Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-v5vhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-03T15:46:52.774Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 May 2017

Veli Mitova
Affiliation:
University of Johannesburg
Get access
Type
Chapter
Information
Believable Evidence , pp. 254 - 263
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2017

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Achinstein, P. (2010). Evidence, Explanation, and Realism: Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Adler, J. (2002). Belief’s Own Ethics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alston, W. P. (1989). Epistemic Justification. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Alston, W. P. (2005). Beyond Justification. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Alvarez, M. (2010). Kinds of Reasons: An Essay in the Philosophy of Action. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. (1976). Intention (2nd edition, repr.). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Audi, R. (1986). Acting for Reasons. The Philosophical Review, 95(4), 511–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baehr, J. (2011). The Inquiring Mind: On Intellectual Virtues and Virtue Epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baehr, J. (2014). Knowledge Need Not Be Virtuously Motivated. In Turri, T., Steup, M., & Sosa, E. (Eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 2nd Edition (pp. 133–9). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bayes, T. (1764). An Essay Toward Solving a Problem in the Doctrine of Chances. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, 53, 370418.Google Scholar
Blackburn, S. (1998). Ruling Passions. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boghossian, P. (2003). The Normativity of Content. Philosophical Issues, 13, Philosophy of Mind, 3145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
BonJour, L. (1985). The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
BonJour, L. & Sosa, E. (2003). Epistemic Justification: Internalism vs. Externalism, Foundations vs. Virtues. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Booth, A. R. (2014). Two Reasons Why Epistemic Reasons Are Not Object-Given Reasons. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 89(1), 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brady, M. (2006). Appropriate Attitudes and the Value Problem. American Philosophical Quarterly, 43(1), 91–9.Google Scholar
Bratman, M. (1984). Two Faces of Intention. Philosophical Review, 93, 375405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bratman, M. (1991). Cognitivism about Practical Reason. Ethics, 102(1), 117–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brink, D. O. (1989). Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, J. (1997). Reasons and Motivation. Aristotelian Society, Suppl., 77, 131–46.Google Scholar
Broome, J. (2000). Normative Requirements. In Dancy, J. (Ed.), Normativity (pp. 7899). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Broome, J. (2013). Rationality through Reasoning. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brueckner, A. (2008). Perceptual Evidence. In Smith, Q. (Ed.), Epistemology: New Essays (pp. 105–19). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Burge, T. (2003). Perceptual Entitlement. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67(3), 503–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chisholm, R. (1976). Person and Object. London: Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Clifford, W. K. (1879). The Ethics of Belief. In Stephen, L. & Pollock, F. (Eds.), Lectures and Essays by W. K. Clifford (pp. 177211). London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Cohen, S. (1987). Knowledge and Context. Journal of Philosophy, 83, 574–83.Google Scholar
Collins, A. (1997). The Psychological Reality of Reasons. Ratio, 10(2), 108–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, H. (1994). A Strong Confirmation of the Experimenters’ Regress. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 25(3), 493503.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Comesaña, J. and McGarth, M. (2014). Having False Reasons. In Littlejohn, C. & Turri, J. (Eds.), Epistemic Norms: New Essays on Action, Belief, and Assertion (pp. 5980). New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conee, E. & Feldman, R. (2004). Evidentialism. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conee, E. & Feldman, R. (2008). Evidence. In Smith, Q. (Ed.), Epistemology: New Essays (83104). New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Copp, D. (1997). Belief, Reason, and Motivation: Michael Smith’s The Moral Problem. Ethics, 108, 3354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cullity, G. & Gaut, B. (Eds.). (1997). Ethics and Practical Reason. Oxford: Clarendon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cuneo, T. (2007). The Normative Web: An Argument for Moral Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dancy, J. (1995). Why There Is Really No Such Thing as the Theory of Motivation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 95, 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dancy, J. (2000). Practical Reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. (2003a). Precis of Practical Reality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67(2), 423–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dancy, J. (2003b). Replies. Philosophy and Phenomenology Research, 67(2), 468–90.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. (2011). Acting in Ignorance. Frontiers of Philosophy in China, 6(3), 345–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Danielsson, S. & Olson, J. (2007). Brentano and the Buck-Passers. Mind, 116(463), 511–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
D’Arms, J. & Jacobson, D. (2000). Sentiment and Value. Ethics, 110, 722–48.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. (1983). Impartial Reason. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. (2003). Desires, Reasons, and Causes. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67(2), 436–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. (2001). Essays on Actions and Events (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
