Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-22dnz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T22:04:42.924Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 November 2019

Kelly Becker
Affiliation:
University of New Mexico
Iain D. Thomson
Affiliation:
University of New Mexico
Get access
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2019

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Masao, Abe. 1989. Zen and Western Thought. Ed. LaFleur, W. R.. University of Hawai‘i Press.Google Scholar
Achinstein, P. 1983. The Nature of Explanation. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Achinstein, P. 1991. Particles and Waves: Historical Essays in the Philosophy of Science. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Achinstein, P. (ed.). 2005. Scientific Evidence: Philosophical Theories and Applications. Johns Hopkins University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Achterhuis, H. 2001. American Philosophy of Technology: The Empirical Turn. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Adams, M. M. 1999. Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Adams, R. 1976. “Motive utilitarianism,” Journal of Philosophy 73:467–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, R. 2006. A Theory of Virtue: Excellence in Being for the Good. Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adorno, T. W. 1973 [1964]. The Jargon of Authenticity. Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Adorno, T. W. 1973 [1966]. Negative Dialectics. Trans. Ashton, E. B.. Routledge.Google Scholar
Adorno, T. W. 1998. Critical Models: Interventions and Catchwords. Trans. Pickford, H. W.. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Adorno, T. W. and Becker, H.. 1999. “Education for maturity and responsibility,” History of the Human Sciences 12(3):2134. Trans. R. French, J. Thomas, and D. Weymann.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adorno, T. W. and Horkheimer, M.. 1944. Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments. Published in book form 1947; ed. Noerr, G. S., trans. Jephcott, E.. Stanford University Press, 2002.Google Scholar
Agamben, G. 1999. Remnants of Auschwitz: The Witness and the Archive. Zone Books.Google Scholar
Ahmed, L. 1992. Women and Gender in Islam: Historical Roots of a Modern Debate. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Albert, D. 2000. Time and Chance. Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alcoff, L. 1999. “Toward a phenomenology of racial embodiment,” Radical Philosophy 95:1526.Google Scholar
Alexander, M. 2012. The New Jim Crow: Mass Incarceration in the Age of Colorblindness. The New Press.Google Scholar
al-Hibri, A. 1999. “Is Western patriarchal feminism good for third world/minority women?” in, as reply to Okin, S. (author), Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women? Princeton University Press, 41–6.Google Scholar
Alicke, M., Rose, D., and Bloom, D.. 2011. “Causation, norm violation, and culpable control,” Journal of Philosophy 108(12):670–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allen, W. S. 1966 [1957]. “On the linguistic study of languages,” in Strevens, P. D. (ed.), Five Inaugural Lectures. Oxford University Press, 326.Google Scholar
Allhoff, F. (ed.). 2007. Wine and Philosophy: A Symposium on Thinking and Drinking. Wiley.Google Scholar
Allhoff, F. and Adams, M. P. (eds.). 2009. Whiskey and Philosophy: A Small Batch of Spirited Ideas. Wiley.Google Scholar
Allison, H. 1990. Kant’s Theory of Freedom. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allison, H. 2011. Kant’s Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals: A Commentary. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alpyagil, R. 2014. “Virtue in Islam,” in van Hooft, S. (ed.), Handbook of Virtue Ethics. Routledge, 318–27.Google Scholar
Alston, W. P. 1955. “Pragmatism and the verifiability theory of meaning,” Philosophical Studies 6:6571.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alston, W. P. 1991. Perceiving God: The Epistemology of Religious Experience. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Alvarez, M. 2010. Kinds of Reasons. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alvarez, M. and Hyman, J.. 1998. “Agents and their actions,” Philosophy 73:219–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Améry, J. 1966. At the Mind’s Limits: Contemplations by a Survivor on Auschwitz and its Realities. Trans. Sidney and Rosenfeld, Stella P.. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Ames, R. 2011. Confucian Role Ethics: A Vocabulary. University of Hawai‘i Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, A. and Belnap, N.. 1975. Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity, vol. 1. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Anderson, E. 2006. “The epistemology of democracy,” Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology 3(1–2):822.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Angle, S. C. and Slote, M. (eds.). 2013. Virtue Ethics and Confucianism. Routledge.Google Scholar
Ankersmit, F. R. 1983. Narrative Logic: A Semantic Analysis of the Historian’s Language. Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Ankersmit, F. R. 2001. Historical Representation. Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Ankersmit, F. R. 2007. “Danto’s philosophy of history in retrospective,” in Danto 2007: 364–93; also in Journal of the Philosophy of History 3(2):109–45.Google Scholar
Ankersmit, F. R. 2009. “Narrative and interpretation,” in Tucker 2009: 199–208.Google Scholar
Ankersmit, F., Bevir, M., Roth, P., Tucker, A., and Wylie, A.. 2007. “The philosophy of history: an agenda,” Journal of the Philosophy of History 1(1):19.Google Scholar
Ankersmit, F. and Kellner, H. (eds.). 1995. A New Philosophy of History. Reaktion Books.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1993. The Morality of Happiness. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 2011. Intelligent Virtue. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, J. 2014. “Why virtue ethics does not have a problem with right action,” in Timmons, M. (ed.), Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics, vol. 4. Oxford University Press, 1333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anon. 1949. Notes on a discussion on “The mind and the computing machine,” at the Manchester Philosophy Seminar 27 October. Written by a member of the Philosophy Department.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. 1957. Intention. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. 1958. “Modern moral philosophy,” Philosophy 33(124):119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. 1974. “Comment on Professor R. L. Gregory’s paper,” in Brown, Stuart C. (ed.), Philosophy of Psychology. Macmillan, 211–20, 235ff, 243ff.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. 1979. “Under a description,” Noûs 13:219–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. 1989. “Von Wright on practical inference,” in Schlipp, P. A. and Hahn, L. E. (eds.), The Philosophy of Georg Henrik Von Wright. Open Court, 377404.Google Scholar
Antognazza, M. R. 2015. “The benefit to philosophy of the study of its history,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 23(1):161–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Antony, L. 2008. “Meta-linguistics: methodology and ontology in Devitt’s Ignorance of Language,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86(4):643–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Antony, L. 2016. “Things oughta make sense,” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 90:2139.Google Scholar
Antony, L. and Hornstein, N. (eds.). 2003. Chomsky and His Critics. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Apel, K.-O. 1980. “The apriori of the communication community and the foundation of ethics,” in Toward a Transformation of Philosophy. Trans. Adey, G. and Frisby, D.. Routledge & Kegan Paul, 225300.Google Scholar
Apel, K.-O. 1990. “Is ethics of the ideal communication community a Utopia? On the relationship between ethics, Utopia, and the critique of Utopia,” in Benhabib, S. and Dallmary, F. (eds.), The Communicative Ethics Controversy. The MIT Press, 2359.Google Scholar
Apel, K.-O. et al. 1981 [1971]. Hermeneutik und Ideologiekritik. Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Apple, M. 2004a. “Race and the politics of educational reform,” in Olssen, M. (ed.), Culture and Learning: Access and Opportunity in the Classroom. Information Age, 299313.Google Scholar
Apple, M. 2004b. “Creating difference: neo-Liberalism, neo-Conservatism and the politics of educational reform,” Educational Policy 18(1):1844.Google Scholar
Applebaum, B. 2003. “Social justice, democratic education and the silencing of words that wound,” Journal of Moral Education 32(2):151–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aquinas, Thomas. 1964–73. Summa Theologiae. Blackfriars.Google Scholar
Aquinas, Thomas. 1964. Sententia Libri Ethicorum: Commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics, 2 vols. Trans. Litzinger, C. I.. Library of Living Catholic Thought. Regnery.Google Scholar
Åqvist, L. 1973. “Modal logic with subjunctive conditionals and dispositional predicates,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 1:176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Archambault, R. D. (ed.). 1965. Philosophical Analysis and Education. Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Arendt, H. 1977. Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil. Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Arendt, H. 2008. “The history of a great crime,” in Kahn, J. (ed.), The Jewish Writings. Schocken, 453–61. Originally published in Commentary, March 1952.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 2000. Nicomachean Ethics. Ed. Crisp, Roger. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 1968. A Materialist Theory of the Mind. Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 1978. “Naturalism, materialism and first philosophy,” Philosophia 8(2–3):261–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 1985. What Is a Law of Nature? Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 1989. Universals: An Opinionated Introduction. Westview Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 1993 [1968]. A Materialist Theory of Mind, revised edition. Routledge.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 1997. A World of States of Affairs. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 1999. The Mind–Body Problem: An Opinionated Introduction. Westview Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 2004. Truth and Truthmakers. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, R. 2000. “Perfectionism and politics,” Ethics 111:3763.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, R. 2005. “Sophisticated rule consequentialism: some simple objections,” Philosophical Issues 15:235–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arnold, D. 2005. Buddhists, Brahmins, and Belief. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Arnold, D. 2009. “Svasaṃvitti as methodological solipsism: ‘narrow content’ and the problem of intentionality in Buddhist philosophy of mind,” in D’Amato, M., Garfield, J. L., and Tillemans, T. J. F. (eds.), Pointing at the Moon: Buddhism, Logic, Analytic Philosophy. Oxford University Press, 135–59.Google Scholar
Arnold, D. 2012. Brains, Buddhas, and Believing: The Problem of Intentionality in Classical Buddhist and Cognitive-Scientific Philosophy of Mind. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Arnsperger, C. and Picavet, E. B.. 2004. “More than modus vivendi, less than overlapping consensus: towards a political theory of social compromise,” Social Science Information 43:167204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arp, K. 2012. “Simone de Beauvoir’s existentialism: freedom and ambiguity in the human world,” in Crowell 2012a: 252–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aschheim, S. 1992. The Nietzsche Legacy in Germany, 1890–1990. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Audi, P. 2012a. “A clarification and defense of the notion of grounding,” in Correia, F. and Schneiders, B. (eds.), Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality. Cambridge University Press, 101–21Google Scholar
Audi, P. 2012b. “Grounding: toward a theory of the in-virtue-of relation,” Journal of Philosophy 109(1):685711.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, R. and Wainwright, W. J. (eds.). 1986. Rationality, Religious Belief, and Moral Commitment: New Essays in the Philosophy of Religion. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Augustine, . 1998. The City of God against the Pagans. Ed. and trans. Dyson, R. W.. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Augustine, . 2010. On the Free Choice of the Will, On Grace and Free Choice, and Other Writings. Ed. and trans. King, Peter. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Aune, B. 1979. Kant’s Theory of Morals. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Aurobindo, . 1942. The Life Divine. Lotus Press.Google Scholar
Austin, John L. 1961. “Other minds,” in John L. Austin, Philosophical Papers. Ed. Urmson, J. O. and Warnock, G. J.. Clarendon Press, 76116.Google Scholar
Austin, John L. 1962. Sense and Sensibilia. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Austin, John L. 1975 [1962]. How to Do Things with Words. Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Austin, John L. 1979. Philosophical Papers, 3rd edition. Ed. Urmson, J. O. and Warnock, G. J.. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Auxier, R., Anderson, D. R., and Hahn, L. E.. 2015. The Philosophy of Hilary Putnam. Open Court.Google Scholar
Ayer, A. J. 1936. Language, Truth, and Logic. Gollancz.Google Scholar
Ayer, A. J. 1952. Language, Truth, and Logic, 2nd (revised) edition. Dover.Google Scholar
Ayer, A. J. 1956. “What is a law of nature?Revue Internationale de Philosophie 10(2/36):144.Google Scholar
Ayer, A. J. (ed.). 1959. Logical Positivism. The Free Press.Google Scholar
