Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-vsgnj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-19T12:14:03.850Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

Bibliography

Colin Bird
Affiliation:
University of Virginia
Get access
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anderson, E. (1999), “What is the Point of Equality?”, Ethics 109/2, pp. 287–337CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aristotle, (1981), The Politics (London: Penguin)Google Scholar
Arrow, Kenneth (1963), Social Choice and Individual Values (New Haven: Yale University Press)Google Scholar
Atiyah, P. S. (1995), Law and Modern Society (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Auden, W. H. (1991), Collected Poems, ed. Mendelson, Edward (London: Faber)Google Scholar
Beitz, Charles (1989), Political Equality: An Essay in Democratic Theory (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Beitz, Charles (1999), Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Bentham, Jeremy (2002), Rights, Representation, and Reform: Nonsense upon Stilts and Other Writings on the French Revolution, eds. Schofield, Philip, Pease-Watkin, Catherine, and Blamires, Cyprian (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Beran, H. (1987), The Consent Theory of Political Obligation (London: Croom Helm)Google Scholar
Berlin, Isaiah (1969), Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Bird, Colin (1996), “Mutual Respect and Neutral Justification,”Ethics 7/1, pp. 62–96CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, Colin (1999), The Myth of Liberal Individualism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Bird, Colin (2000), “The Possibility of Self-Government,”American Political Science Review 94/2, pp. 563–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blake, Michael (2001), “Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy,”Philosophy and Public Affairs 30/3, pp. 257–96CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carter, Ian (1999), A Measure of Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chan, Joseph (2000), “Legitimacy, Unanimity and Perfectionism,”Philosophy and Public Affairs 29/1, pp. 5–43CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christiano, Thomas (1996), The Rule of the Many (Boulder, CO: Westview)Google Scholar
Cohen, Gerald (2000), If You're an Egalitarian, How Come You're So Rich? (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Cohen, Joshua (1989), “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy,” in Goodin, Robert and Hamlin, Alan (eds.), The Good Polity (Oxford: Blackwell)Google Scholar
Davidson, Arnold (1997) (ed.), Foucault and his Interlocutors (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)Google Scholar
Delgado, Richard, and Stefancic, Jean (2001) (eds.), Critical Race Theory: An Introduction (New York: New York University Press)Google Scholar
Dewey, John (1939), Intelligence in the Modern World: John Dewey's Philisophy, ed. Ratner, Joseph (New York: Modern Library)Google Scholar
Downs, Anthony (1957), An Economic Theory of Democracy (New York: Harper)Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. (1985), “Liberalism,” in A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), pp. 181–205Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. (1986), Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Edgeworth, F. Y. (1967), Mathematical Psychics: An Essay on the Application of Mathematics to the Moral Sciences (New York: A. M. Kelley)Google Scholar
Elshtain, Jean Bethke (1981), Public Man, Private Woman (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Elshtain, Jean Bethke (2004), “But Was It Just? Reflections on the Iraq War,” in Nexus: A Journal of Opinion 9, pp. 1–9. Available online at <http://www.nexusjournal.org/separate%20pdf/Volume9/ElshtainArticle.pdf>Google Scholar
Engels, Frederick (1958), The Condition of the Working Class in England, ed. Henderson, W. O., and Chaloner, W. H. (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Finnis, John (1980), Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Flyvberg, Bent (1998), Rationality and Power: Democracy in Practice (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)Google Scholar
Foucault, Michel (1984), The Foucault Reader, ed. Rabinow, Paul (New York: Pantheon)Google Scholar
Frank, Robert (1985), Choosing the Right Pond (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry (1988), “Equality as a Moral Ideal,” in Harry Frankfurt, The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 134–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freeman, Samuel (2001), “Illiberal Libertarianism: Why Libertarianism is Not a Liberal View,”Philosophy and Public Affairs 30/2, pp. 105–51Google Scholar
Gallie, W. B. (1956), “Essentially Contested Concepts,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 56, pp. 167–220CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galston, William (2002), Liberal Pluralism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gans, C. (1992), Philosophical Anarchism and Political Disobedience (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gauthier, David (1986), Morals by Agreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Geuss, Raymond (1981), The Idea of a Critical Theory: Habermas and the Frankfurt School (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Geuss, Raymond (2001), History and Illusion in Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Geuss, Raymond (2005), Outside Ethics (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Green, L. (1990), The Authority of the State (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Grotius, Hugo (1901), The Rights of War and Peace, trans. Campbell, A. C. (Westport: Hyperion)Google Scholar