dePaul, M. (2003). Value Monism in Epistemology. In de Paul, M., and Zagzebski, L. (Eds.), Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology (pp. 170–83). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
dePaul, M. (2009). Ugly Analyses and Knowledge. In Haddock, A., Millar, A., & Pritchard, D. (Eds.), Epistemic Value (pp. 112–38). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
de Paul, M. and Zagzebski, L. (Eds.) (2003). Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology (pp. 170–83). New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dickens, C. (2006). The Life and Adventures of Nicolas Nickleby, www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/967/pg967.txt, accessed 19 February 2015. Retrieved 19 February 2015.Google Scholar
Dougherty, T. (2011a). In Defense of Propositionalism about Evidence. In Dougherty, T. (Ed.), Evidentialism and Its Discontents (pp. 226–31). New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dougherty, T. (Ed.). (2011b). Evidentialism and Its Discontents. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dougherty, T. & Rysiew, P. (2014). Experience First. In Steup, M., Turri, J., & Sosa, E. (Eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 2nd Edition (pp. 1721). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Doyle, A. C. (2008). The Sign of The Four. www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/2097/pg2097.txt.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. (2005). Is Knowledge Closed under Known Entailment? In Steup, M. & Sosa, E. (Eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology (pp. 2739). Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Fantl, J. and McGrath, M. (2009). Knowledge in an Uncertain World. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feldman, R. (2000). The Ethics of Belief. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 60(3), 667–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finlay, S. (2009). The Obscurity of Internal Reasons. Philosopher’s Imprint, 9(7), 122.Google Scholar
Foley, R. (2012). When Is True Belief Knowledge? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. G. (1988). The Importance of What We Care About. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumerton, R. (1995). Metaepsitemology and Skepticism. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Fumerton, R. & Hasan, A. (2010). Foundationalist Theories of Epistemic Justification. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2010 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/justep-foundational.Google Scholar
Garrard, E. & McNaughton, D. (1998). Mapping Moral Motivation. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 1, 4559.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerken, M. (2011). Warrant and Action. Synthese, 178(3), 529–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gettier, E. (1963). Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginet, C. (2001). Deciding to Believe. In Steup, M. (Ed.), Knowledge, Truth, and Duty: Essays on Epistemic Justification, Responsibility, and Virtue (pp. 6376). New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. (1976). Discrimination and Perceptual Knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 73(20), 771–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. (1979). What Is Justified Belief? In Pappas, G. (Ed.), Justification and Knowledge (pp. 123). Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. (1988). Strong and Weak Justification. Philosophical Perspectives, 2, Epistemology, 5169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. (1999). Internalism Exposed. The Journal of Philosophy, 96(6), 271–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greco, J. (1993). Virtues and Vices of Virtue Epistemology. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23, 413–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greco, J. (2010). Achieving Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greenough, P. & Pritchard, D. (Eds.) (2009). Williamson on Knowledge. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grimm, S. (2009). Epistemic Normativity. In Haddock, A. M., Millar, A., & Pritchard, D. (Eds.), Epistemic Value (pp. 243–64). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Haddock, A. & Macpherson, F. (Eds.) (2008). Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hampshire, S. & Hart, H. L. A. (1958). Decision, Intention and Certainty. Mind, 67(1), 112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. (1965). The Inference to the Best Explanation. The Philosophical Review, 74(1), 8895.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. (1976). Practical Reasoning. The Review of Metaphysics, 29(3), 431–63.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, J. & Stanley, J. (2008). Knowledge and Action. Journal of Philosophy, 105(10), 571–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heal, J. (1988). The Disinterested Search for Truth. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 88, 97108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, J. (1992). Believing Reasonably. Nous, 26(1), 4762.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heuer, U. (2004). Reasons for Actions and Desires. Philosophical Studies, 121(1), 4363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heuer, U. (2011). Guided by Reasons: Raz on the Normative-Explanatory Nexus. Jurisprudence, 2(2), 353–65.Google Scholar
Heuer, U. (forthcoming). Two Kinds of Wrong Reasons. In McHugh, C., Way, J., & Whiting, D. (Eds.), Normativity: Normativity: Epistemic and Practical. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hieronymi, P. (2005). The Wrong Kind of Reason. Journal of Philosophy, 102(9), 437–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hieronymi, P. (2011). Acting for Reasons. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 111(3), 407–27.Google Scholar