Ayer, A. J. 1967. “Has Austin refuted the sense-datum theory?Synthese 17:117–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ayers, M. and Garber, D.. 1998. “Introduction,” in Garber and Ayers 1998: 1–5.Google Scholar
Bach, K. 1994. “Conversational implicature,” Mind & Language 9:124–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bach, K. 2010. “Refraining, omitting, and negative acts,” in O’Connor, T. and Sandis, C. (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Action. Blackwell, 50–7.Google Scholar
Baehr, J. 2011. The Inquiring Mind: On Intellectual Virtues and Virtue Epistemology. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baert, P. 2015. The Existentialist Moment: The Rise of Sartre as a Public Intellectual. Polity Press.Google Scholar
Baier, K. 1995. The Rational and the Moral Order: The Social Roots of Reason and Morality. Open Court.Google Scholar
Baker, C. L. and McCarthy, J. (eds.). 1981. The Logical Problem of Language Acquisition. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Baker, G. 2002. “Wittgenstein on metaphysical/everyday use,” Philosophical Quarterly 52:289302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baker, G. and Hacker, P. M. S.. 1980. Wittgenstein, Understanding and Meaning. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Baker, G. and Hacker, P. M. S.. 1985. Wittgenstein, Rules, Grammar, and Necessity. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bakhurst, D. 1991. Consciousness and Revolution in Soviet Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baldwin, T. 1979. “The original choice in Sartre and Kant,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 80:3144.Google Scholar
Baldwin, T. 2004. “G. E. Moore,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Zalta, E. N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moore/.Google Scholar
Bales, R. 1971. “Act utilitarianism: account of right-making characteristics or decision-making procedure?American Philosophical Quarterly 8:257–65.Google Scholar
Ball, S. J. (ed.). 1990. Foucault and Education: Disciplines and Knowledge. Routledge.Google Scholar
Ball, S. J. 2006. Education Policy and Social Class: The Selected Works of Stephen J. Ball. Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ball, S. J. 2009. “Lifelong learning, subjectivity and the totally pedagogical society,” in Peters, M. A. et al. (eds.), Governmentality Studies in Education. Sense, 201–16.Google Scholar
Ball, S. J. 2013. Foucault, Power, and Education. Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barad, K. 2007. Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of Matter and Meaning. Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Barcan, R. 1946. “A functional calculus of first order based on strict implication,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 11:116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baril, A. 2013. “The role of welfare in eudaimonism,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 51(4):511–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, B. 1982. T. S. Kuhn and Social Science. Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, B. and Bloor, D.. 1982. “Relativism, rationalism and the sociology of knowledge,” in Hollis, M. and Lukes, S. (eds.), Rationality and Relativism. Blackwell, 2147.Google Scholar
Barnes, E. 2008. The Paradox of Predictivism. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E. 2018. “Symmetric dependence,” in Bliss, R. L. and Priest, G. (eds.), Reality and Its Structure. Oxford University Press, 5069.Google Scholar
Baron, M. 1995. Kantian Ethics almost without Apology. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Barrett, W. 1958. Irrational Man: A Study in Existential Philosophy. Doubleday. Revised edition Anchor Books, 1990.Google Scholar
Barry, B. 1995. “John Rawls and the search for stability.” Ethics 105(4):874915.Google Scholar
Barwise, K. J. (ed.). 1977. Handbook of Mathematical Logic. North Holland.Google Scholar
Baudrillard, J. 1994 (1981). Simulacra and Simulation. University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Baumgartner, H. M. 1972. Kontinuität und Geschichte. Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Baxley, A. 2010. Kant’s Theory of Virtue: The Value of Autocracy. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baxley, A. 2015. “Virtue, self-mastery and the autocracy of practical reason,” in Denis, L. and Sense, O. (eds.), Kant’s Lectures on Ethics: A Critical Guide. Cambridge University Press, 223–38.Google Scholar
Bayne, T. and Montague, M. (eds.). 2011. Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beaney, M. 2004. “Carnap’s conception of explication: from Frege to Husserl?” in Awodey, S. and Klein, C. (eds.), Carnap Brought Home: The View from Jena. Open Court, 117–50.Google Scholar
Beaney, M. (ed.). 2013a. The Oxford Handbook of the History of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beaney, M. 2013b. “What is analytic philosophy?” in Beaney 2013a: 3–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beaney, M. 2013c. “The historiography of analytic philosophy,” in Beaney 2013a: 30–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beaney, M. 2013d. “Analytic philosophy and history of philosophy: the development of the idea of rational reconstruction,” in Reck 2013: 231–60.Google Scholar
Beaney, M. 2013e. “Twenty years of the British Journal for the History of Philosophy,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 21(1):112.Google Scholar
Beaney, M. 2014. “Analysis,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Zalta, E. N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/analysis/.Google Scholar
Beaney, M. 2016. “Historiography, philosophy of history and the historical turn in analytic philosophy,” Journal of the Philosophy of History 10(2):211–34.Google Scholar
Beaney, M. 2018. “Twenty-five years of the British Journal for the History of Philosophy,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 26(1):110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beaney, M. 2019. “First steps and conceptual creativity,” in Conant, J. and Sunday, S. (eds.), Wittgenstein on Philosophy, Objectivity, and Meaning. Cambridge University Press, pp. 11942.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beardsley, M. C. 1958. Aesthetics: Problems in the Philosophy of Criticism. Harcourt and Brace and World.Google Scholar
Beardsley, M. C. 1966. Aesthetics from Classical Greece to the Present. Macmillan.Google Scholar
Beardsley, M. C. 1983. “An aesthetic definition of art,” in Curtler, H. (ed.), What Is Art? Haven, 1529.Google Scholar
Beaty, M. D. 1990. Christian Theism and the Problems of Philosophy. University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Beauvoir, S. de. 1976 [1947]. The Ethics of Ambiguity. Trans. Frechtman, B.. Philosophical Library.Google Scholar
Beauvoir, S. de. 1989 [1949]. The Second Sex. Trans. Parshley, H. M.. Vintage.Google Scholar
Beauvoir, S. de. 2009 [1949]. The Second Sex. Trans. Borde, C. and Malovany-Chevallier, S.. Random House.Google Scholar
Bechtel, W. 1985. “Attributing responsibility to computer systems,” Metaphilosophy 16:296306.Google Scholar
Bechtel, W. 1994. “Levels of descriptions and explanation in cognitive science,” Minds and Machines 4:125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bechtel, W. and Richardson, R. C.. 2010 [1993]. Discovering Complexity: Decomposition and Localization as Strategies in Scientific Research, 2nd edition. The MIT Press/Bradford Books.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beck, L. W. 1960. A Commentary on Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Becker, K. 2007. Epistemology Modalized. Routledge.Google Scholar
Becker, L. C. 1998. A New Stoicism. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Beckermann, A., Flohr, H., and Kim, J.. 1992. Emergence or Reduction? Essays on the Prospects of Nonreductive Physicalism. International Phenomenological Society.Google Scholar
Behme, C. 2014a. Evaluating Cartesian Linguistics: From Historical Antecedents to Computational Modeling. Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Behme, C. 2014b. “A ‘Galilean’ science of language,” Journal of Linguistics 50(3):671704.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bekoff, M. and Goodall, J.. 2007. The Emotional Lives of Animals: A Leading Scientist Explores Animal Joy, Sorrow, and Empathy – And Why They Matter. New World Library.Google Scholar
Bellah, N., Madsen, R., Sullivan, W. M., Swidler, A., and Tipton, S. M.. 1985. Habits of the Heart. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Benjamin, W. 1968. “Theses on the philosophy of history,” in Illuminations. Ed. Arendt, H., trans. Zohn, H.. Schocken Books, 253–64.Google Scholar
Bennett, J. 1971. Locke, Berkeley, Hume: Central Themes. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bennett, J. 1995. The Act Itself. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bennett, K. 2011. “By our bootstraps,” Philosophical Perspectives 25(1):2741.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bennett, K. 2017. Making Things Up. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bennett, M. R. S., Dennett, D., Hacker, P., and Searle, J.. 2007. Neuroscience and Philosophy. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Bennett, M. R. S. and Hacker, P. M. S.. 2003. Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bergoffen, D. 2001. “The politics of the vulnerable body,” Hypatia 18(1):116–34.Google Scholar
Berker, S. 2007. “Particular reasons,” Ethics 118:109–39.Google Scholar
Berker, S. 2018. “The unity of grounding,” Mind 127(507):72977.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berleant, A. 2002. Environment and the Arts: Perspectives on Environmental Aesthetics. Ashgate.Google Scholar
Berlin, I. 1969. Four Essays on Liberty. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bernasconi, R. 2006. How to Read Sartre. W. W. Norton.Google Scholar
Bernstein, R. J. 2008. “The conversation that never happened (Gadamer/Derrida),” Review of Metaphysics 61(3):577603.Google Scholar
Bernstein, S. 2014. “Omissions as possibilities,” Philosophical Studies 167(1):123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernstein, S. 2015. “A closer look at trumping,” Acta Analytica 1(1):122.Google Scholar
Bernstein, S. 2016a. “Omission impossible,” Philosophical Studies 173:2,575–89.Google Scholar
Bernstein, S. 2016b. “Grounding is not causation,” Philosophical Perspectives 30:2138.Google Scholar
Berto, F. 2013. “Impossible worlds,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Zalta, E. N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/impossible-worlds/.Google Scholar
Besley, T. [A. C.]. 2007. “Foucault, truth-telling and technologies of the self: confessional practices of the self and schools,” in Peters, M. and Besley, T. [A. C.] (eds.), Why Foucault? Peter Lang, 5570.Google Scholar
Besley, T. 2009. “Governmentality of youth: beyond cultural studies,” in Peters, M., Besley, A., Olson, M., Maurer, S., and Weber, S., Governmentality Studies in Education. Sense, 165200.Google Scholar
Besley, T. [A. C.] and Peters, M.. 2007. Subjectivity and Truth: Foucault, Education, and the Culture of Self. Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Betzler, M. (ed.). 2008. Kant’s Ethics of Virtue. Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Bhushan, N. and Garfield, J.. 2011. Indian Philosophy in English. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bickle, J. 1992. “Mental anomaly and the new mind–brain reductionism,” Philosophy of Science 59(2):217–30.Google Scholar
Biesta, G. 2010. “A new ‘logic’ of emancipation: the methodology of Jacques Rancière,” Educational Theory 60(1):3959.Google Scholar
Bilimoria, P. 2014. “Ethics and virtue in classical Indian thinking,” in van Hooft, S. (ed.), Handbook of Virtue Ethics. Routledge, 294305.Google Scholar
Bird, A. 2000. Thomas Kuhn. Princeton University Press and Acumen Press.Google Scholar
Bird, A. 2007. Nature’s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Birkhoff, G. and von Neumann, J.. 1936. “The logic of quantum mechanics,” Annals of Mathematics 37:823–43.Google Scholar
Birnbaum, D. and Olson, A.. 2009. “An interview with Jacques Derrida on the limits of digestion,” Journal #02. www.e-flux.com/journal/02/68495/an-interview-with-jacques-derrida-on-the-limits-of-digestion/, accessed May 26, 2018.Google Scholar
Bìro, A. 2005. Denaturalizing Ecological Politics: Alienation from Nature from Rousseau to the Frankfurt School and Beyond. University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bishop, J. 1989. Natural Agency: An Essay on the Causal Theory of Action. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bittner, R. 2001. Doing Things for Reasons. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Blake, N., Smeyers, P., Smith, R., and Standish, P.. 1998. Thinking Again: Education after Postmodernism. Bergin and Garvey.Google Scholar
Blattner, W. 2007. “Ontology, the a priori, and the primacy of practice,” in Crowell, S. and Malpas, J. (eds.), Transcendental Heidegger. Stanford University Press, 1027.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blattner, W. 2013. “Some thoughts about ‘analytic’ and ‘continental’ philosophy.” www.georgetown.edu/faculty/blattner/contanalytic.html, accessed September 1, 2017.Google Scholar
Bliss, R. L. 2013. “Viciousness and the structure of reality,” Philosophical Studies 166(2):399418.Google Scholar
Bliss, R. L. 2014. “Viciousness and circles of ground,” Metaphilosophy 45(2):245–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bliss, R. L. and Trogdon, K.. 2014. “Metaphysical grounding,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Zalta, E. N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/grounding/.Google Scholar
Block, N. 1978. “Troubles with functionalism,” in Block, N. (ed.), Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology, vol. 1. University of Minnesota Press, 261325.Google Scholar
Block, N. 1990. “Inverted Earth,” in Tomberlin, James (ed.), Action Theory and the Philosophy of Mind (vol. 4 of Philosophical Perspectives). Ridgeview, 5379.Google Scholar
Block, N. 1995. “On a confusion about the function of consciousness,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18:227–47.Google Scholar