Gutmann, Amy, and Thompson, Dennis (1996), Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Haksar, Vinit (1979), Equality, Liberty and Perfectionism (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Hardin, Russell (1993), “Public Choice versus Democracy,” in Copp, David, Hampton, Jean, and Roemer, John (eds.), The Idea of Democracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. (1981), Moral Thinking: its Levels, Methods and Point (Oxford: Oxford University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrison, Edward (1987), Darkness at Night: A Riddle of the Universe (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. (1975), “Rawls on Liberty and Its Priority,” in Daniels, Norman (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York: Basic), pp. 249–52Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. (1997), The Concept of Law, 2nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich (1937), “Economics and Knowledge,” Economica 4, pp. 33–54Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich (1976), Law, Legislation and Liberty, II: The Mirage of Social Justice (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)Google Scholar
Held, David (1980), Introduction to Critical Theory: Horkheimer to Habermas (Berkeley: University of California Press)Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas (1994), Leviathan, ed. Curley, E. (Indianapolis: Hackett)Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas (1998), De Cive, ed. and trans. Tuck, Richard and Silverthorne, Michael (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Holmes, Robert (1989), On War and Morality (Princeton: Princeton University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holmes, Stephen, and Sunstein, Cass (1999), The Cost of Rights (New York: Norton)Google Scholar
Honig, Bonnie (1993), Political Theory and the Displacement of Politics (Ithaca: Cornell University Press)Google Scholar
Horkheimer, Max (1972), Critical Theory, trans. O'Connell, Matthew et al. (New York: Herder and Herder)Google Scholar
Horton, J. (1992), Political Obligation (Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, David (1969), A Treatise of Human Nature (London: Penguin)Google Scholar
Hume, David (1985), “On the Original Contract,” in Miller, Eugene (ed.), Essays Moral, Political and Literary (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund)Google Scholar
Hurka, Thomas (1993), Perfectionism (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Jevons, W. S. (1988), The Theory of Political Economy (London: Macmillan)Google Scholar
Joad, C. E. M. (1939), Why War? (London: Penguin)Google Scholar
Johnston, David (1994), The Idea of a Liberal Theory (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1991), Political Writings, ed. Reiss, Hans, trans. Nisbett, H. B. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1993), Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Ellington, James (Indianapolis: Hackett)Google Scholar
Kairys, David (1990) (ed.), The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique (New York: Pantheon)
Kekes, John (1997), Against Liberalism (Ithaca: Cornell University Press)Google Scholar
King, Martin Luther (1989), “Letter from Birmingham Jail,” in Harris, Paul, Civil Disobedience (Lanham: University Press of America)Google Scholar
Klosko, George (1992), The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield)Google Scholar
Klosko, George (2005), Political Obligations (Oxford: Oxford University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kymlicka, Will (1989), Liberalism, Community and Culture (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Kymlicka, Will (1995), Multicultural Citizenship (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Kymlicka, Will (2002), Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Lane, Robert E. (2000), The Loss of Happiness in the Market Democracies (New Haven: Yale University Press)Google Scholar
Larmore, Charles (1987), Patterns of Moral Complexity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Larmore, Charles (1996), The Morals of Modernity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Larmore, Charles (1999), “The Moral Basis of Political Liberalism,” Journal of Philosophy 96/12, pp. 599–612CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lively, Jack (1975), Democracy (Oxford: Blackwell)Google Scholar
Locke, John (1993), The Political Writings of John Locke, ed. Wootton, David (New York: Mentor)Google Scholar
McBride, William (1972), “Social Theory sub specie aeternitatis,” review of J. Rawls'sA Theory of Justice, Yale Law Journal 81/5 (April 1972), pp. 980–1003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair (1984), After Virtue (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press)Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff (2004), “The Ethics of Killing in War,”Ethics 114, pp. 693–733CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacNamara, Robert (2005), “Apocalypse Soon,” in Foreign Policy (May/June 2005), pp. 28–36Google Scholar