Hieronymi, P. (2013). The Use of Reasons in Thought (and the Use of Earmarks in Arguments). Ethics, 124(1), 114–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huemer, M. (2001). Skepticism and the Veil of Perception. New York: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Huemer, M. (2007). Compassionate Phenomenal Conservatism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXXIV(1), 3055.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hughes, N. (2014). Consistency and Evidence. Philosophical Studies, 169, 333–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hursthouse, R. (1991). Arational Actions. The Journal of Philosophy, 88(2), 5768.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hyman, J. (1999). How Knowledge Works. The Philosophical Quarterly, 49(197), 433–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hyman, J. (2011). Acting for Reasons: Reply to Dancy. Frontiers of Philosophy in China, 63(3), 358–68.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. (1982). Review of The Nature of Causation by Miles Brand. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 47(2), 470–3.Google Scholar
James, W. (1896). The Will to Believe. New World, 5.Google Scholar
Jones, W. (2009). The Goods and Motivation of Believing. In Haddock, A. M. (Ed.), Epistemic Value (pp. 139–62). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kagan, S. (1989). The Limits of Morality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kavka, G. (1983). The Toxin Puzzle. Analysis, 43, 33–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kearns, S. & Star, D. (2008). Reasons: Explanation or Evidence? Ethics, 119(1), 3156.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelly, T. (2003). Epistemic Rationality as Instrumental Rationality: A Critique. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXVI(3).Google Scholar
Kelly, T. (2008). Evidence. In Zalta, E. N., Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/evidence/.Google Scholar
Kenny, A. (2003). Action, Emotion and Will. London and New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kiesewetter, B. (2012). A Dilemma for Parfit’s Conception of Normativity. Analysis, 72(3), 466–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kincaid, H. (1990). Assessing Functional Explanations in the Social Sciences. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1, 341–54.Google Scholar
Klein, P. (1998). Foundationalism and the Infinite Regress of Reasons. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58(4), 919–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kornblith, H. (1993). Epistemic Normativity. Synthèse 94, 357–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, C. (1986). Skepticism about Practical Reason. The Journal of Philosophy, 83(1), 525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, C. (1996). The Sources of Normativity. Edited by O’Niell, O. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kusch, M. (2002). Knowledge by Agreement. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kvanvig, J. (2003). The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kvanvig, J. (2012). Coherentism and Justified Inconsistent Beliefs: A Solution. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 50(1), 2141.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kyburg, H. (1965). Comment. Philosophy of Science, 32, 147–51.Google Scholar
Lackey, J. (2008). Learning from Words: Testimony as a Source of Knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Littlejohn, C. (2012). Justification and The Truth Connection. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Littlejohn, C. (2013a). No Evidence Is False. Acta Analytica, 28, 145–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Littlejohn, C. (2013b). The Russellian Retreat. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 113(3), 293320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lycan, W. G. (1988a). Epistemic Value. In Lycan, W. G., Judgement and Justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. G. (1988b). Judgement and Justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lynch, M. (2004). True to Life. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackie, J. L. (1965). Causes and Conditions. American Philosophical Quarterly, 2(4), 245–64.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Maitzen, S. (1995). Our Errant Epistemic Aim. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55(4), 869–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mantel, S. (2014). No Reason for Identity: On the Relation between Motivating and Normative Reasons. Philosophical Explorations, 17(1), 4963.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCormick, M. (2015). Believing Against the Evidence. New York and London: Routledge.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. (1982). Criteria, Defeasibility, and Knowledge. Proceedings of the British Academy, 68, 455–79.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. (1998). Singular Thought and the Extent of Inner Space. Meaning, Knowledge, and Reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Mele, A. R. (2003). Motivation and Agency. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitova, V. (2008a). Why W. K. Clifford Was a Closet Pragmatist. Philosophical Papers, 37(3), 471–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitova, V. (2008b). Why Pragmatic Justifications of Epistemic Norms Don’t Work. South African Journal of Philosophy, 27(2), 141–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitova, V. (2011). Epistemic Motivation: Towards a Metaethics of Belief. In Reisner, A. & Steglich-Petersen, A. (Eds.), Reasons for Belief (pp. 5474). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitova, V. (2015). Truthy Psychologism about Evidence. Philosophical Studies, 172(4), 1105–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitova, V. (2016). Clearing Space for Extreme Psychologism about Reasons. South African Journal of Philosophy, 35(3), 293301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitova, V. (forthcoming). The Duty of Inquiry, or Why Othello Was a Fool. In Bourne, C. & Bourne, E. C. (Eds.), The Routledge Companion to Shakespeare and Philosophy. Routledge.Google Scholar