Block, N. 2011. “Perceptual consciousness overflows cognitive access,” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 15:567–75.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Block, N., Flanagan, O., and Güzeldere, G. (eds.). 1997. The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Block, N. and Fodor, J. A.. 1972. “What psychological states are not,” Philosophical Review 81:159–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bloomfield, L. 1933. Language. Henry Holt.Google Scholar
Bloor, D. 1976. Knowledge and Social Image. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Boas, F. 1911. “Introduction,” in Boas, F. (ed.), Handbook of American Indian Languages, Part I. US Government Printing Office.Google Scholar
Bobik, J. and Sayre, K. M.. 1963. “Pattern recognition mechanisms and St. Thomas’ theory of abstraction,” Revue Philosophique de Louvain 61:2443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boden, M. A. 1965. “McDougall revisited,” Journal of Personality 33:119.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Boden, M. A. 1970. “Intentionality and physical systems,” Philosophy of Science 37:200–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boden, M. A. 1972. Purposive Explanation in Psychology. Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boden, M. A. 1988. Computer Models of Mind: Computational Approaches in Theoretical Psychology. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Boden, M. A. 2006. Mind as Machine: A History of Cognitive Science, 2 vols. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Boden, M. A. 2014. “Aaron Sloman: a bright tile in AI’s mosaic,” in Wyatt, J. L., Petters, D. D., and Hogg, D. C. (eds.), From Animals to Robots and Back: Reflections on Hard Problems in the Study of Cognition. A Collection in Honour of Aaron Sloman. Springer, 930.Google Scholar
Boghossian, P. 1996. “Analyticity reconsidered,” Noûs 30(3):360–91.Google Scholar
Bohman, J. and Richardson, H. S.. 2009. “Liberalism, deliberative democracy, and ‘reasons that all can accept’,” Journal of Political Philosophy 17:253–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boler, M. 1999. Feeling Power: Emotions and Education. Routledge.Google Scholar
Bolzano, B. 1837. Wissenschaftslehre, 4 vols. Seidel.Google Scholar
Bondy, A. S. 1968. Existe una filosofía de nuestra América? Siglo XXI Editores.Google Scholar
Bookchin, M. 1982. The Ecology of Freedom: The Emergence and Dissolution of Hierarchy. Cheshire Books.Google Scholar
Bordo, S. 2004. Unbearable Weight, 2nd edition. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Bordwell, D. and Carroll, N.. 1996. Post-Theory: Reconstructing Film Studies. University of Wisconsin Press.Google Scholar
Borgmann, A. 1984. Technology and the Character of Contemporary Life. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Botts, T. F. 2015. “Hermeneutics, race, and gender,” in Malpas, J. and Gander, H.-H. (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Hermeneutics. Routledge, 498518.Google Scholar
Bourdieu, P., Passeron, J.-C., and de Saint Martin, M., with Baudelot, C. and Vincent, G.. 1965. Academic Discourse: Linguistic Misunderstanding and Professorial Power. Trans. Teese, R.. Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Bourgeois, P. L. 2006. “Marcel and Ricoeur: mystery and hope at the boundary of reason in the postmodern situation,” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 80(3):421–33.Google Scholar
Bovens, L. and Hartmann, S.. 2003. Bayesian Epistemology. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bowles, S. and Gintis, H.. 1979. Schooling in Capitalist America: Education Reform and the Contradictions of Economic Life. Basic Books.Google Scholar
Boyd, D. 2004. “The legacies of liberalism and oppressive relations: facing a dilemma for the subject of moral education,” Journal of Moral Education 33(1):322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, R. 1999. “Species, homeostasis and higher taxa,” in Wilson, R. A. (ed.), Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays. The MIT Press, 141–85.Google Scholar
Boyd, R. and Richerson, P.. 2007. “Culture, adaptation, and innateness,” in Carruthers, P., Laurence, S., and Stich, S. (eds.), The Innate Mind, vol. 2: Culture and Cognition. Oxford University Press, 2338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bradshaw, G. A. 2009. Elephants on the Edge: What Animals Teach Us about Humanity. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Braithwaite, R. 1953. Scientific Explanation. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brand, P. Z. and Korsmeyer, C. (eds.). 1995. Feminism and Tradition in Aesthetics. Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
Brandis, C. A. 1815. Von dem Begriff der Geschichte der Philosophie. G. Bonnier.Google Scholar
Brandom, R. 1994. Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Brandom, R. 2008. Between Saying and Doing: Towards Analytic Pragmatism. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brandom, R. 2009. Reason in Philosophy: Animating Ideas. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Brandom, R. 2010. “Reply to Danielle Macbeth’s ‘Inference, Meaning, and Truth’,” in Weiss, B. and Wanderer, J. (eds.), Reading Brandom: On Making It Explicit. Routledge, 338–41.Google Scholar
Brandon, R. N. 1978. “Adaptation and evolutionary theory,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science (Part A) 9(3):181206.Google Scholar
Brandt, R. 1992 [1956]. “Some merits of one form of rule-utilitarianism,” reprinted in Brandt, Morality, Utilitarianism, and Rights. Cambridge University Press, 111–36.Google Scholar
Bratman, M. 1987. Intentions, Plans, and Practical Reason. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Bratman, M. 1999. Faces of Intention: Selected Essays on Intention and Agency. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Braudy, L. and Cohen, M. (eds.). 1999. Film Theory and Criticism: Introductory Readings. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bredo, E. 1989. “After positivism, what?Educational Theory 39(4):401–13.Google Scholar
Breton, A. 1969. Manifestoes of Surrealism. Trans. Seaver, R. and Lane, H. R.. University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Bridges, D. (ed.). 1997. Education, Autonomy and Democratic Citizenship: Philosophy in a Changing World. Routledge.Google Scholar
Bridges, J. 2014. “Rule-following skepticism, properly so-called,” in Conant, J. and Kern, A. (eds.), Varieties of Skepticism. de Gruyter, 249–88.Google Scholar
Briggs, R. 2012. “Interventionist counterfactuals,” Philosophical Studies 160(1):139–66.Google Scholar
Brink, D. 1993. “The separateness of persons, distributive norms, and moral theory,” in Frey, R. and Morris, C. (eds.), Value, Welfare, and Morality. Cambridge University Press, 252–89.Google Scholar
Brink, D. 2013. Mill’s Progressive Principles. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brogaard, B. and Salerno, J.. 2013. “Remarks on counterpossibles,” Synthese 190(4):639–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bronkhorst, J. 2011. “A note on ‘nirvikalpaka’ and ‘savikalpaka’ perception,” Philosophy East and West 61(2):373–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, J. 1999. “Normative requirements,” Ratio 12(4):398419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, J. 2004. “Reasons,” in Wallace, R. J., Pettit, P., Scheffler, S., and Smith, M. (eds.), Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz. Oxford University Press, 2855.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, C. and Toadvine, T.. 2003. Eco-Phenomenology: Back to the Earth Itself. SUNY Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, H. 1993. Perception, Theory and Commitment. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Brown, H. R. and Harré, R. (eds.). 1988. Philosophical Foundations of Quantum Field Theory. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brown, J. 1995. “The incompatibility of anti-individualism and privileged access,” Analysis 55:149–56.Google Scholar
Brown, J. 2004. Anti-Individualism and Knowledge. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Brown, L. B. 1991. “The theory of jazz music: ‘it don’t mean a thing …’,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 49:115–27.Google Scholar
Brown, L. B., Goldblatt, D., and Gracyk, T.. 2018. Jazz and the Philosophy of Art. Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, S. 2014. “The professionalization of British philosophy,” in Mander, W. J. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of British Philosophy in the Nineteenth Century. Oxford University Press, 619–40.Google Scholar
Brucker, J. J. 1742–4. Historia critica philosophiae, 5 vols. B. C. Breitkopf.Google Scholar
Brueckner, A. 1994. “The structure of the skeptical argument,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54:827–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bruner, J. S., Goodnow, J. J., and Austin, G. A.. 1956. A Study of Thinking. Wiley.Google Scholar
Brunner, O., Conze, W., and Koselleck, R. (eds.). 1972–97. Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe. Historisches Lexikon zur politisch-sozialen Sprache in Deutschland, 8 vols. Klett.Google Scholar
Brush, S. G. 2007. “Predictivism and the periodic table,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 38(1):256–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bruya, B. 2010. “The rehabilitation of spontaneity: a new approach in philosophy of action,” Philosophy East and West 60(2):207–50.Google Scholar
Bryson, N. 1986. Vision and Painting: The Logic of the Gaze. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Bubner, R., Cramer, K., and Weihl, R. (eds.). 1970. Hermeneutik und Dialektik. J. C. B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).Google Scholar
Budd, M. 1995. The Values of Art: Pictures, Poetry, and Music. Allen Lane, The Penguin Press.Google Scholar
Budd, M. 2002. The Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bunge, M. 1966. “Technology as applied science,” Technology and Culture 7(3):329–47.Google Scholar
Bunge, M. 1979. “Philosophical inputs and outputs of technology,” in Bugliarello, G. and Doner, D. B. (eds.), The History of Philosophy and Technology. University of Illinois Press, 262–81.Google Scholar
Burbules, N. 2000. “Lyotard on Wittgenstein,” in Dhillon, P. A. and Standish, P. (eds.), Lyotard: Just Education. Routledge, 3653.Google Scholar
Burbules, N. 2008. “Tacit teaching,” Educational Philosophy and Theory 40(5 Sept.):666–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, T. 1979. “Individualism and the mental,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4:73121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, T. 1986. “Individualism and psychology,” Philosophical Review 95(1):345.Google Scholar
Burge, T. 1988. “Individualism and self-knowledge.” Journal of Philosophy 85(11):649–63.Google Scholar
Burge, T. 2010. Origins of Objectivity. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burgess, J. P. 1998. “Quinus ab omni naevo vindicatus,” in Kazmi, Ali (ed.), Meaning and Reference, Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplement 23:25–65.Google Scholar
Burgess, J. P. 1999. “Which modal logic is the right one?Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40:8193.Google Scholar
Burgess, J. P. 2005. Fixing Frege. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Burgess, J. P. Kripke. Polity Press.Google Scholar
Butler, J. 1990. Gender Trouble. Routledge.Google Scholar
Butler, J. 1997. “Merely cultural,” Social Text 52–3:265–77.Google Scholar
Butler, J. 2004. Precarious Life: The Powers of Mourning and Violence. Verso.Google Scholar
Butler, J. 2011 [1993]. Bodies that Matter: On the Discursive Limits of Sex. Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, A. 2001. “Intentionalism defended,” Philosophical Review 110:199240.Google Scholar
Byrne, A. 2004. “How hard are the sceptical paradoxes?Noûs 38:299325.Google Scholar
Byrne, A. and Thau, M.. 1996. “In defence of the hybrid view,” Mind 105(417):139–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cage, J. 1961. Silence: Lectures and Writings by John Cage. Wesleyan University Press.Google Scholar
Cahill, A. 2001. Rethinking Rape. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Calle-Gruber, M. (ed.). 2016. Heidegger, Politics, and Philosophy: The Heidelberg Conference. Trans. Fort, J.. Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
Callicott, J. B. 1986. “The metaphysical implications of ecology,” Environmental Ethics 8(4):301–16.Google Scholar
Callicott, J. B. 1989. In Defense of the Land Ethic: Essays in Environmental Philosophy. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Cameron, R. 2008. “Truthmakers and ontological commitment: or how to deal with complex objects and mathematical ontology without getting into trouble,” Philosophical Studies 140(1):118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, J. 2006. A Thoughtful Profession: The Early Years of the American Philosophical Association. Open Court.Google Scholar
