Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-n9wrp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-17T00:12:45.196Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

91 - Higher-order interests

from H

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 February 2015

Jon Mandle
Affiliation:
State University of New York, Albany
David A. Reidy
Affiliation:
University of Tennessee, Knoxville
Get access

Summary

Rawls’s theory of justice is supposed to tell us how to fairly assign the beneits and burdens of social cooperation. To answer this question one must irst develop a metric for determining whether and how much different individuals beneit from different sets of social arrangements: a metric of advantage. This metric will serve as a public basis that all members of society can appeal to for evaluating whether some people are being unfairly advantaged over others.

Rawls suggests that because it is to play this public role the metric of advantage must meet some important constraints. One constraint is that it needs to be relatively easy to evaluate how someone is doing according to the metric. For instance, Rawls rejects using simply a person’s happiness as the basis for evaluating advantage because it would be too hard to work out whether one individual was happier than another and thus there would be too much disagreement to reach public consensus on whether there was unfairness.

Another important constraint is that the metric must not be biased toward any particular conception of what makes for a good life. Different members of society have very different views about what it takes to live well but they are all going to be expected to use the same public criterion for evaluating advantage. Thus, the metric must be suitable for a “pluralistic society,” where there is disagreement about the nature of the good life. If we are to show respect for these people with their different views we need to adopt a metric that doesn’t rest on a view of the good life that some people endorse but others reject. This constraint is part of what is required to accept the use of “public reason” in political decision making, a central part of Rawls’s “political liberalism.”

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×