Montmarquet, J. (1993). Epistemic Virtue and Doxastic Responsibility. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. (1970). The Possibility of Altruism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. (1986). The View From Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Neta, R. (2002). S Knows That P. Nous, 36(4), 663–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neta, R. (2008). What Evidence Do You Have? The British Journal of Philosophy of Science, 59, 89119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Norman, R. (1997). Moral Realism. Philosophical Investigations, 20(2), 117–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Norman, R. (2001). Practical Reasons and the Redundancy of Motives. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 4, 322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical Explanations. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Owens, D. (2000). Reason without Freedom: The Problem of Epistemic Normativity. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. (2001). Rationality and Reasons. In Dan, E. & et al. (Eds.), Exploring Practical Philosophy (pp. 1739). Burlington, VT: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. (2007). Exploring Practical Philosophy. In Egonsson, D., Josefsson, J., Petersson, B. & Rønnow-Rasmussen, T. (Eds.), Hommage à Wlodek. Philosophical Papers Dedicated to Wlodek Rabinowicz (Vol. 2007). Aldershot: Ashgate. www.fil.lu.se/hommageawlodek.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. (2011). On What Matters. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pauer-Studer, H. (2014). Rationality through Reasoning. Economics and Philosophy, 30, 513–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Piller, C. (2001). Normative Practical Reasoning. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Suppl. 25, 195216.Google Scholar
Piller, C. (2013). The Bootstrapping Objection. Organon F, 20(4), 612–31.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant and Proper Function. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pollock, J. (1987a). Defeasible Reasoning. Cognitive Science, 481518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pollock, J. (1987b). Epistemic Norms. Synthese, 71, 6195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2007). Recent Work on Epistemic Value. American Philosophical Quarterly, 44(2), 85110.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2011). The Value of Knowledge. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Google Scholar
Rabinowicz, W. & Rønnow-Rasmussen, T. (2004). The Strike of the Demon: On Fitting Pro-attitudes and Value. Ethics, 114, 391423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Railton, P. (1997). On the Hypothetical and Non-hypothetical in Reasoning about Belief and Action. In Cully, G. & Gaut, B. (Eds.), Ethics and Practical Reason (pp. 5179). Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Railton, P. (2003). Facts, Values and Norms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, J. (1999). Engaging Reason: On the Theory of Value and Action. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Reisner, A. (2009). The Possibility of Pragmatic Reasons for Belief and the Wrong Kind of Reasons Problem. Philosophical Studies, 145(2), 257–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reisner, A. (forthcoming). Pragmatic Reasons for Belief. In Star, D. (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Roberts, R. C. (1988). What an Emotion Is: A Sketch. Philosophical Studies, 77, 319–38.Google Scholar
Roberts, R. C. & Wood, W. J. (2007). Intellectual Virtues: An Essay in Regulative Epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rysiew, P. (2011). Making It Evident: Evidence and Evidentness, Justification, and Belief. In Dougherty, T. (Ed.), Evidentialism and Its Discontents (pp. 207–25). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Saint-Exupery, A. (1997). The Little Prince. London: Pavilion.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. (1971). Statistical Explanation. In Salmon, W. (Ed.), Statistical Explanation and Statistical Relevance (pp. 2987). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Schroeder, M. (2007). Slaves of the Passions. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, M. (2008). Having Reasons. Philosophical Studies, 139, 5771.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, M. (2011). What Does It Take to ‘Have’ a Reason? In Reisner, A. & Steglich-Petersen, A. (Eds.), Reasons for Belief (pp. 201–22). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schroeder, M. (2012). The Ubiquity of State-Given Reasons. Ethics, 122(3), 457–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sebald, W. (2001). Austerlitz. Translated by Bell, A.. London: Penguin.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellars, W. (1991). Science, Perception and Reality. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Setiya, K. (2007a). Reasons without Rationalism. Princeton, NJ, and Oxford: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Setiya, K. (2007b). Means-End Coherence, Stringency, and Subjective Reasons. Philosophical Studies, 143(2), 223–48.Google Scholar
Shah, N. (2002). Clearing Space for Doxastic Voluntarism. The Monist, 85(3), 436–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shah, N. (2003). How Truth Governs Belief. The Philosophical Review, 112(4), 447–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shah, N. (2006). A New Argument for Evidentialism. The Philosophical Quarterly, 56: 225, 481–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shah, N. (2008). How Action Governs Intention. Philosophers’ Imprint, 8(5), 119.Google Scholar
Shah, N. & Velleman, D. (2005). Doxastic Deliberation. The Philosophical Review, 114(4), 497534.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shakespeare, W. (2005). Othello. Edited by Raffel, B.. New Haven, CT, and London: Yale University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skorupski, J. (2007). Buck-Passing about Goodness. In Rønnow-Rasmussen, T., Petersson, B., Josefsson, J., & Egonsson, D. (Eds.), Hommage à Wlodek. Philosophical Papers Dedicated to Wlodek Rabinowicz (Vol. 2007). www.fil.lu.se/hommageawlodek.Google Scholar