Candlish, S. 2007. The Russell/Bradley Dispute and Its Significance for Twentieth-Century Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caputo, J. D. 1987. Radical Hermeneutics: Repetition, Deconstruction, and the Hermeneutic Project. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Carlson, A. 1999. Aesthetics and the Environment: The Appreciation of Nature, Art and Architecture. Routledge.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1928. Der Logische aufbau der Welt. Weltkreis-Verlag. Trans. R. A. George, The Logical Structure of the World. University of California Press, 1967.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1934a. “The task of the logic of science” (English translation of a paper originally published in German in 1934), in McGuinness, B. (ed.), Unified Science: The Vienna Circle Monographs Series Originally Edited by Otto Neurath. Reidel, 4666.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1934b. The Unity of Science (English translation of an article originally published in German in 1931). Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1936–37. “Testability and meaning,” parts I and II, Philosophy of Science 3:419–71 and 4:1–40.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1937. The Logical Syntax of Language (expanded version of original German of 1934. Trans. Smeaton, A.). Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1942. Introduction to Semantics. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1945. “The two concepts of probability,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 5(4):513–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, R. 1946. “Modalities and quantification,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 11:3364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, R. 1947. Meaning and Necessity. University of Chicago Press. 2nd, expanded edition, 1956.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1950. Logical Foundations of Probability. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1955. “Meaning and synonymy in natural language,” Philosophical Studies 6:3347.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1956. “Empiricism, semantics, and ontology,” in Meaning and Necessity, 2nd edition. University of Chicago Press, 205–21.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1958. “Beobachtungssprache und theoretische sprache,” Dialectica 12(3–4):236–48. Reprinted (in a translation by Herbert Bonhert) as “Observation language and theoretical language,” in J. Hintikka (ed.), Rudolf Carnap, Logical Empiricist: Materials and Perspectives. D. Reidel Publishing Co. (1975), 75–85. (References in the text are to the latter publication.).Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1959. “Psychology in physical language” (English translation of an article originally published in German in 1932 ). In A. J. Ayer (ed.), Logical Positivism. Macmillan,165?98.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1963a. “Intellectual autobiography,” in Schilpp, 1963: 3–84.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1963b. “Carl G. Hempel on scientific theories,” in Schilpp, 1963: 958–66.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1963c. “W. V. Quine on logical truth,” in Schilpp, 1963: 915–22.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1966. The Philosophical Foundations of Physics: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Ed. Gardner, M.. Basic Books. Reprinted in a slightly revised edition as An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science, Dover, 1995. (References in the text are to the Dover edition.)Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1967. The Logical Structure of the World. Trans. George, R. A.. University of California Press. Reprinted Open Court, 2003.Google Scholar
Carnap, R., Hahn, H., and Neurath, O.. 1929. “The scientific conception of the world,” in Sarkar, Sahotra (ed.), The Emergence of Logical Empiricism. Garland, 1996, 321–41.Google Scholar
Carney, J. D. 1991. “The style theory of art,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 72:273–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carr, D. 1986. Time, Narrative and History. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Carr, D. 2006. “The moral roots of citizenship: towards a virtue ethical reconciliation of principle and character in education for effective citizenship,” Journal of Moral Education 35(4):443–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carr, D. 2008. “Character education as the cultivation of virtue,” in Nucci, L. P. and Navaez, D. (eds.), Handbook of Moral and Character Education. Routledge.Google Scholar
Carroll, N. 1988. “Art, practice, and narrative,” Monist 71:140–56.Google Scholar
Carroll, N. 1990. The Philosophy of Horror or Paradoxes of the Heart. Routledge.Google Scholar
Carroll, N. 1996. Theorizing the Moving Image. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Carroll, N. 1998. A Philosophy of Mass Art. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Carroll, N. 2007a. The Philosophy of Motion Pictures. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Carroll, N. 2007b. “Vertigo and the pathologies of romantic love,” in Baggett, D. and Drumin, W. A. (eds.), Hitchcock and Philosophy: Dial M for Metaphysics. Open Court, 101–14.Google Scholar
Carroll, N. 2013. Minerva's Night Out: Philosophy, Pop Culture, and Moving Pictures. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Carroll, N. 2014. Humour: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, P. 2000. Phenomenal Consciousness. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Carston, R. 2002. Thoughts and Utterances. Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N. 1983. How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. 1989. Nature’s Capacities and Their Measurement. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. 1994. “Fundamentalism vs. the patchwork of laws,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 94:279–92.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. 1999. The Dappled World. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carus, A. W. 2007. Carnap and Twentieth-Century Thought: Explication as Enlightenment. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Carus, P. 2001 [1911]. “Truth on trial: an exposition of the nature of truth,” in Shook, J. (ed.), Early Critics of Pragmatism. Thoemmes Press, vol. 3, 1143.Google Scholar
Catana, L. 2008. The Historiographical Concept “System of Philosophy”: Its Origin, Nature and Legitimacy. Brill.Google Scholar
Catana, L. 2012. “The history of the history of philosophy, and the lost biographical tradition,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20(3):619–25.Google Scholar
Catana, L. 2013. “Philosophical problems in the history of philosophy: what are they?” in Laerke, , Smith, , and Schliesser, 2013: 115–33.Google Scholar
Cavell, S. 1962. “The availability of Wittgenstein’s later philosophy,” Philosophical Review 71:6793.Google Scholar
Cavell, S. 1976. “A matter of meaning it,” in Must We Mean What We Say? Cambridge University Press, 197219.Google Scholar
Cavell, S. 1979a. The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein, Skepticism, Morality, and Tragedy. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cavell, S. 1979b. The World Viewed: Reflections on the Ontology of Film. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Cavell, S. 1981. Pursuits of Happiness: The Hollywood Comedy of Remarriage. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Cavell, S. 1994. A Pitch of Philosophy. Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cerbone, D. R. 2003. “The limits of conservatism: Wittgenstein on ‘our life’ and ‘our concepts’,” in Heyes, C. (ed.), The Grammar of Politics. Cornell University Press, 4362.Google Scholar
Chadha, M. 2001. “Perceptual cognition: a Nyāya-Kantian approach,” Philosophy East and West 51(2):197209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chadha, M. 2004. “Perceiving particulars-as-such is incoherent: a reply to Mark Siderits,” Philosophy East and West 54(3):382–9.Google Scholar
Chadha, M. 2011. “Self-awareness: eliminating the myth of the ‘invisible subject’,” Philosophy East and West 61(3):453–67.Google Scholar
Chakrabarti, A. 1997. Denying Existence: The Logic, Epistemology, and Pragmatics of Negative Existentials and Fictional Discourse. Kluwer Academic.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chakrabarti, A. 2000. “Against immaculate perception: seven reasons for eliminating nirvikalpaka perception from Nyāya,” Philosophy East and West 50(1):18.Google Scholar
Chakrabarti, A. 2001. “Reply to Stephen Phillips,” Philosophy East and West 51(1):114–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chakrabarti, A. and Matilal, B. K. (eds.). 1994. Knowing from Words: Western and Indian Philosophical Analysis of Understanding and Testimony. Kluwer Academic.Google Scholar
Chakrabarti, K. K. 1975. “The Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika theory of universals,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 3(3/4):363–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chakrabarti, K. K. 1999. Classical Indian Philosophy of Mind: The Nyāya Dualist Tradition. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Chakrabarti, K. K. 2010. Classical Indian Philosophy of Induction. Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Chalmers, A. 1976. What Is This Thing Called Science? University of Queensland Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, A. 2011. “Drawing philosophical lessons from Perrin’s experiments on Brownian motion: a response to van Fraassen,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 62(4):711–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. 1996. The Conscious Mind. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. (ed.). 2002. Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. 2003. “The content and epistemology of phenomenal belief,” in Smith, Q. and Jokic, A. (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Essays. Oxford University Press, 220–72.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. 2004. “The representational character of experience,” in Leiter, B. (ed.), The Future for Philosophy. Oxford University Press, 153–80. Reprinted as chapter 11 of Chalmers 2010, 181–94.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. 2006a. “The foundations of two-dimensional semantics,” in Garcia-Carpintero, M. and Macia, J. (eds.), Two-Dimensional Semantics: Foundations and Applications. Oxford University Press, 55140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. 2006b. “Perception and the Fall from Eden,” in Szabó Gendler, T. and Hawthorne, J. (eds.), Perceptual Experience. Oxford University Press, 49125. Reprinted as chapter 12 of Chalmers 2010: 195–209.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. 2010. The Character of Consciousness. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D., Manley, D., and Wasserman, R. (eds.). 2009. Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chastain, C. 1975. “Reference and context,” in Gunderson, K. (ed.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science VII: Language, Mind, and Knowledge. University of Minnesota Press, 194269.Google Scholar
Chatterjee, A. K. 1962. The Yogācāra Idealism. Banaras Hindu University Press.Google Scholar
Chatterjee, D. 1977. “Skepticism and Indian philosophy,” Philosophy East and West 27(2):195209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chaudhuri, H. 1953. “The integralism of Sri Aurobindo,” Philosophy East and West 3(2):131–6.Google Scholar
Cheng, Chung-ying and Bunnin, N. (eds.). 2002. Contemporary Chinese Philosophy. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Cheng, L. 2002. “Zhang Dainian: creative synthesis and Chinese philosophy,” in Cheng, and Bunnin, 2002: 235–45.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1953. “Systems of syntactic analysis,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 18:242–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1957. Syntactic Structures. Mouton.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1958. “Linguistics, logic, psychology, and computers,” in Carr, J. W. (ed.), Computer Programming and Artificial Intelligence, An Intensive Course for Practicing Scientists and Engineers: Lectures Given at the University of Michigan (Summer 1958). University of Michigan College of Engineering, 429–56.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1959a. “On certain formal properties of grammars,” Information and Control 1:91112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1959b. “Review of B. F. Skinner, Verbal Behavior,” Language 35:2658.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1964. Current Issues in Linguistic Theory. Mouton.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1965. Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1966. Cartesian Linguistics. Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1967. “Recent contributions to the theory of innate ideas,” Synthese 17(1):211.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1968. Language and Mind. Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1969a. “Quine’s empirical assumptions,” in Davidson, D. and Hintikka, J. (eds.), Words and Objections. Reidel, 5368.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1969b. “Linguistics and philosophy,” in Hook, S. (ed.), Language and Philosophy: A Symposium. New York University Press, 5194.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1969c. “Some empirical assumptions in modern philosophy of language,” in Morgenbesser, S., Suppes, P., and Gabriel White, M. (eds.), Philosophy, Science and Method: Essays in Honor of Ernest Nagel. St. Martin’s Press, 260–85.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1971. Problems of Knowledge and Freedom. Pantheon.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1975a. The Logical Structure of Linguistic Theory. Plenum. (Written in 1955–6.)Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1975b. Reflections on Language. Pantheon.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1980. Rules and Representations. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1986. Knowledge of Language: Its Nature, Origin and Use. Praeger.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 2000. “Explaining language use,” in Chomsky, N., New Horizons in the Study of Language and Mind. Cambridge University Press, 1945.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N. 2012. The Science of Language: Interviews with James McGilvray. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N. and Miller, G. A.. 1958. “Finite state languages,” Information and Control 1(2):91112.Google Scholar
Chrisley, R. 1998. “What might dynamical intentionality be, if not computation? Peer commentary on T. van Gelder,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21(4):634–5.Google Scholar
Chrisley, R. 2000. “Transparent computationalism,” in Scheutz, M. (ed.), New Computationalism. Academia Verlag, 105–20.Google Scholar
Chrisley, R. and Sloman, A.. 2016. “Functionalism, revisionism, and qualia,” APA Newsletter on Philosophy and Computers 16(1):213.Google Scholar
