Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-vfjqv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T11:55:00.783Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

9 - Wolterstorff's Realism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 July 2009

Lambert Zuidervaart
Affiliation:
Institute for Christian Studies, Toronto
Get access

Summary

We cannot evaluate the action of fictional projection by reference to the truth and falsehood of what was claimed. For nothing was claimed.

Nicholas Wolterstorff

Nicholas Wolterstorff's Works and Worlds of Art challenges modern aesthetic emphases on expressive artistic creation (genius) and disinterested aesthetic experience (taste). His alternative is to construe works of art as instruments and objects of action, and to portray representation (mimesis) as an action that is “pervasive and fundamental in the arts” (p. xv). This alternative implies a propositionally inflected and realist correspondence theory of truth. Unlike Goodman, Wolterstorff retains propositions as the locus of truth, and he endorses correspondence as the primary criterion of truth. But unlike the propositionist T. M. Greene, he denies that the propositional content of artworks can be substantially true or false. Central to Wolterstorff's account of art's cognitive functions is the “action” of fictive world projection: presenting “states of affairs” for people “to reflect on, to ponder over, to explore the implications of, to conduct strandwise extrapolation on” (p. 233). This presenting can be either direct (“introducing”) or indirect (“posing of”), and it can be true to actuality or true to a person's or community's beliefs, including the artist's own vision. It does not appear as if the presenting, or the work itself, can be true about something, however. Hence for Wolterstorff artworks cannot be substantially true or false: fictive world projection involves correspondence without truth. That, at least, is the interpretation I propose.

Type
Chapter
Information
Artistic Truth
Aesthetics, Discourse, and Imaginative Disclosure
, pp. 182 - 202
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2004

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×