Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-2l2gl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-28T12:35:01.543Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

11 - Wittgenstein

from Part Four - Wittgenstein and After

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2015

Paul Guyer
Affiliation:
Brown University, Rhode Island
Get access

Summary

Wittgenstein and the Tractatus

As were many other areas of Anglo-American philosophy, the field of aesthetics was transformed by the influence of Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951), although in this case the magnitude of Wittgenstein’s influence was far out of proportion to the few words he himself devoted to the field in both the two books that were published at his own instigation and the vast body of writings published after his death. Wittgenstein’s first book, the 1919 Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (as it has always been known in English, although it does not bear that pretentious Latin title in German, in which it is called simply a “Logical-Philosophical Treatise”), strongly influenced the logical positivism of the 1920s Vienna Circle, through which it in turn led several prominent British and American philosophers in the 1930s to argue that aesthetic judgments, like ethical judgments, are not verifiable judgments at all, but purely expressions of personal emotion or preference. This position, as we have already seen, did not constrain the aesthetic theorizing that continued in Britain through the 1930s and in the United States through the 1940s and even beyond in the case of such aestheticians as Langer, Beardsley, and Goodman. Wittgenstein’s second book, however, the 1953 Philosophical Investigations published after his death but largely in the form in which he intended to publish it, radically transformed the practice of aesthetics, indeed leading some of those most influenced by Wittgenstein to bemoan “The Dreariness of Aesthetics” and others to ask “Does Traditional Aesthetics Rest on a Mistake?” The immediate effect of the Investigations was to undermine the focus of aesthetics in the first half of the century on the phenomenon of aesthetic experience, the common denominator in cognitivist, play, and expressionist theories and their syntheses, and to redirect debate to the single question of whether there can be a definition of art that dominated so much aesthetic theory from the 1960s to the 1980s. However, we will see that the most innovative thinkers influenced by Wittgenstein, such as Arthur Danto, Stanley Cavell, and Richard Wollheim, managed to incorporate Wittgensteinian influences into the mainstream of traditional aesthetic thought without simply damming up that stream.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Logisch-Philosophische Abhandlung, Annalen der Naturphilosophie 14 (1921), Hefte 3–4; Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, trans. C.K. Ogden with an introduction by Russell, Bertrand (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1922)Google Scholar
Passmore, John, “The Dreariness of Aesthetics,”Mind 60 (1951): 318–35CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kennick, William E., “Does Traditional Aesthetics Rest on a Mistake?”Mind 67 (1958): 317–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Monk, Ray, Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius (London: Jonathan Cape, 1990)Google Scholar
Janik, Allan and Toulmin, Stephen, Wittgenstein’s Vienna (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1973)Google Scholar
Waugh, Alexander, The House of Wittgenstein: A Family at War (London: Bloomsbury, 2008)Google Scholar
Pears, David, Ludwig Wittgenstein (New York: Viking Press, 1970)Google Scholar
Hacker, P.M.S., Insight and Illusion (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972)Google Scholar
Kenny, Anthony, Wittgenstein (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1973)Google Scholar
Fogelin, Robert J., Wittgenstein (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1976)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koethe, John, The Continuity of Wittgenstein’s Thought (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996)Google Scholar
McGinn, Marie, Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Wittgenstein and the Philosophical Investigations (London: Routledge, 1997)Google Scholar
Williams, Meredith, Wittgenstein, Mind and Meaning: Toward a Social Conception of Mind (London: Routledge, 1999)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blind Obedience: Paradox and Learning in the Later Wittgenstein (London: Routledge, 2010)
Forster, Michael N., Wittgenstein on the Arbitrariness of Grammar (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2004)Google Scholar
Fogelin, Robert J., Taking Wittgenstein at His Word: A Textual Study (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allen, Richard and Turvey, Malcom, Wittgenstein, Theory and the Arts (London: Routledge, 2001)Google Scholar
The Literary Wittgenstein, ed. Gibson, John and Huemer, Wolfgang (London: Routledge, 2004)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Aesthetics and Philosophy ed. Lewis, Peter B. (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2004)
Day, William and Krebs, Victor J., Seeing Wittgenstein Anew (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lüdeking, Karlheinz, Analytische Philosophie der Kunst (Frankfurt am Main: Athenäum Verlag, 1988), pp. 148–51Google Scholar
Ayer, Alfred Jules, Language, Truth, and Logic (London: Gollantz, 1936), second edition (London: Gollantz, 1946), p. 108Google Scholar
Stevenson, Charles L., “Interpretation and Evaluation in Aesthetics,” in Philosophical Analysis, ed. Black, Max, editor (Ithaca:Cornell University Press, 1950), pp. 341–83Google Scholar
Stevenson, Charles L., “On ‘What Is a Poem?’”Philosophical Review 66 (1957): 329–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief, compiled from notes taken by Smythies, Yorick, Rhees, Rush, and Taylor, James, ed. Barrett, Cyril (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1967), p. 17Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Preliminary Studies for the “Philosophical Investigations,” Generally Known as the Blue and Brown Books, with Preface by “R.R.” (Rush Rhees) (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1958)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Philosophical Grammar, ed. Rhees, Rush, trans. Kenny, Anthony (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1974)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Zettel, ed. Anscombe, G.E.M. and Wright, G.H. von, trans. Anscombe, G.E.M. (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1967)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, On Certainty, ed. Anscombe, G.E.M. and Wright, G.H. von, trans. Paul, Denis and Anscombe, G.E.M. (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1969)Google Scholar
Austin, J.L.’s theory of the illocutionary and perlocutionary use of language in How to Do Things with Words (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1962)Google Scholar
Lectures, William James of 1967, “Logic and Conversation,” in his Studies in the Way of Words (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1989)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule, ed. Holtzmann, Steven and Leich, Christopher (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1981)Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul A., Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1982)Google Scholar
Jastrow, J., Fact and Fable in Psychology (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1900)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Wittgenstein
  • Paul Guyer, Brown University, Rhode Island
  • Book: A History of Modern Aesthetics
  • Online publication: 05 June 2015
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781107110342.045
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Wittgenstein
  • Paul Guyer, Brown University, Rhode Island
  • Book: A History of Modern Aesthetics
  • Online publication: 05 June 2015
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781107110342.045
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Wittgenstein
  • Paul Guyer, Brown University, Rhode Island
  • Book: A History of Modern Aesthetics
  • Online publication: 05 June 2015
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781107110342.045
Available formats
×