Christensen, C. 1998. “Getting Heidegger off the West Coast,” Inquiry 41(1):6587.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Church, A. 1949. “Review of Ayer, Language, Truth, and Logic, 2nd edition,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 14:52–3.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M. 1979. Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. 1981. “Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes,” Journal of Philosophy 78:6790.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M. 1986a. “Cognitive neurobiology: a computational hypothesis for laminar cortex,” Biology and Philosophy 1:2551.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. 1986b. “Some reductive strategies in cognitive neurobiology,” Mind 95:279309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. 1989. A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M. 1995. The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain. The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. and Churchland, P. S.. 1981. “Functionalism, qualia, and intentionality,” Philosophical Topics 12:121–45.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M. and Hooker, C. A. (eds.). 1985. Images of Science: Essays on Realism and Empiricism. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. S. 2012. Braintrust: What Neuroscience Tells Us about Morality. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Clark, A. J. 1989. Microcognition: Philosophy, Cognitive Science, and Parallel Distributed Processing. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Clark, A. J. 1991. “Systematicity, structured representations and cognitive architecture: a reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn,” in Horgan, T. and Tienson, J. (eds.), Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind. Kluwer, 198218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, A. J. 1993. Associative Engines: Connectionism, Concepts, and Representational Change. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Clark, A. J. 1997. Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Clark, A. J. 2003. Natural-Born Cyborgs: Why Minds and Technologies Are Made to Merge. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Clark, A. J. 2013. “Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36(3):181204.Google Scholar
Clark, A. J. 2016. Surfing Uncertainty: Prediction, Action, and the Embodied Mind. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Clark, A. J. and Chalmers, D.. 1998. “The extended mind,” Analysis 58:719.Google Scholar
Clark, A. J. and Karmiloff-Smith, A.. 1993. “The cognizer’s innards: a psychological and philosophical perspective on the development of thought,” Mind and Language 8:487519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, A. J. and Thornton, C.. 1997. “Trading spaces: computation, representation, and the limits of uninformed learning,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20:5790.Google Scholar
Clark, M. 1963. “Knowledge and grounds: a comment on Mr. Gettier’s paper,” Analysis 24(2):46–8.Google Scholar
Clark, M. and Liggins, D.. 2012. “Recent work on grounding,” Analysis 72(4):812–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, T. 1972. “The legacy of skepticism,” Journal of Philosophy 68:754–69.Google Scholar
Cleveland, T. 1997. Trying without Willing: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Ashgate.Google Scholar
Cobb, J. B. Jr. and Ives, C.. 1990. The Emptying God: A Buddhist–Jewish–Christian Conversation. Orbis Books.Google Scholar
Coetzee, P. H. and Roux, A. P. J. (eds). 2004. The African Philosophy Reader. Routledge.Google Scholar
Cohen, M. R. and Nagel, E.. 1934. An Introduction to Logic and Scientific Method. Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Cohen, P. J. 1966. Set Theory and the Continuum Hypothesis. Benjamin.Google Scholar
Cohen, S. 1984. “Justification and truth,” Philosophical Studies 46(3):279–95.Google Scholar
Cohen, S. 1986. “Knowledge and context,” Journal of Philosophy 83(10):574–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, S. 1998. “Two kinds of sceptical argument,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58:143–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, S. 1999. “Contextualism, skepticism, and the structure of reasons,” Philosophical Perspectives 13:5789.Google Scholar
Cohen, S. 2000. “Contextualism and skepticism,” Philosophical Issues 10:94107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, T. 1999. Jokes: Philosophical Thoughts on Joking Matters. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Cole, D. 2014. “The Chinese room argument,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Zalta, E. N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/ sum2014/entries/chinese-room/.Google Scholar
Coliva, A. 2015. Extended Rationality: A Hinge Epistemology. Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collingwood, R. G. 1992 [1942]. The New Leviathan. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Collingwood, R. G. 1994 [1946]. The Idea of History. Ed. van der Dussen, J.. Oxford University Press (revised edition).Google Scholar
Collingwood, R. G. 1999. The Principles of History. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Collingwood, R. G. 2005 [1933]. An Essay on Philosophical Method. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Collins, James. 1952. The Existentialists: A Critical Study. Henry Regnery.Google Scholar
Collins, John. 2007. “Counterfactuals, causation, and preemption,” in Jacquette, D. (ed.), Philosophy of Logic. Elsevier, 1,127–44.Google Scholar
Collins, P. H. 2002. Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Consciousness, and the Politics of Empowerment. Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, R. 1998. The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Change. Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Collins, S. 1982. Selfless Persons. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conant, J. 1998. “Wittgenstein on meaning and use,” Philosophical Investigations 21:222–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conant, J. 2002. “The method of the Tractatus,” in Reck, E. (ed.), From Frege to Wittgenstein: Perspectives on Early Analytic Philosophy. Oxford University Press, 374462.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conant, J. 2016. “The emergence of the concept of the analytic tradition,” in Bell, J. A., Cutrofello, A., and Livingston, P. M. (eds.), Beyond the Analytic-Continental Divide: Pluralist Philosophy in the Twenty-First Century. Routledge, 1758.Google Scholar
Connolly, W. E. 1991. Identity/Difference: Democratic Negotiations of Political Paradox. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Conze, E. 1962. Buddhist Thought in India. Routledge.Google Scholar
Cook, S. 2006. “The P versus NP problem” [Official Cray Foundation Millennium Prize Description]. www.claymath.org/sites/default/files/pvsnp.pdf.Google Scholar
Cooper, D. E. 1998. “Interpretation, construction and the ‘postmodern ethos’,” in Carr, D. (ed.), Education, Knowledge and Truth: Beyond the Postmodern Impasse. Routledge, 3749.Google Scholar
Cooper, D. E. 1999. Existentialism: A Reconstruction. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Cooper, D. E. 2012. “Existentialism as a philosophical movement,” in Crowell, 2012a: 27–49.Google Scholar
Cooper, R. V. 2005. Classifying Madness: A Philosophical Examination of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders. Springer.Google Scholar
Copleston, F. 1946–86. A History of Philosophy, 11 vols. Continuum.Google Scholar
Copp, D. 1997. “The Ring of Gyges: overridingness and the unity of reason,” Social Philosophy of Policy 14:86106.Google Scholar
Copp, D. 2009. “Toward a pluralist and teleological theory of normativity,” Philosophical Issues 19 (Metaethics):2137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Correia, F. 2005. Existential Dependence and Cognate Notions. Philosophia Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Correia, F. 2010. “Grounding and truth-functions,” Logique et Analyse 53(211):251–79.Google Scholar
Correia, F. 2013. “Metaphysical grounds and essence,” in Hoeltje, M., Schnieder, B., and Steinberg, A. (eds.), Varieties of Dependence: Ontological Dependence, Grounding, Supervenience, Response-Dependence. Philosophia Verlag, 271–96.Google Scholar
Correia, F. 2014. “Logical grounds,” Review of Symbolic Logic 7(1):3159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Correia, F. and Schnieder, B.. 2012. “Grounding: an opinionated introduction,” in Correia, F. and Schnieder, B. (eds.), Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality. Cambridge University Press, 136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coseru, C. 2012. Perceiving Reality: Consciousness, Intentionality, and Cognition in Buddhist Philosophy. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cowherds, . 2011. Moonshadows: Conventional Truth in Buddhist Philosophy. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cowherds, . 2016. Moonpaths: Ethics and Emptiness. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cowie, F. 1999. What’s Within? Nativism Reconsidered. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Craik, K. J. W. 1943. The Nature of Explanation. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Crary, A. and Read, R. (eds.). 2000. The New Wittgenstein. Routledge.Google Scholar
Crisp, R. 1996. “Modern moral philosophy and the virtues,” in Crisp, R. (ed.), How Should One Live? Essays on the Virtues. Oxford University Press, 118.Google Scholar
Critchley, S. 2001. Continental Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cronin, H. 1991. The Ant and the Peacock: Altruism and Sexual Selection from Darwin to Today. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cronon, W. 1995. “The trouble with wilderness; or, getting back to the wrong Nature,” in Cronon, (ed.), Uncommon Ground: Rethinking the Human Place in Nature. W. W. Norton & Co, 6990.Google Scholar
Crowe, B. D. 2006. Heidegger’s Phenomenology of Religion: Realism and Cultural Criticism. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Crowell, S. (ed.). 2012a. The Cambridge Companion to Existentialism. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Crowell, S. 2012b. “Sartre’s existentialism and the nature of consciousness,” in Crowell, 2012a: 199–226.Google Scholar
Crutzen, P. 2002. “Geology of mankind,” Nature 415:23.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cua, A. S. (ed.). 2003. Encyclopedia of Chinese Philosophy. Routledge.Google Scholar
Cua, A. S. 2009. “The emergence of the history of Chinese philosophy,” in Mou, 2009: 43–68.Google Scholar
Cureton, A. and Hill, T. E. Jr. 2014. “Kant on virtue and the virtues,” in Snow, N. (ed.), Cultivating Virtue. Oxford University Press, 87110.Google Scholar
Currie, G. 1988. An Ontology of Art. Macmillan.Google Scholar
Currie, G. 1990. The Nature of Fiction. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Currie, G. 1995. Image and Mind: Film, Philosophy, and Cognitive Science. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Currie, G. 2004. Arts and Minds. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Currie, G. 2010. Narratives and Narrators: A Philosophy of Stories. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Currie, G. and Ravenscroft, I.. 2002. Recreative Minds: Imagination in Philosophy and Psychology. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Currie, G., Kieran, M., Meskin, A., and Robson, J. (eds.). 2014. Aesthetics and the Sciences of the Mind. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cushman, P. 1990. “Why the self is empty: toward a historically situated psychology,” American Psychologist 45(5):599611.Google Scholar
D’Agostino, F. 1996. Free Public Reason: Making It Up as We Go. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dahlstrom, D. O. 2001. Heidegger’s Concept of Truth. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
D’Amato, M., Garfield, J. L., and Tillemans, T. J. F. (eds.). 2009. Pointing at the Moon: Buddhism, Logic, Analytic Philosophy. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. 1981. “On moral properties,” Mind 90(359):367–85.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. 2000. Practical Reality. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. 2004. Ethics without Principles. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Alighieri, Dante. 2008 [1308–20]. The Divine Comedy. Ed. Higgins, D. H., trans Sisson, C. H.. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Danto, A. C. 1964. “The artworld,” Journal of Philosophy 61:571–84.Google Scholar
Danto, A. C. 1965. Analytical Philosophy of History. Cambridge University Press. Reprinted in Danto 1985.Google Scholar
Danto, A. C. 1975. Jean-Paul Sartre. Viking.Google Scholar
Danto, A. C. 1981. The Transfiguration of the Commonplace. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Danto, A. C. 1985. Narration and Knowledge. Columbia University Press. Reprinted in Danto 2007.Google Scholar
Danto, A. C. 1986. The Philosophical Disenfranchisement of Art. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Danto, A. C. 1995. “The decline and fall of the analytical philosophy of history,” in Ankersmit, and Kellner, 1995: 70–85.Google Scholar
Danto, A. C. 2007 [1965]. Narration and Knowledge. With a new introduction by Goehr, L. and a new conclusion by Ankersmit, F.. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. 1990. “Autonomous internalism and the justification of morals,” Noûs 24(2):257–67.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. 1997. “Reasons, motives, and the demands of morality: an introduction,” in Darwall, S., Gibbard, A., and Railton, P. (eds.), Moral Discourse and Practice. Oxford University Press, 305–12.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. 1859. On the Origin of Species. London: John Murray.Google Scholar
Dasgupta, Shamik. 2014a. “On the plurality of grounds,” Philosophers’ Imprint 14(20).Google Scholar