Manin, Bernard (1997), The Principles of Representative Government (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mannheim, Karl (1985), Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge, trans. Wirth, Louis and Shils, Edward (San Diego: Harcourt Brace)Google Scholar
Marx, Karl (1978), The Marx–Engels Reader, ed. Tucker, Robert (New York: Norton)Google Scholar
Mearsheimer, John (2001), The Tragedy of Great Power Politics (New York: Norton)Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart (1972), Utilitarianism, On Liberty, and Considerations on Representative Government (London: Everyman)Google Scholar
Miller, David (1995), On Nationality (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Miller, Richard (1998), “Cosmopolitan Respect and Patriotic Concern,”Philosophy and Public Affairs 27/3, pp. 202–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milner, Murray (2004), Freaks, Geeks, and Cool Kids: American Teenagers and the Culture of Consumption (London: Routledge)Google Scholar
Moellendorf, Darrell (2002), Cosmopolitan Justice (Boulder, CO: Westview)Google Scholar
Murphy, Liam, and Nagel, Thomas (2002), The Myth of Ownership (Oxford: Oxford University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas (2004), “The Problem of Global Justice,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 33/2, pp. 113–47Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert (1974), Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York: Basic Books)Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha (2006), The Frontiers of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Okin, Susan (1989), Justice, Gender and the Family (New York: Basic Books)Google Scholar
Oldfield, A. (1990), Citizenship and Community: Civic Republicanism and the Modern World (London: Routledge)Google Scholar
Paley, William (1828), The Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy (Boston: Whitaker)Google Scholar
Pateman, Carole (1970), Participation and Democratic Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pateman, Carole (1983), “Feminist Criticisms of the Public/Private Dichotomy,” in Benn, Stanley and Gaus, Gerald (eds.), Public and Private in Social Life (London: Croom Helm)Google Scholar
Penn, William (1682), A Frame of Government of Pennsylvania, excerpts online at <http://www.constitution.org/bcp/frampenn.htm>Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip (1999), Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government (Oxford: Oxford University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plato (1992), The Republic, ed. Grube, G. M. A. and Reeve, C. D. C. (Indianapolis: Hackett)Google Scholar
Pogge, Thomas (1994), “An Egalitarian Law of Peoples,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 23/3, pp. 195–225CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pogge, Thomas (2002), World Poverty and Human Rights (Cambridge: Polity)Google Scholar
Popper, Karl (1966), The Open Society and its Enemies (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Przworski, Adam (1991), Democracy and the Market (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John (1993), Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press)Google Scholar
Rawls, John (1999a), A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Rawls, John (1999b), The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Rawls, John (2001), Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph (1986), The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Riker, William (1988), Liberalism against Populism (Prospect Heights: Waveland)Google Scholar
Rosen, Michael (1996), On Voluntary Servitude (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (1987), The Basic Political Writings, ed. and trans. Cress, Donald (Indianapolis: Hackett)Google Scholar
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (1990), “The State of War,” in Roosevelt, Grace (ed.), Reading Rousseau in the Nuclear Age (Philadelphia: Temple University Press), pp. 185–98Google Scholar
Sandel, Michael (1982), Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Sandel, Michael (1996), Democracy's Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Scanlon, Thomas (1998), What We Owe Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Schumpeter, Joseph (1956), Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy (New York: Harper)Google Scholar
Schwartz, Barry (2004), The Paradox of Choice: Why More is Less (New York: ECCO)Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya (2000), Development as Freedom (New York: Anchor)Google Scholar
Sher, George (1997), Beyond Neutrality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sidwick, Henry (1981), The Methods of Ethics (Indianapolis: Hackett)Google Scholar
Simmons, A. John (1979), Moral Principles and Political Obligation (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Simmons, A. John (2001), Justification and Legitimacy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Singer, Peter (1972), “Famine, Affluence and Morality,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 1/3, pp. 229–43Google Scholar
Singer, Peter (1993), Practical Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Singer, Peter (2002), One World (New Haven: Yale University Press)Google Scholar
Skinner, Quentin (1998), Liberty before Liberalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Skinner, Quentin (2001), “A Third Concept of Liberty,” in Proceedings of the British Academy 117, pp. 237–69Google Scholar