Smith, M. (1987). The Humean Theory of Motivation. Mind, 96(381), 3661.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, M. (1994). The Moral Problem. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Smith, M. (2003). Humenaism, Psychologism and the Argument in Favour of the Normative Story. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXVII(2), 460–7.Google Scholar
Smith, M. (2010). What Else Justification Could Be. Nous, 44(1), 1031.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, E. (1991). Knowledge in Perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, E. (2007). A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge (Vol. 1). New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, E. (2009). Reflective Knowledge. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soteriou, M. (2010). The Disjunctive Theory of Perception. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2010). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2010/entries/perception-disjunctive/.Google Scholar
Steglich-Petersen, A. (2006). No Norm Needed: On the Aim of Belief. The Philosophical Quarterly, 56(225), 499516.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steglich-Petersen, A. (2009). Weighing the Aim of Belief. Philosophical Studies, 145, 395405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. P. (1990). The Fragmentation of Reason: Preface to a Pragmatic Theory of Cognitive Evaluation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Stout, R. (2005). Action. Acumen.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, R. (2011). Evidence. In Dougherty, T. (Ed.), Evidentialism and Its Discontents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Turri, J. (2009). The Ontology of Epistemic Reasons. Nous, 43(3), 490512.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turri, J. (2010). On the Relationship between Propositional and Doxastic Justification. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80(2), 312–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turri, J. (2011). Believing for a Reason. Erkenntnis, 74, 383–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, D. J. (1985). Practical Reflection. The Philosophical Review, 94(1), 3361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, D. J. (2000a). The Possibility of Practical Reason. Oxford: Clarendon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, D. J. (2000b). From Self Psychology to Moral Philosophy. Philosophical Perspectives, 14 , Action and Freedom, 349–77.Google Scholar
Velleman, D. J. (2005). The Self as Narrator. In Christman, J. & Anderson, J. (Eds.), Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism (5676). New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, D. J. (2007). Practical Reflection (2nd edition). Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Velleman, D. J. (2009). How We Get Along. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wallace, R. J. (2003). Explanation, Deliberation, and Reason. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67(2), 429–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wallace, R. J. (2006). Normativity and the Will: Selected Papers on Moral Psychology and Practical Reason. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watson, G. (1975). Free Agency. Journal of Philosophy, 72(8), 205–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Way, J. (2009). Two Accounts of the Normativity of Rationality. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 18.Google Scholar
Wedgwood, R. (2002). The Aim of Belief. Philosophical Perspectives, 16, 267–97.Google Scholar
Wedgwood, R. (2008). Book Review: Reasons without Rationalism. Mind, 117(468), 1130–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. (1973). Deciding to Believe. In Williams, B. (Ed.), Problems of the Self (pp. 136–51). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. (1981). Internal and External Reasons. In Williams, B. (Ed.), Moral Luck (pp. 101–13). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, T. (1999). Truthmakers and the Converse Barcan Formula. Dialectica, 53, 253–70.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (forthcoming a). Acting on Knowledge. In Carter, J. A., Gordon, E., & Jarvis, B. (Eds.), Knowledge-First. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (forthcoming b). Justifications, Excuses, and Sceptical Scenarios. In Dutant, J. & Dohrn, D. (Eds.), The New Evil Demon. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wimmer, H. & Perner, J. (1983). Beliefs about Beliefs: Representation and Constraining Function of Wrong Beliefs in Young Children’s Understanding Deception. Cognition, 13(1), 103–28.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Woodward, J. (2014). Scientific Explanation. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/scientific-explanation/.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, L. T. (1996). Virtues of the Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zagzebski, L. T. (2003). Intellectual Motivation and the Good of Truth. In DePaul, M. & Zagzebski, L. (Eds.), Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology (pp. 135–54). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, L. T. (2004). Epistemic Value and the Primacy of What We Care About. Philosophical Papers, 33(3), 353–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Veli Mitova, University of Johannesburg
  • Book: Believable Evidence
  • Online publication: 19 May 2017
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316981276.016
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Veli Mitova, University of Johannesburg
  • Book: Believable Evidence
  • Online publication: 19 May 2017
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316981276.016
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Veli Mitova, University of Johannesburg
  • Book: Believable Evidence
  • Online publication: 19 May 2017
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316981276.016
Available formats
×