Dasgupta, Shamik. 2014b. “The possibility of physicalism,” Journal of Philosophy 111(9/10):557–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dasgupta, Surendranath. 1953. Indian Idealism. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dasti, M. 2012. “Parasitism and disjunctivism in Nyāya epistemology,” Philosophy East and West 62(1):115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dasti, M. (ed.). 2014. Free Will, Agency, and Selfhood in Indian Philosophy. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1963. “Actions, reasons, and causes,” Journal of Philosophy 60:685700. Reprinted in Davidson 1980a: 3–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. 1967a. “The logical form of action sentences,” in Rescher, N. (ed.), The Logic of Decision and Action. University of Pittsburgh Press, 113–14. Reprinted in Davidson 1980a: 105–21.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1967b. “Truth and meaning,” Synthese 17:304–23. Reprinted in Davidson 2001: 17–36.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1970. “Mental events,” in Foster, L. and Swanson, J. W. (eds.), Experience and Theory. Duckworth, 137–49. Reprinted in Davidson 1980a: 207–28.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1974. “On the very idea of a conceptual scheme,” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 47:520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. 1978. “Intending,” Philosophy of History and Action 11:41-60. Reprinted in Davidson 1980a: 83–102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. 1980a. Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1980b. “Introduction,” in Davidson, 1980a: xv.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1987. “Problems in the explanation of action,” in Pettit, P., Sylvan, R., and Norman, J. (eds.), Metaphysics and Morality. Blackwell, 317.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 2001. Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1736.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. and Harman, G. (eds.). 1970. Semantics of Natural Language. Springer.Google Scholar
Davies, D. 2003. Art as Performance. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Davies, D. 2007. Aesthetics and Literature. Continuum.Google Scholar
Davies, D. 2011. Philosophy of the Performing Arts. Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, M. 2004. “Epistemic entitlement, warrant transmission and easy knowledge,” Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 78(1):213–45.Google Scholar
Davies, S. 1980. “The expression of emotion in music,” Mind 89:6786.Google Scholar
Davies, S. 1991. Definitions of Art. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Davies, S. 1994. Musical Meaning and Expression. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Davies, S. 2001. Musical Works and Performances: A Philosophical Exploration. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Davies, S. 2012. The Artful Species: Aesthetics, Art, and Evolution. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davis, B. W., Schroeder, B., and Wirth, J. M.. 2011. Japanese and Continental Philosophy: Conversations with the Kyoto School. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Davis, L. S. 2014. “Mindfulness, non-attachment and other Buddhist virtues,” in van Hooft, S. (ed.), Handbook of Virtue Ethics. Routledge, 306–17.Google Scholar
Davis, M. and Putnam, H.. 1960 [1959]. “A computing procedure for quantification theory,” Journal of the Association for Computing Machinery 7:201–15. (An earlier version was published in 1959 by the Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawkins, R. 1976. The Selfish Gene. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
de Bary, W. T., Gluck, C., and Tiedemann, A. (eds.). 2006. Sources of Japanese Tradition, vol. 2: 1600–2000. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
de Bary, W. T., Keene, D., Tanabe, G., and Varley, H. P. (eds.). 2002. Sources of Japanese Tradition, vol. 1: From Earliest Times to 1600. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
De Caro, M. and Macarthur, D. (eds.). 2004. Naturalism in Question. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
De Caro, M. and Macarthur, D. (eds.). 2010. Naturalism and Normativity. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Dearden, R. F., Hirst, P. H., and Peters, R. S. (eds.). 1972. Education and the Development of Reason. Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Deleuze, G. 1983 [1962]. Nietzsche and Philosophy. Trans. Tomlinson, H.. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Deleuze, G. 1990 [1968]. Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza. Trans. Joughin, M.. Zone Books.Google Scholar
Deleuze, G. 1994 [1968]. Difference and Repetition. Trans. Patton, P.. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Denis, L. 2006. “Kant’s conception of virtue,” in Guyer, P. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy. Cambridge University Press, 505–37.Google Scholar
Denis, L. (ed.). 2011. Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Denis, L. and Sensen, O. (eds.). 2015. Kant’s Lectures on Ethics: A Critical Guide. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1969. Content and Consciousness. Routledge.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1971. “Intentional systems,” Journal of Philosophy 68:87106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. 1978. Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1981. “True believers: the intentional strategy and why it works,” in Heath, A. F. (ed.), Scientific Explanation. Oxford University Press, 5375.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1984. Elbow Room: The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1988. “Quining qualia,” in Marcel, A. J. and Bisiach, E. (eds.), Consciousness in Contemporary Science. Oxford University Press, 4277. Reprinted in Chalmers 2002, 226–46.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1991. Consciousness Explained. Allen Lane.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1995a. “The unimagined preposterousness of zombies: commentary on Moody, Flanagan, and Polger,” Journal of Consciousness Studies 2:322–6.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1995b. Darwin’s Dangerous Idea. Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1997. “When HAL kills, who’s to blame? Computer ethics,” in Hal’s Legacy: 2001’s Computer as Dream and Reality. Ed. Stork, D. G.. The MIT Press, 351–65.Google Scholar
DePaul, M. 1987. “Supervenience and moral dependence,” Philosophical Studies 51(3):425–39.Google Scholar
Depoortere, F. 2008. Christ in Postmodern Philosophy: Gianni Vattimo, René Girard, and Slavoj Žižek. T & T Clark.Google Scholar
DeRose, K. 1995. “Solving the skeptical problem,” Philosophical Review 104:152.Google Scholar
DeRose, K. 1999. “Can it be that it would have been even though it might not have been?Philosophical Perspectives 13:385413.Google Scholar
deRosset, L. 2013. “Grounding explanations,” Philosophers’ Imprint 13(7):126.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. 1961. Dissemination. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. 1973 [1967]. Speech and Phenomena and Other Essays on Husserl’s Theory of Signs. Trans. Allison, D.. Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. 1978 [1967]. Writing and Difference. Trans. Bass, A.. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. 1989 [1984]. “Three questions to Hans-Georg Gadamer.” Trans. Michelfelder, D. and Palmer, R.. In Michelfelder, D. and Palmer, R. (eds.), Dialogue and Deconstruction: The Gadamer–Derrida Encounter. SUNY Press, 52–4.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. 1989 [1987]. Of Spirit: Heidegger and the Question. Trans. Bennington, G. and Bowlby, R.. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. 1997 [1994]. Politics of Friendship. Trans. Collins, G.. Verso.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. 2005a [2003]. Rogues: Two Essays on Reason. Trans. Brault, P.-A. and Naas, M.. Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. 2005b [2003]. “Rams: uninterrupted dialogue – between two infinities, the poem,” in Dutoit, T. and Pasanen, O. (eds.), Sovereignties in Question: The Poetics of Paul Celan. Fordham University Press, 135–63.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. 2008. The Animal that Therefore I Am. Trans. Wills, D., ed. Mallet, M.-L.. Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
Devall, B. 1988. Simple in Means, Rich in Ends: Practicing Deep Ecology. Peregrine Smith Books.Google Scholar
Devall, B. and Sessions, G.. 1985. Deep Ecology: Living as if the Earth Really Mattered. Peregrine Books.Google Scholar
Devereux, D. 1995. “Socrates’ Kantian conception of virtue,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 33:407–8.Google Scholar
Devitt, M. 2006. Ignorance of Language. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Devitt, M. 2008. “Resurrecting biological essentialism,” Philosophy of Science 75(3):344–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
deVries, W. 2016. “Hegelian spirits in Sellarsian bottles,” Philosophical Studies. doi:10.1007/s11098-016-0830-0.Google Scholar
deVries, W. and Coates, P.. 2009. “Brandom’s two-ply error,” in deVries, W. (ed.), Empiricism, Perceptual Knowledge, Normativity, and Realism. Oxford University Press, 131–45.Google Scholar
DeVries, W. and Triplett, T.. 2000. Knowledge, Mind, and the Given. Hackett.Google Scholar
de Waal, F. 2016. Are We Smart Enough to Know How Smart Animals Are? W. W. Norton & Co.Google Scholar
de Waal, F. 2010. The Age of Empathy: Nature’s Lessons for a Kinder Society. Broadway Books.Google Scholar
de Waal, F. and Suchak, M.. 2010. “Prosocial primates: selfish and unselfish motivations,” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences 365(1553):2,711–22.Google Scholar
Dewey, J. 1882–1953. The Works of John Dewey. Ed. Boydston, Jo Ann. Southern Illinois University Press.Google Scholar
Dewey, J. 1934. Art as Experience. Minton, Balch.Google Scholar
Dewey, J. 1938. Experience and Education. Collier Books. In John Dewey: The Later Works. Ed. Boydston, Jo Ann, vol. 12. Southern Illinois University Press, 1991.Google Scholar
Dewey, J. 1941. “My philosophy of law,” in My Philosophy of Law: Credos of Sixteen American Scholars. Published under the direction of the Julius Rosenthal Foundation for General Law. Boston Law Book Co., 7385.Google Scholar
Dewey, J. 1960 [1929]. The Quest for Certainty. Capricorn BooksGoogle Scholar
Dewey, J. 1966. Democracy and Education. Collier-Macmillan Canada.Google Scholar
Dewey, J. 2003. The Later Works, 1925–1953. Ed. Boydston, Jo Ann. In The Collected Works of John Dewey, 1882–1953, vol. 4: 1929. Southern Illinois University Press.Google Scholar
Diamond, C. 1995. The Realistic Spirit. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Di Cesare, D. 2013. Gadamer: A Philosophical Portrait. Trans. Keane, N.. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Dickie, G. 1974. Art and the Aesthetic: An Institutional Analysis. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Dickie, G. 1984. The Art Circle: A Theory of Art. Haven.Google Scholar
Diffey, T. J. 1969. “The republic of art,” British Journal of Aesthetics 9:145–56.Google Scholar
Dilthey, W. 1989 [1883]. Introduction to the Human Sciences: An Attempt to Lay a Foundation for the Study of Society and History. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Diprose, R. 2002. Corporeal Generosity: On Giving with Nietzsche, Merleau-Ponty and Levinas. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Dobzhansky, T. G. 1973. Mankind Evolving: The Evolution of the Human Species. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Donagan, A. 1962. The Later Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Donnellan, K. 1966. “Reference and definite descriptions,” Philosophical Review 75(3):281304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donovan, J. and Adams, C. J.. 2007. The Feminist Care Tradition in Animal Ethics: A Reader. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Doppelt, G. 1981. “Rawls’ system of justice: a critique from the Left,” Noûs 15:259307.Google Scholar
Doris, J. 1998. “Persons, situations, and virtue ethics,” Noûs 32:504–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doris, J. 2002. Lack of Character: Personality and Moral Behavior. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dostal, R. J. (ed.). 2002. The Cambridge Companion to Gadamer. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dougherty, T. and Tweedt, C.. 2015. “Religious epistemology,” Philosophy Compass 10(8):547–59.Google Scholar
Douven, I. and Meijs, W.. 2007. “Measuring coherence,” Synthese 156:405–25.Google Scholar
Dowe, P. 2001. “A counterfactual theory of prevention and ‘causation’ by omission,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 79:216–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Downs, J. 1992. “A healthy and ecologically balanced environment: an argument for a third generation Right,” Duke Journal of Comparative and International Law 3:351–85.Google Scholar
Draper, P. 1989. “Pain and pleasure: an evidential problem for theists,” Noûs 23(3):331–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Draper, P. and Dougherty, T.. 2013. “Explanation and the problem of evil,” in McBrayer, J. and Howard-Snyder, D. (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil. John Wiley & Sons, 6782.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dravid, R. R. 1972. The Problem of Universals in Indian Philosophy. Motilal Banarsidass.Google Scholar
Dray, W. H. 1957. Laws and Explanation in History. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Dray, W. H. 1964. Philosophy of History. Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Dray, W. H. 1995. History as Re-Enactment. R. G. Collingwood’s Idea of History. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dreben, B. 2003. “On Rawls and political liberalism,” in Freeman, S. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Rawls. Cambridge University Press, 316–46.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1970. “Epistemic operators,” Journal of Philosophy 67:1,007–23.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1971. “Conclusive reasons,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49(1):122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, F. 1977. “Laws of nature,” Philosophy of Science 44(2):248–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, F. 1981. Knowledge and the Flow of Information. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1988. Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1995. Naturalizing the Mind. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 2005a. “The case against closure,” in Sosa, E. and Steup, M. (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology. Blackwell, 1326.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 2005b. “Reply to Hawthorne,” in Sosa, E. and Steup, M. (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology. Blackwell, 43–6.Google Scholar
