Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-jwnkl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-13T15:57:53.557Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - The imperative mood and directive force

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 July 2014

Mark Jary
Affiliation:
Roehampton University, London
Mikhail Kissine
Affiliation:
Université Libre de Bruxelles
Get access

Summary

In the last chapter, we identified the imperative as a morpho-syntactic structure whose prototypical function is to perform directives. If imperatives were used only to perform directive speech acts, then one could justifiably claim that what they encode is directive force. Life would be simpler and this book much shorter. However, it has been suggested that there is a range of data that indicates that imperatives have a use beyond directive speech acts. In this and the next chapter, we will consider these claims in some depth. In the next chapter, we will look at cases where an imperative is conjoined with a declarative sentence, giving rise to a conditional interpretation. In this chapter, by contrast, we will be concerned with cases where the imperative is used in a single-clause utterance, but, allegedly, lacks directive force. These include, among others, cases where the imperative is used to express good wishes and give advice.

Whether a given use of an imperative is classified as non-directive will depend on how directive force is defined. Before asking whether the imperative has uses beyond the performance of directive speech acts, then, we need to consider what exactly constitutes a directive speech act: perhaps the view that some of the examples considered in this chapter are non-directive is simply a result of an overly restrictive notion of directive illocutionary force. Section 1 of this chapter will therefore consider possible definitions of directive force, before section 2 takes a close look at the range of uses that have been argued to constitute non-directive uses of the imperative. We will show that, in many cases, whether these uses can indeed be considered non-directive depends on how directive speech acts are defined.

Type
Chapter
Information
Imperatives , pp. 53 - 109
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×