Stone, Julius (1984), Visions of World Order: Between State Power and Human Justice (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press)Google Scholar
Taurek, John (1977), “Should the Numbers Count?Philosophy and Public Affairs 6/4, pp. 293–316Google ScholarPubMed
Tawney, Richard (1964), Equality (London: George Allen and Unwin)Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles (1985), “Atomism,” in Charles Taylor, Philosophical Papers, II (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 197–210Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles (1994), Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition, ed. Gutmann, Amy (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles (1995), “Cross-Purposes: The Liberal-Communitarian Debate,” in Philosophical Arguments (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), ch. 10Google Scholar
Unger, Roberto (1986), The Critical Legal Studies Movement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Vattel, E. (1844), Law of Nations (Philadelphia: T. and J. V. Johnson)Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy (1988), “Locke: Toleration and the Rationality of Persecution,” in Mendus, Susan (ed.), Justifying Toleration: Philosophical and Historical Perspectives (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 61–86CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wall, Steven (1998), Liberalism, Perfectionism and Restraint (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walzer, Michael (1973), “Political Action: The Problem of Dirty Hands,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 2/2, pp. 160–80Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael (1977), Just and Unjust Wars (New York: Basic)Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael (1983), Spheres of Justice (New York: Basic)Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael (1987), Interpretation and Social Criticism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Weldon, T. D. (1947), States and Morals (New York: Whittlesley House)Google Scholar
Williams, B. A. O. (1985), Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Wolff, Robert (1970), In Defense of Anarchism (New York: Harper)Google Scholar
Yates, Michael (2003), Naming the System: Inequality and Work in the Global Economy (New York: Monthly Review Press)Google Scholar
Young, Iris (1990), Justice and the Politics of Difference (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Young, Iris (1997), Intersecting Voices (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Anderson, E. (1999), “What is the Point of Equality?”, Ethics 109/2, pp. 287–337CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aristotle, (1981), The Politics (London: Penguin)Google Scholar
Arrow, Kenneth (1963), Social Choice and Individual Values (New Haven: Yale University Press)Google Scholar
Atiyah, P. S. (1995), Law and Modern Society (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Auden, W. H. (1991), Collected Poems, ed. Mendelson, Edward (London: Faber)Google Scholar
Beitz, Charles (1989), Political Equality: An Essay in Democratic Theory (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Beitz, Charles (1999), Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Bentham, Jeremy (2002), Rights, Representation, and Reform: Nonsense upon Stilts and Other Writings on the French Revolution, eds. Schofield, Philip, Pease-Watkin, Catherine, and Blamires, Cyprian (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Beran, H. (1987), The Consent Theory of Political Obligation (London: Croom Helm)Google Scholar
Berlin, Isaiah (1969), Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Bird, Colin (1996), “Mutual Respect and Neutral Justification,”Ethics 7/1, pp. 62–96CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, Colin (1999), The Myth of Liberal Individualism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Bird, Colin (2000), “The Possibility of Self-Government,”American Political Science Review 94/2, pp. 563–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blake, Michael (2001), “Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy,”Philosophy and Public Affairs 30/3, pp. 257–96CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carter, Ian (1999), A Measure of Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chan, Joseph (2000), “Legitimacy, Unanimity and Perfectionism,”Philosophy and Public Affairs 29/1, pp. 5–43CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christiano, Thomas (1996), The Rule of the Many (Boulder, CO: Westview)Google Scholar
Cohen, Gerald (2000), If You're an Egalitarian, How Come You're So Rich? (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Cohen, Joshua (1989), “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy,” in Goodin, Robert and Hamlin, Alan (eds.), The Good Polity (Oxford: Blackwell)Google Scholar
Davidson, Arnold (1997) (ed.), Foucault and his Interlocutors (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)Google Scholar
Delgado, Richard, and Stefancic, Jean (2001) (eds.), Critical Race Theory: An Introduction (New York: New York University Press)Google Scholar
Dewey, John (1939), Intelligence in the Modern World: John Dewey's Philisophy, ed. Ratner, Joseph (New York: Modern Library)Google Scholar