Dreyfus, G. and Thompson, E.. 2007. “Asian perspectives: Indian theories of mind,” in Zelazo, D., Moscovitch, M., and Thompson, E. (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness. Cambridge University Press, 89114.Google Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L. 1965. Alchemy and Artificial Intelligence. Research Report P-3244, Dec. Rand Corporation.Google Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L. 1967. “Why computers must have bodies in order to be intelligent,” Review of Metaphysics 21:1332.Google Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L. 1972. What Computers Can’t Do: A Critique of Artificial Reason. Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L. 1991. Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger’s Being and Time, Division I. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L. 2000. “Teaching between skill and philosophy by a philosopher of skills,” Journal of Nordic Educational Research 20(2):107–16.Google Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L. 2008. On the Internet. Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L. 2014. Skillful Coping: Essays on the Phenomenology of Everyday Perception and Action. Ed. Wrathall, M.. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L. 2017. Background Practices. Ed. Wrathall, M.. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L. and Dreyfus, S. E.. 1988. “Making a mind versus modelling the brain: artificial intelligence back at a branch point,” in Graubard, S. (ed.), The Artificial Intelligence Debate: False Starts, Real Foundations. The MIT Press, 1543.Google Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L. and Hall, H. (eds.). 1982. Husserl, Intentionality, and Cognitive Science. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L. and Rabinow, P.. 1982. Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics, 2nd edition. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Dries, M. (ed.). 2008. Nietzsche on Time and History. Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Driver, J. 1996. “The virtues and human nature,” in Crisp, R. (ed.), How Should One Live? Oxford University Press, 111–29.Google Scholar
Driver, J. 2001. Uneasy Virtue. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Driver, J. 2011. “A Humean account of the status and character of animals,” in Beauchamp, Tom and Frey, R. G. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Animal Ethics. Oxford University Press, 91118.Google Scholar
Ducasse, C. J. 1948. Art, the Critics, and You. Hafner.Google Scholar
Duerlinger, J. 1993. “Reductionist and nonreductionist theories of persons in Indian philosophy,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 20(1):79101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duhem, P. 1914. The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory. Trans. Wiener, P., 1954. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. 1973. Frege: Philosophy of Language. London: Duckworth. 2nd edition, 1981.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. 1977. Elements of Intuitionism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. 1993. The Origins of Analytic Philosophy. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Duncan, A. R. C. 1957. Practical Reason and Morality: A Study of Immanuel Kant’s “Foundations for the Metaphysics of Morals.” Thomas Nelson.Google Scholar
Dupré, J. 1981. “Natural kinds and biological taxa,” Philosophical Review 90:6690.Google Scholar
Dupré, J. 1993. The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Dupré, J. 2001. Human Nature and the Limits of Science. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Durbin, P. T. 2006. “Philosophy of technology: in search of discourse synthesis,” Technè: Research in Philosophy and Technology 10(2):95–6.Google Scholar
Dutihl Novaes, C. 2016. “Conceptual genealogy for analytic philosophy,” in Bell, J., Cutrofello, A., and Livingston, P. (eds.), Beyond the Analytic–Continental Divide. Routledge, 75108.Google Scholar
Dutton, D. 2009. The Art Instinct. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Earman, J. 1971. “Kant, incongruous counterparts, and the nature of space,” Ratio 13:118.Google Scholar
Earman, J. 1992. Bayes or Bust. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Earman, J. and Salmon, M. H.. 1992. “Confirmation of scientific hypotheses,” in Salmon, M. H. et al. (eds.), Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Hackett, 42103.Google Scholar
Ebbs, G. 2011a. “Carnap and Quine on truth by convention,” Mind 102(478):193237. Reprinted in Ebbs 2017a: 57–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ebbs, G. 2011b. “Quine gets the last word,” Journal of Philosophy 108(11): 617–32. Reprinted in Ebbs 2017a: 113–27.Google Scholar
Ebbs, G. 2016. “Reading Quine’s claim that no statement is immune to revision,” in Janssen-Lauret, F. and Kemp, G. (eds.), Quine and his Place in History. Palgrave Macmillan, 123–45. Reprinted in Ebbs 2017a: 168–87.Google Scholar
Ebbs, G. 2017a. Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ebbs, G. 2017b. “Reading Quine’s claim that definitional abbreviations create synonymies,” in Ebbs, 2017a: 128–43.Google Scholar
Eddington, A. 1929. The Nature of the Physical World. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Edsall, T. 2017. “The peculiar populism of Donald Trump,” The New York Times. 2 February 2017.Google Scholar
Eells, E. 1991. Probabilistic Causality. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eggleston, B. 2014. “Act utilitarianism,” in Eggleston, B. and Millers, D. (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Utilitarianism. Cambridge University Press, 125–45.Google Scholar
Eldridge, R. 2008. Literature, Life, and Modernity. Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eliot, T. S. 1917. Prufrock and Other Observations. The Egoist.Google Scholar
Elliot, R. 1992. “Intrinsic value, environmental obligation and naturalness,” The Monist 75(2):138–60.Google Scholar
Ellis, B. 2001. Scientific Essentialism. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ellis, E. A. 2011. “Anthropogenic transformation of the terrestrial biosphere,” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences 369:1010–35.Google Scholar
Ellis, F. 2014. God, Value, and Nature. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Emerson, R. W. 1982. Selected Essays. Ed. Ziff, L.. Penguin.Google Scholar
Engstrom, S. 2002. “The inner freedom of virtue,” in Timmons, M. (ed.), Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretive Essays. Oxford University Press, 289315.Google Scholar
Engstrom, S. 2009. The Form of Practical Knowledge: A Study of the Categorical Imperative. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Enoch, D. 2015. “Against public reason,” in Sobel, D., Vallentyne, P., and Wall, S. (eds.), Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199669530.003.0006.Google Scholar
Eodice, A. 1990. “Dewey and Wittgenstein on the idea of certainty,” Philosophy Today 34(1):30–8.Google Scholar
Eribon, D. 2018. Returning to Reims. Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Evans, G. 1973. “The causal theory of names,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 47:187225.Google Scholar
Evans, G. 1982. The Varieties of Reference. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Everett, D. 2005. “Cultural constraints on grammar and cognition in Pirahã,” Current Anthropology 46(4):621–46.Google Scholar
Evernden, N. 1993 [1985]. The Natural Alien: Humankind and Environment, 2nd edition. University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fackenheim, E. 1987. Encounters between Judaism, and Modern Philosophy: A Preface to Future Jewish Thought. Schocken.Google Scholar
Fackenheim, E. 1996. Jewish Philosophers and Jewish Philosophy. Ed. Morgan, M.. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Fahmy, M. S. 2009. “Active sympathetic participation: reconsidering Kant’s duty of sympathy,” Kantian Review 14:3152.Google Scholar
Fahmy, M. S. 2010. “Kantian practical love,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 91:313–31.Google Scholar
Fairbairn, C., Wilkins, H., Kennedy, S., and Thurley, D., 2018. Polygamy. House of Commons Briefing Paper.Google Scholar
Falk, W. D. 1947–8. “‘Ought’ and motivation,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 48:111–38.Google Scholar
Fantl, J. and McGrath, M.. 2007. “On pragmatic encroachment in epistemology,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75(3):558–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farkas, K. 2003. “What is externalism?Philosophical Studies 112(3):187208.Google Scholar
Farrell, B. A. 1950. “Experience,” Mind 59:170–98.Google Scholar
Faye, E. 2009. Heidegger: The Introduction of Nazism into Philosophy. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Feagin, S. 1996. Reading with Feeling: The Aesthetics of Appreciation. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Feenberg, A. 1981. Lukacs, Marx and the Sources of Critical Theory. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Feenberg, A. 1999. Questioning Technology. Routledge.Google Scholar
Feenberg, A. 2005. “Heidegger, Marcuse and the philosophy of technology,” in Feenberg, A., The Catastrophe and Redemption of History. Routledge, n.p.Google Scholar
Feferman, S. 1984. “Useful type-free theories. I,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 49(1):75111.Google Scholar
Feferman, S. 1998. In the Light of Logic. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feigl, H. and Brodbeck, M. (eds.). 1953. Readings in the Philosophy of Science. Appleton-Century-Crofts.Google Scholar
Feinberg, W. 1995. “The communitarian challenge to liberal social and educational theory,” Peabody Journal of Education 70(4):3455.Google Scholar
Feldman, R. and Conee, E.. 1985. “Evidentialism,” Philosophical Studies 48(1):1534.Google Scholar
Fell, J. 1979. Heidegger and Sartre: An Essay on Being and Place. Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fendler, L. 1998. “What is it impossible to think? A genealogy of the educated subject,” in Popkewitz, T. and Brennan, M. (eds.), Foucault’s Challenge: Discourse, Knowledge, and Power in Education. Teachers College Press, 3963.Google Scholar
Fendler, L. 2010. Michel Foucault. Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Ferrara, A. 1993. Modernity and Authenticity: A Study of the Social and Ethical Thought of Jean-Jacques Rousseau. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, F. 1975. Against Method. Verso.Google Scholar
Figal, G. 2010. Objectivity: The Hermeneutical and Philosophy. Trans. George, Theodore. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Fine, A. 1970. “Insolubility of the quantum measurement problem,” Physical Review D. 2(12):2,783–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, A. 1986. “Unnatural attitudes: realist and instrumentalist attachments to science,” Mind 95(378):149–79.Google Scholar
Fine, K. 2001. “The question of realism,” Philosophers’ Imprint 1(2):130.Google Scholar
Fine, K. 2005. “The varieties of necessity,” in Modality and Tense: Philosophical Papers. Oxford University Press, 235–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, K. 2007. Semantic Relationism. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Fine, K. 2010. “Some puzzles of ground,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 51(1):97118.Google Scholar
Fine, K. 2012a. “Guide to ground,” in Correia, F. and Schnieder, B. (eds.), Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality. Cambridge University Press, 3780.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, K. 2012b. “The pure logic of ground,” Review of Symbolic Logic 25(1):125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, K. 2013. “Fundamental truths and fundamental terms,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 87(3):725–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, K. 2015. “Unified foundations for essence and ground,” Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1(2):296311.Google Scholar
Fine, K. 2017. “Truthmaker semantics,” in Hale, B., Wright, C., and Miller, A. (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, 2nd edition. Wiley-Blackwell, 556–77.Google Scholar
Finlayson, G. and Freyenhagen, F. (eds.). 2011. Habermas and Rawls: Disputing the Political. Routledge.Google Scholar
Finlayson, L. 2016. An Introduction to Feminism. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
von Fintel, K. 1997. “Can it be that it would have been even though it might not have been?” in Tomberlin, J. (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives 11: Mind, Causation, and World. Blackwell, 385413Google Scholar
Firth, J. R. 1957a. Papers in Linguistics 1934–1951. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Firth, J. R. 1957b. Studies in Linguistic Analysis. Oxford Philological Society.Google Scholar
Fischer, J. M. 1999. “Recent work on moral responsibility,” Ethics 110:93139.Google Scholar
Fitelson, B. 2006. “The paradox of confirmation,” Philosophy Compass 1(1):95113.Google Scholar
Flew, A. 2007. There Is a God: How the World’s Most Notorious Atheist Changed His Mind. HarperOne.Google Scholar
Flew, A. and MacIntyre, A.. 1955. New Essays in Philosophical Theology. SCM Press.Google Scholar
