar
Englert, W. G. (1987) Epicurus on the Swerve and Voluntary Action, American Classical Studies 16 (Atlanta).Google Scholar
Furley, D. J. (1967) Two Studies in the Greek Atomists, 1. Indivisible Magnitudes. 2. Aristotle and Epicurus on Voluntary Action (Princeton).Google Scholar
Furley, D. J. (1985) ‘Strato's theory of the void’, in Wiesner (1985–7) I.Google Scholar
Furley, D. J. (1989a (1966)) ‘Lucretius and the Stoics’, in Furley (1989c).Google Scholar
Furley, D. J. (1989b (1985)) ‘Strato's theory of the void’, in Furley (1989c).Google Scholar
Furley, D. J. (1989c) Cosmic Problems: Essays on Greek and Roman Philosophy of Nature (Cambridge).Google Scholar
Glucker, J. (1988) ‘Πρòζτòν ∊ιπóντα – Sources and credibility of De Stoicorum repugnantiis 8’, ICS 13.Google Scholar
Gottschalk, H. B., ed. (1965) Strato of Lampsacus: Some Texts, Edited with a Commentary, Proceedings of the Leeds Philosophical and Literary Society, Lit. and Hist. Sect. (11.6).Google Scholar
Gottschalk, H. B. (1967) (rev. Steinmetz 1964) Gnomon 39.Google Scholar
Hahm, D. E. (1977) The Origins of Stoic Cosmology (Columbus Ohio).Google Scholar
Hahm, D. E. (1991) ‘Aristotle and the Stoics: a methodological crux’, AGPh 73.Google Scholar
Huby, P. M. (1978) ‘Epicurus' attitude to Democritus’, Phronesis, 23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kenney, E. J. (1972) ‘The historical imagination of Lucretius’, G&R 19.Google Scholar
Kidd, I. G. (1988) Posidonius, II: The Commentary, 2 vols., Cambridge Classical Texts and Commentaries 14 A & B (Cambridge) (vol. I see Edelstein & Kidd 1972).Google Scholar
Kirk, G. S. (1955) ‘Some problems in Anaximander’, CQ 5 ; repr. in Furley, D. J. & Allen, R. E., edd.Google Scholar
Kirk, G. S. (1970) Studies in Presocratic Philosophy, vol. I (London).Google Scholar
Konstan, D. (1972) ‘Epicurus on “up” & “down” (Letter to Herodotus § 60)’, Phronesis 17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laks, A. & Most, G. W., edd. (1993a) Théophraste: Métaphysique (Paris).Google Scholar
Lapidge, M. (1978) ‘Stoic cosmology’, in Rist (1978).Google Scholar
Lennox, J. (1985) ‘Theophrastus on the limits of teleology’, in Fortenbaugh et al. (1985).Google Scholar
Long, A. A. (1985) ‘The Stoics on world-conflagration and everlasting recurrence’, in Epp (1985).Google Scholar
Long, A. A. & Sedley, D. N., edd. (1987) The Hellenistic Philosophers, 2 vols.: i. Translations of the principal sources with philosophical commentary; ii. Greek and Latin texts with notes and bibliography (Cambridge, various reprints).Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (1979) ‘Providence and the destruction of the universe in early Stoic thought’, in Vermaseren, M. J., ed., Studies in Hellenistic Religions, EPRO 78 (Leiden) ; repr. in Mansfeld, (1989b) study 1.Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (1986) ‘Diogenes Laertius on Stoic philosophy’, in Giannantoni, (1986a) ; repr. in Mansfeld, (1990b).Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (1994a) ‘Epicurus peripateticus’, in Alberti, A., ed., Realtà e ragione, Studi di filosofia antica (Florence).Google Scholar
Mau, J. (1954a) Zum Problem des Infinitesimalen bei den Antiken Atomisten (Berlin).Google Scholar
Mau, J. (1973) ‘Was there a special Epicurean mathematics?’, in Lee, E. N., Mourelatos, A. P. D. & Rorty, R. M., edd., Exegesis and Argument. Studies presented to Gregory Vlastos (Assen).Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. (1986) ‘Therapeutic arguments: Epicurus and Aristotle’, in Schofield & Striker (1986a).Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. (1994) The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in Hellenistic Ethics (Princeton).Google Scholar
O'Brien, D. (1981) Theories of Weight in the Ancient World, vol. I: Democritus, Weight and Size, PhA 37 (Leiden/Paris).Google Scholar
Sambursky, S. (1959) Physics of the Stoics (London).Google Scholar
Sandbach, F. H. (1985) Aristotle and the Stoics, PCPhS suppl. vol. 10 (Cambridge).Google Scholar
Schmid, W. (1936) Epikurs Kritik der platonischen Elementenlehre, Klassisch-philologische Studien 9 (Leipzig).Google Scholar
Schmidt, J. (1990) Lukrez, der Kepos und die Stoiker, Untersuchungen zur Schule Epikurs und zu den Quellen von De rerum natura (Frankfurt am Main).Google Scholar
Sedley, D. N. (1976a) ‘Epicurus and his professional rivals’, in Bollack, & Laks, (1976).Google Scholar
Sedley, D. N. (1976b) ‘Epicurus and the mathematicians of Cyzicus’, CErc 6.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. N. (1983b) ‘Epicurus’ refutation of determinism’, in AA. VV. (1983).Google Scholar
Sedley, D. N. (1998) Lucretius and the Transmission of Greek Wisdom (Cambridge).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sorabji, R. (1980a) Necessity, Cause, and Blame: Perspectives on Aristotle's Theory (Ithaca, N.Y. and London).Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. (1983) Time, Creation and the Continuum (London).Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. (1988) Matter, Space and Motion: Theories in Antiquity and Their Sequel (London).Google Scholar
Todd, R. B. (1978) ‘Monism and immanence: foundations of Stoic physics’, in Rist, (1978b).Google Scholar
Todd, R. B. (1985) ‘The title of Cleomedes' treatise’, Philologus 129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vlastos, G. (1965) ‘Minimal parts in Epicurean atomism’, Isis 56 ; repr. in Graham, (1995).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wasserstein, A. (1978) ‘Epicurean science’, Hermes, 106.Google Scholar
Wehrli, F., ed. (1969a) Straton von Lampsakos, Die Schule des Aristoteles: H. 5, Zweite Auflage (Basle/Stuttgart).Google Scholar
Wolff, M. (1988) ‘Hipparchus and the Stoic theory of motion’, in Barnes & Mignucci (1988a).Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Cosmology
  • Edited by Keimpe Algra, Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands, Jonathan Barnes, Université de Genève, Jaap Mansfeld, Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands, Malcolm Schofield, University of Cambridge
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy
  • Online publication: 28 March 2008
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHOL9780521250283.013
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Cosmology
  • Edited by Keimpe Algra, Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands, Jonathan Barnes, Université de Genève, Jaap Mansfeld, Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands, Malcolm Schofield, University of Cambridge
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy
  • Online publication: 28 March 2008
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHOL9780521250283.013
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Cosmology
  • Edited by Keimpe Algra, Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands, Jonathan Barnes, Université de Genève, Jaap Mansfeld, Universiteit Utrecht, The Netherlands, Malcolm Schofield, University of Cambridge
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy
  • Online publication: 28 March 2008
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHOL9780521250283.013
Available formats
×