Downs, Anthony (1957), An Economic Theory of Democracy (New York: Harper)Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. (1985), “Liberalism,” in A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), pp. 181–205Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. (1986), Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Edgeworth, F. Y. (1967), Mathematical Psychics: An Essay on the Application of Mathematics to the Moral Sciences (New York: A. M. Kelley)Google Scholar
Elshtain, Jean Bethke (1981), Public Man, Private Woman (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Elshtain, Jean Bethke (2004), “But Was It Just? Reflections on the Iraq War,” in Nexus: A Journal of Opinion 9, pp. 1–9. Available online at <http://www.nexusjournal.org/separate%20pdf/Volume9/ElshtainArticle.pdf>Google Scholar
Engels, Frederick (1958), The Condition of the Working Class in England, ed. Henderson, W. O., and Chaloner, W. H. (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Finnis, John (1980), Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Flyvberg, Bent (1998), Rationality and Power: Democracy in Practice (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)Google Scholar
Foucault, Michel (1984), The Foucault Reader, ed. Rabinow, Paul (New York: Pantheon)Google Scholar
Frank, Robert (1985), Choosing the Right Pond (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry (1988), “Equality as a Moral Ideal,” in Harry Frankfurt, The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 134–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freeman, Samuel (2001), “Illiberal Libertarianism: Why Libertarianism is Not a Liberal View,”Philosophy and Public Affairs 30/2, pp. 105–51Google Scholar
Gallie, W. B. (1956), “Essentially Contested Concepts,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 56, pp. 167–220CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galston, William (2002), Liberal Pluralism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gans, C. (1992), Philosophical Anarchism and Political Disobedience (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gauthier, David (1986), Morals by Agreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Geuss, Raymond (1981), The Idea of a Critical Theory: Habermas and the Frankfurt School (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Geuss, Raymond (2001), History and Illusion in Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Geuss, Raymond (2005), Outside Ethics (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Green, L. (1990), The Authority of the State (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Grotius, Hugo (1901), The Rights of War and Peace, trans. Campbell, A. C. (Westport: Hyperion)Google Scholar
Gutmann, Amy, and Thompson, Dennis (1996), Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Haksar, Vinit (1979), Equality, Liberty and Perfectionism (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Hardin, Russell (1993), “Public Choice versus Democracy,” in Copp, David, Hampton, Jean, and Roemer, John (eds.), The Idea of Democracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. (1981), Moral Thinking: its Levels, Methods and Point (Oxford: Oxford University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrison, Edward (1987), Darkness at Night: A Riddle of the Universe (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. (1975), “Rawls on Liberty and Its Priority,” in Daniels, Norman (ed.), Reading Rawls (New York: Basic), pp. 249–52Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. (1997), The Concept of Law, 2nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich (1937), “Economics and Knowledge,” Economica 4, pp. 33–54Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich (1976), Law, Legislation and Liberty, II: The Mirage of Social Justice (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)Google Scholar
Held, David (1980), Introduction to Critical Theory: Horkheimer to Habermas (Berkeley: University of California Press)Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas (1994), Leviathan, ed. Curley, E. (Indianapolis: Hackett)Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas (1998), De Cive, ed. and trans. Tuck, Richard and Silverthorne, Michael (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Holmes, Robert (1989), On War and Morality (Princeton: Princeton University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holmes, Stephen, and Sunstein, Cass (1999), The Cost of Rights (New York: Norton)Google Scholar
Honig, Bonnie (1993), Political Theory and the Displacement of Politics (Ithaca: Cornell University Press)Google Scholar
Horkheimer, Max (1972), Critical Theory, trans. O'Connell, Matthew et al. (New York: Herder and Herder)Google Scholar
Horton, J. (1992), Political Obligation (Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, David (1969), A Treatise of Human Nature (London: Penguin)Google Scholar
Hume, David (1985), “On the Original Contract,” in Miller, Eugene (ed.), Essays Moral, Political and Literary (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund)Google Scholar
Hurka, Thomas (1993), Perfectionism (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Jevons, W. S. (1988), The Theory of Political Economy (London: Macmillan)Google Scholar
Joad, C. E. M. (1939), Why War? (London: Penguin)Google Scholar
Johnston, David (1994), The Idea of a Liberal Theory (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1991), Political Writings, ed. Reiss, Hans, trans. Nisbett, H. B. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1993), Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Ellington, James (Indianapolis: Hackett)Google Scholar
