Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-m9pkr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T03:14:06.587Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

31 - Logic and philosophical analysis

from 8 - Logic and philosophy: the analytic programme

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Thomas Baldwin
Affiliation:
University of York
Thomas Baldwin
Affiliation:
University of York
Get access

Summary

As we look back to the philosophy of the period from 1914 to 1945, we tend to think of this as a time when ‘analytic philosophy’ flourished, though of course many other types of philosophy also flourished at this time (idealism, phenomenology, pragmatism, etc.). But what was this ‘analytic philosophy’ of which John Wisdom wrote when he opened his book Problems of Mind and Matter (1934) by saying ‘It is to analytic philosophy that this book is intended to be introduction’ (1934: 1)? Wisdom makes a start at answering this question by contrasting analytic philosophy with ‘speculative’ philosophy: the contrast is that speculative philosophy aims to provide new information (for example, by proving the existence of God), whereas analytic philosophy aims only to provide clearer knowledge of facts already known. Much the same contrast is to be found in the ‘statement of policy’ which opens the first issue of the journal Analysis in 1933: papers to be published will be concerned ‘with the elucidation or explanation of facts…the general nature of which is, by common consent, already known; rather than with attempts to establish new kinds of fact about the world’ (Vol. I: 1). As we shall see, the thesis that philosophy does not aim to provide new knowledge is indeed a central theme of many ‘analytic’ philosophers of this period. But first we need to investigate the relevant conception of analysis – ‘philosophical’ analysis.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2003

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ayer, A. J. (1936). Language, Truth and Logic, London: Gollancz. New edn 1971, Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1934). ‘On the Character of Philosophical Problems’, Philosophy of Science 1 Repr. 1967 in Rorty, R. (ed.), The Linguistic Turn, Chicago: Chicago University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, R. (1950). ‘Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology’, Revue Internationale de Philosophie 4.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1781(A), 1787(B)). Kritik der reinen Vernuft, Riga. Trans. 1929 Smith, N. Kemp, Critique of Pure Reason, London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Lewis, C. I. and Langford, C. H. (1932). Symbolic Logic, New York: Appleton Century.Google Scholar
Lewis, C. I. (1929). Mind and World-Order, New York: Charles Scribner’s.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1899). ‘The Nature of Judgement’, Mind 8 Repr. 1993 in Moore, G. E. (ed. Baldwin, T.), Selected Writings, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia Ethica, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rev. edn 1993 (ed. Baldwin, T.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Russell, B. A. W. (1905). ‘On Denoting’, Mind 14 Repr. 1994 in Urquart, A. (ed.), The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell, vol. IV, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Russell, B. A. W. (1914). Our Knowledge of the External World, London: Open Court.Google Scholar
Russell, B. A. W. (1918–19). ‘The Philosophy of Logical Atomism’, The Monist 28, 29. Repr. 1986 in Slater, J. (ed.), The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell, vol. VIII, London: George Allen and Unwin.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, B. A. W. (1959). My Philosophical Development, London: George Allen and Unwin. Repr. 1995, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Wisdom, J. (1934). Problems of Mind and Matter, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1921). ‘Logische-philosophische Abhandlung’, Annalen der Naturphilosophie. Trans. 1922 Ogden, C. K., Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, London: Routledge.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×