Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-pkt8n Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-06T22:28:12.358Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

21 - How American Legal Academics' Positions on Economic-Efficiency Analysis, Moral Philosophy, and Valid Legal Argument Disserve Law and Society Empirical Research

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 October 2011

Richard S. Markovits
Affiliation:
University of Texas, Austin
Robert W. Gordon
Affiliation:
Yale University, Connecticut
Morton J. Horwitz
Affiliation:
Harvard University, Massachusetts
Get access

Summary

Lawrence Friedman's work is certainly not atheoretical. However, the hallmark both of his scholarship and of the law and society movement to whose development he has made such a great contribution is the recognition that for a theory to be valuable it must explain or predict specified facts.

American law professors have long recognized that success as a transaction lawyer or litigator often depends at least as much on knowledge of the facts of the situation or case as on doctrinal knowledge or skill in legal argument. However, until fairly recently, these academics have done little empirical research themselves; instead they have made scholarly choices that implicitly assume that such research has little bearing on the academic questions their research investigates. Yet over the past two decades, American law professors have revised upward their assessment of the contribution that law and society empirical research can make to legal scholarship. This reassessment is manifest in (1) a vast increase in the amount of such empirical research that American law faculties conduct, (2) the fact that the plenary session of the 2006 Annual Meeting of the Association of American Law Schools was devoted to “Empirical Research: What Should We Study and How Should We Study It?” and (3) the decision of the Cornell, New York University, and University of Texas law schools to sponsor a series of annual conferences on empirical legal studies.

Type
Chapter
Information
Law, Society, and History
Themes in the Legal Sociology and Legal History of Lawrence M. Friedman
, pp. 395 - 430
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adler, Matthew and Posner, Eric (2001). Implementing Cost-Benefit Analysis When Preferences Are Distorted, in Adler, Matthew and Posner, Eric, eds., Cost-Benefit Analysis: Economic, Legal, and Philosophical Perspectives. Chicago: University of Chicago Press Journals.Google Scholar
Baker, Lynn and Dinkin, Samuel (1997). The Senate: An Institution Whose Time Has Gone, 13 J. L. & Pol. 21.Google Scholar
Bobbitt, Philip (1982). Constitutional Fate. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bobbitt, Philip. (1992). Constitutional Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, Felix (1935). Transcendental Nonsense and the Functional Approach, 35 Cal. L. Rev. 809.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, Kristin A. (2008). “Let the Government Become Their Guardians”: Administrative Law, Social Provision, and the Legal Construction of the Family in the Early Nineteenth Century (unpublished manuscript).
(Dauber), Landis, Michele (1998). “Let Me Next Time Be ‘Tried by Fire’”: Disaster Relief and the Origins of the American Welfare State 1789–1874, 92 Nw. U.L. Rev. 967.Google Scholar
(Dauber) Landis, Michele. (2005). The Sympathetic State, 23 L. & Hist. Rev. 245.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald (1978). Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. (1986). Law's Empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Franck, Thomas M. (1990). The Power of Legitimacy among Nations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Green, Leslie (2003). Legal Positivism, in Bullock, Penelope A. and Raz, Joseph, eds., Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (an online publication), citing H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law 116 (2nd ed., 1994). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. (1961). The Concept of Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hilbink, Lisa (2007). Judges beyond Politics in Democracy and Dictatorship: Lessons From Chile. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (2001). Fairness versus Welfare, 114 Harv. L. Rev. 961.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levinson, Sanford (2006). Our Undemocratic Constitution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lipsey, R. G. and Lancaster, Kelvin (1956). The General Theory of Second Best, 24 Rev. Econ. Stud. 11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Markovits, Daniel (2004). Contract and Collaboration, 113 Yale L.J. 1417.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Markovits, Richard S. (1998). Matters of Principle: Legitimate Legal Argument and Constitutional Interpretation. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Markovits, Richard S.. (2004). Learning from the Foreigners: A Response to Professor Levinson's and Justice Scalia's Professional Moral Parochialism, 39 Tex. J. of Int'l Law367.Google Scholar
Markovits, Richard S.. (2006). Liberalism and Tort Law: On the Content of the Corrective-Justice-Securing Tort Law of a Liberal, Rights-Based Society, 2006 Ill. L. Rev243.Google Scholar
Markovits, Richard S.. (2008). Truth or Economics: On the Definition, Prediction, and Relevance of Economic Efficiency. New Haven: Yale University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mertz, Elizabeth (2007). The Language of Law School: Learning to Think Like a Lawyer. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quinn, Michael Sean (1999). Argument and Authority in Common Law Advocacy and Adjudication: An Irreducible Pluralism of Principles, 74 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 655.Google Scholar
Radin, Max. (1930). Statutory Interpretation, 43 Harv. L. Rev. 863.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, Joseph (1979). The Authority of Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Segal, Jeffrey and Spaeth, Harold (1993). The Supreme Court and the Attitudinal Model. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Tyler, Tom R. and Mitchell, Gregory (1994). Legitimacy and the Empowerment of Discretionary Legal Authority: The United States Supreme Court and Abortion Rights, 43 Duke L.J.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×