Kairys, David (1990) (ed.), The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique (New York: Pantheon)
Kekes, John (1997), Against Liberalism (Ithaca: Cornell University Press)Google Scholar
King, Martin Luther (1989), “Letter from Birmingham Jail,” in Harris, Paul, Civil Disobedience (Lanham: University Press of America)Google Scholar
Klosko, George (1992), The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield)Google Scholar
Klosko, George (2005), Political Obligations (Oxford: Oxford University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kymlicka, Will (1989), Liberalism, Community and Culture (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Kymlicka, Will (1995), Multicultural Citizenship (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Kymlicka, Will (2002), Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Lane, Robert E. (2000), The Loss of Happiness in the Market Democracies (New Haven: Yale University Press)Google Scholar
Larmore, Charles (1987), Patterns of Moral Complexity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Larmore, Charles (1996), The Morals of Modernity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Larmore, Charles (1999), “The Moral Basis of Political Liberalism,” Journal of Philosophy 96/12, pp. 599–612CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lively, Jack (1975), Democracy (Oxford: Blackwell)Google Scholar
Locke, John (1993), The Political Writings of John Locke, ed. Wootton, David (New York: Mentor)Google Scholar
McBride, William (1972), “Social Theory sub specie aeternitatis,” review of J. Rawls'sA Theory of Justice, Yale Law Journal 81/5 (April 1972), pp. 980–1003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair (1984), After Virtue (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press)Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff (2004), “The Ethics of Killing in War,”Ethics 114, pp. 693–733CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacNamara, Robert (2005), “Apocalypse Soon,” in Foreign Policy (May/June 2005), pp. 28–36Google Scholar
Manin, Bernard (1997), The Principles of Representative Government (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mannheim, Karl (1985), Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge, trans. Wirth, Louis and Shils, Edward (San Diego: Harcourt Brace)Google Scholar
Marx, Karl (1978), The Marx–Engels Reader, ed. Tucker, Robert (New York: Norton)Google Scholar
Mearsheimer, John (2001), The Tragedy of Great Power Politics (New York: Norton)Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart (1972), Utilitarianism, On Liberty, and Considerations on Representative Government (London: Everyman)Google Scholar
Miller, David (1995), On Nationality (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Miller, Richard (1998), “Cosmopolitan Respect and Patriotic Concern,”Philosophy and Public Affairs 27/3, pp. 202–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milner, Murray (2004), Freaks, Geeks, and Cool Kids: American Teenagers and the Culture of Consumption (London: Routledge)Google Scholar
Moellendorf, Darrell (2002), Cosmopolitan Justice (Boulder, CO: Westview)Google Scholar
Murphy, Liam, and Nagel, Thomas (2002), The Myth of Ownership (Oxford: Oxford University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas (2004), “The Problem of Global Justice,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 33/2, pp. 113–47Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert (1974), Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York: Basic Books)Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha (2006), The Frontiers of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Okin, Susan (1989), Justice, Gender and the Family (New York: Basic Books)Google Scholar
Oldfield, A. (1990), Citizenship and Community: Civic Republicanism and the Modern World (London: Routledge)Google Scholar
Paley, William (1828), The Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy (Boston: Whitaker)Google Scholar
Pateman, Carole (1970), Participation and Democratic Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pateman, Carole (1983), “Feminist Criticisms of the Public/Private Dichotomy,” in Benn, Stanley and Gaus, Gerald (eds.), Public and Private in Social Life (London: Croom Helm)Google Scholar
Penn, William (1682), A Frame of Government of Pennsylvania, excerpts online at <http://www.constitution.org/bcp/frampenn.htm>Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip (1999), Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government (Oxford: Oxford University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plato (1992), The Republic, ed. Grube, G. M. A. and Reeve, C. D. C. (Indianapolis: Hackett)Google Scholar
Pogge, Thomas (1994), “An Egalitarian Law of Peoples,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 23/3, pp. 195–225CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pogge, Thomas (2002), World Poverty and Human Rights (Cambridge: Polity)Google Scholar
Popper, Karl (1966), The Open Society and its Enemies (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Przworski, Adam (1991), Democracy and the Market (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John (1993), Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press)Google Scholar
Rawls, John (1999a), A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Rawls, John (1999b), The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Rawls, John (2001), Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph (1986), The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press)Google Scholar
Riker, William (1988), Liberalism against Populism (Prospect Heights: Waveland)Google Scholar
Rosen, Michael (1996), On Voluntary Servitude (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (1987), The Basic Political Writings, ed. and trans. Cress, Donald (Indianapolis: Hackett)Google Scholar
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (1990), “The State of War,” in Roosevelt, Grace (ed.), Reading Rousseau in the Nuclear Age (Philadelphia: Temple University Press), pp. 185–98Google Scholar
Sandel, Michael (1982), Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Sandel, Michael (1996), Democracy's Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Scanlon, Thomas (1998), What We Owe Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Schumpeter, Joseph (1956), Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy (New York: Harper)Google Scholar
Schwartz, Barry (2004), The Paradox of Choice: Why More is Less (New York: ECCO)Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya (2000), Development as Freedom (New York: Anchor)Google Scholar
Sher, George (1997), Beyond Neutrality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sidwick, Henry (1981), The Methods of Ethics (Indianapolis: Hackett)Google Scholar
Simmons, A. John (1979), Moral Principles and Political Obligation (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Simmons, A. John (2001), Justification and Legitimacy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Singer, Peter (1972), “Famine, Affluence and Morality,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 1/3, pp. 229–43Google Scholar
Singer, Peter (1993), Practical Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Singer, Peter (2002), One World (New Haven: Yale University Press)Google Scholar
Skinner, Quentin (1998), Liberty before Liberalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Skinner, Quentin (2001), “A Third Concept of Liberty,” in Proceedings of the British Academy 117, pp. 237–69Google Scholar
Stone, Julius (1984), Visions of World Order: Between State Power and Human Justice (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press)Google Scholar
Taurek, John (1977), “Should the Numbers Count?Philosophy and Public Affairs 6/4, pp. 293–316Google ScholarPubMed
Tawney, Richard (1964), Equality (London: George Allen and Unwin)Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles (1985), “Atomism,” in Charles Taylor, Philosophical Papers, II (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 197–210Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles (1994), Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition, ed. Gutmann, Amy (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles (1995), “Cross-Purposes: The Liberal-Communitarian Debate,” in Philosophical Arguments (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), ch. 10Google Scholar
Unger, Roberto (1986), The Critical Legal Studies Movement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Vattel, E. (1844), Law of Nations (Philadelphia: T. and J. V. Johnson)Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy (1988), “Locke: Toleration and the Rationality of Persecution,” in Mendus, Susan (ed.), Justifying Toleration: Philosophical and Historical Perspectives (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 61–86CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wall, Steven (1998), Liberalism, Perfectionism and Restraint (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walzer, Michael (1973), “Political Action: The Problem of Dirty Hands,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 2/2, pp. 160–80Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael (1977), Just and Unjust Wars (New York: Basic)Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael (1983), Spheres of Justice (New York: Basic)Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael (1987), Interpretation and Social Criticism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Weldon, T. D. (1947), States and Morals (New York: Whittlesley House)Google Scholar
Williams, B. A. O. (1985), Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
Wolff, Robert (1970), In Defense of Anarchism (New York: Harper)Google Scholar
Yates, Michael (2003), Naming the System: Inequality and Work in the Global Economy (New York: Monthly Review Press)Google Scholar
Young, Iris (1990), Justice and the Politics of Difference (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar
Young, Iris (1997), Intersecting Voices (Princeton: Princeton University Press)Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Colin Bird, University of Virginia
  • Book: An Introduction to Political Philosophy
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511801273.015
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Colin Bird, University of Virginia
  • Book: An Introduction to Political Philosophy
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511801273.015
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Colin Bird, University of Virginia
  • Book: An Introduction to Political Philosophy
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511801273.015
Available formats
×