Floridi, L. 2011. The Philosophy of Information. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Floridi, L. 2014. The Philosophy of Information and The Fourth Revolution: How the Infosphere Is Reshaping Human Reality. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Floridi, L. and Sanders, J. W.. 2004. “On the morality of artificial agents,” Minds and Machines 14:349–79.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1968. Psychological Explanation: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Psychology. Random House.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1974. “Special sciences: or the disunity of science as a working hypothesis,” Synthese 28(2):97115.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1975. The Language of Thought: A Philosophical Study of Cognitive Psychology. Harvester Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1978. “Propositional attitudes,” The Monist 61:501–23.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1980. “Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in cognitive psychology,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3:6372.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1983. The Modularity of Mind: An Essay in Faculty Psychology. The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1987. Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1990. A Theory of Content and Other Essays. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1991. “Too hard for our kind of mind?London Review of Books 13:12.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1992. “The big idea: can there be a science of mind?” Times Literary Supplement, 3 July, 5–7.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 1995. “Review of John McDowell, Mind and World,” London Review of Books 17/8:1011. Reprinted in J. A. Fodor, In Critical Condition: Polemical Essays on Cognitive Science and the Philosophy of Mind. The MIT Press, 3–8.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 2000. The Mind Doesn’t Work That Way: The Scope and Limits of Computational Psychology. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. 2001. “Doing without what’s within: Fiona Cowie’s critique of nativism,” Mind 110(437):99148.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. and McLaughlin, B. P.. 1990. “Connectionism and the problem of systematicity: why Smolensky’s solution doesn’t work,” Cognition 35:183204.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. and Pylyshyn, Z. W.. 1988. “Connectionism and cognitive architecture: a critical analysis,” Cognition 28:371.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fogelin, R. 1997. “Quine’s limited naturalism,” Journal of Philosophy 94(11):543–63.Google Scholar
Føllesdal, D. 1982 [1969]. “Husserl's notion of noema,” Journal of Philosophy 66:680–7. Reprinted in Dreyfus and Hall 1982: 73–80.Google Scholar
Føllesdal, D. 2004 [1961]. Referential Opacity and Modal Logic. Routledge.Google Scholar
Foot, P. 1978. Virtues and Vices and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Foot, P. 1983. “Utilitarianism and the virtues,” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 57(2):273–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ford, A., Hornsby, J., and Stoutland, F. (eds.). 2011. Essays on Anscombe’s Intention. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Foreman, M. and Kanamori, A. (eds.). 2010. Handbook of Set Theory. Springer.Google Scholar
Forst, R. 2011. The Right to Justification: Elements of a Constructivist Theory of Justice. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Forster, M. N. 2011. German Philosophy of Language: From Schlegel to Hegel and Beyond. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forster, M. and Sober, E.. 1994. “How to tell when simpler, more unified, or less ad hoc theories will provide more accurate predictions,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45(1):135.Google Scholar
Fossen, T. 2008. “Agonistic critiques of liberalism,” Contemporary Political Theory 7:376–94.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1965. Madness and Civilization. Random House.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1966. Les mots et les choses. Gallimard. Trans. A. Sheridan as The Order of Things. Vintage, 1973.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1969. L’archéologie du savoir. Gallimard. Trans. A. Sheridan as The Archaeology of Knowledge. Harper & Row, 1972.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1975. Surveiller et punir. Gallimard. Trans. A. Sheridan as Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. Pantheon, 1977.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1976. Histoire de la sexualité. Gallimard. Trans. R. Hurley as The History of Sexuality, 3 vols. Vintage, 1988–90.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1977a. “Nietzsche, genealogy, history,” in Language, Counter-Memory, Practice: Selected Essays and Interviews. Trans. Brouchard, D. F.. Cornell University Press, 139–64.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1977b [1975]. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. Trans. Sheridan, A.. Random House.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1980a [1976]. The History of Sexuality, vol. 1: An Introduction. Vintage.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1980b. “Two lectures,” in Gordon, C. (ed.), Power/Knowledge. Pantheon, 78108.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1989. The Birth of the Clinic. Trans. Sheridan, A.. Routledge.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1990 [1976]. The History of Sexuality, vol. 2: The Use of Pleasure. Trans. Hurley, Robert. Random House.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1994 [1966]. The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences. Vintage.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1994a. “What is enlightenment?” in Essential Works, vol. 1. Ed. Rabinow, P.. The New Press, 3250.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1994b. “The ethics of the concern for self as a practice of freedom,” in Essential Works, vol. 1. Ed. Faubion, J.. The New Press, 281302.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1994c. “The subject and power,” in Essential Works, vol. 3. Ed. Faubion, J.. The New Press, 327–48.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1994d. “Truth and power,” in Essential Works, vol. 3. Ed. Faubion, J.. The New Press, 111–33.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1994e. “On the archaeology of the sciences: response to the epistemology circle,” in Essential Works, vol. 2. Ed. Faubion, J.. The New Press, 280–97.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1994f. “Foucault, ,” in Essential Works, vol. 2. Ed. Faubion, J.. The New Press, 459–64.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1996. “Aesthetics of experience,” in Lotringer, S. (ed.), Foucault Live. Collected Interviews, 1961–1984. Semiotext(e), 450–4.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 2000. Power, The Essential Works, vol. 3: Ed. Faubion, J., trans. Hurley, Robert. The New Press.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 2001. Fearless Speech. Ed. Pearson, J.. Semiotext(e).Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 2003. “The question of method,” in The Essential Writings. Ed. Rabinow, P. and Rose, N.. The New Press.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 2006. The Hermeneutics of the Subject. Ed. Gros, F., trans. Burchell, G.. New Picador.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 2009. The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the College de France, 1978–79. Ed. Senellart, Michel, trans. Burchell, Graham. Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Fox, R. and Swazey, J. P.. 2008. Observing Bioethics. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fox, W. 1984. “Deep ecology: a new philosophy of our time?The Ecologist 14(5,6):194200.Google Scholar
Fox, W. 1990. Toward a Transpersonal Ecology: Developing New Foundations for Environmentalism. Shambala.Google Scholar
Frankena, W. K. 1976 [1958]. “Obligation and motivation in recent moral philosophy,” in Goodpaster, K. E. (ed.), Perspectives on Morality: Essays by William K. Frankena. University of Notre Dame Press, 4973.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. 1969. “Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility,” Journal of Philosophy 66(4):829–39.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. 1978. “The problem of action,” American Philosophical Quarterly 15:157–62.Google Scholar
Franks, P. 2005. All or Nothing: Systematicity, Transcendental Arguments and Skepticism in German Idealism. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Franks, P. 2007. “From Quine to Hegel: naturalism, antirealism and Maimon’s question of quid facti,” in Hammer, E. (ed.), German Idealism: Contemporary Perspectives. Routledge, 5069.Google Scholar
Franks, P. 2008. “Serpentine naturalism and protean nihilism: transcendental philosophy in anthropological post-Kantianism, German idealism, and neo-Kantianism,” in Leiter, B. and Rosen, M. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Continental Philosophy. Oxford University Press, 243–86.Google Scholar
Franssen, M. 2013. “Analytic philosophy of technology,” in Friis, , Pedersen, , and Hendricks, 2013 [2009]: 184–8.Google Scholar
Franssen, M., Lokhorst, G.-J., and van de Poel, I.. 2015. “Philosophy of technology,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Zalta, E. N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/technology/.Google Scholar
Fraser, Nancy. 1997. Justice Interruptus: Critical Reflections on the “Postsocialist" Condition. Routledge.Google Scholar
Freddoso, A. J. 1983. The Existence and Nature of God. University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Freeland, C. 2001. But Is It Art? Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Freeland, C. 2002. The Naked and the Undead: Evil and the Appeal of Horror. Westview Press.Google Scholar
Freeland, C. 2010. Portraits and Persons. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Freeman, S. 2006. Justice and the Social Contract: Essays on Rawlsian Political Philosophy. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Frege, G. 1884. Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik, Koebner, W.. Selections trans. in Frege, 1997a: 84–129.Google Scholar
Frege, G. 1980. The Foundations of Arithmetic. Trans. Austin, J. L.. Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Frege, G. 1997a. The Frege Reader. Ed. Beaney, Michael. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Frege, G. 1997b [1892]. “On sense and reference [Über Sinn und Bedeutung],” in Frege, 1997a: 151–71.Google Scholar
Freire, P. 1970. Pedagogy of the Oppressed. Trans. Ramos, M. B.. Herder and Herder.Google Scholar
Freire, P. 1998. Pedagogy of Freedom: Ethics, Democracy, and Civic Courage. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Freud, S. 1900. The Interpretation of Dreams, in Freud, 1953–73: vols. 4–5.Google Scholar
Freud, S. 1908. “The Moses of Michelangelo,” in Freud, 1953–73: vol. 13, 210–38.Google Scholar
Freud, S. 1953–73. The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, 24 volumes. Trans. from the German under the general editorship of Strachey, James, in collaboration with Freud, Anna. Hogarth Press and the Institute of Psycho-Analysis.Google Scholar
Friedan, B. 1997 [1963]. The Feminine Mystique. W. W. Norton & Co.Google Scholar
Friedberg, R. 1957. “Two recursively enumerable sets of incomparable degrees of unsolvability,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 43:236–8.Google Scholar
Friedlander, E. 2011. “Meaning schematics in Cavell’s Kantian reading of Wittgenstein,” Revue Internationale de Philosophie 65:183–99.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. 1981. “Theoretical explanation,” in Healey, R. (ed.), Reduction, Time and Reality. Cambridge University Press, 116.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. 1983. Foundations of Space–Time Theories: Relativistic Physics and Philosophy of Science. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. 1987. “Carnap’s Aufbau reconsidered,” Noûs 21:521–45.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. 2000. A Parting of the Ways: Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger. Open Court.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. 2010. “Synthetic history reconsidered,” in Domski, M. and Dickson, M. (eds.), Discourse on a New Method. Open Court, 573813.Google Scholar
Frierson, P. 2014. Kant’s Empirical Psychology. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friis, J. K. B. O., Pedersen, S. A., and Hendricks, V. F. (eds.). 2013 [2009]. A Companion to the Philosophy of Technology. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Frontline, . 2016. “At for-profit colleges, large loans and broken promises,” USA: WGBH Educational Foundation, Public Broadcasting Corporation. www.pbs.org/wgbh/frontline/article/watch-at-for-profit-colleges-large-loans-and-broken-promises/.Google Scholar
Frost-Arnold, G. 2013. Carnap, Tarski, and Quine at Harvard: Conversations on Logic, Mathematics, and Science. Open Court.Google Scholar
Frykholm, E. 2015. “A Humean particularist virtue ethic,” Philosophical Studies 172:2,171–91.Google Scholar
Fung, Yu-lan. 1948. A Short History of Chinese Philosophy. Ed. and trans. Bodde, D.. The Free Press.Google Scholar
Fung, Yu-lan. 1952–3. A History of Chinese Philosophy, 2 vols. Trans. Bodde, D.. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gabbay, D. M., Kanamori, A., and Woods, J. H. (eds.). 2012. Handbook of the History of Logic, vol. 6: Sets and Extensions in the Twentieth Century. Elsevier.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. 1960. Wahrheit und Methode. J. C. B. Mohr. 2nd edition 1965; trans. W. Glen-Doepel as Truth and Method. Sheed & Ward, 1975; Translation revised J. Weinsheimer and D. Marshall, 1989.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. 1976. Philosophical Hermeneutics. Trans. and ed. Ling, D. E.. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. 1987. “Was ist Praxis? Die Bedingungen gesellschaftlicher Vernunft,” in Gesammelte Werke, vol. 4: Neuere Philosophie II: Probleme, Gestalten. J. C. B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck), 216–28.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. 1989. “Text and interpretation.” Trans. Schmidt, D. J. and Palmer, R.. In Dialogue and Deconstruction: The Gadamer–Derrida Encounter. Ed. Michelfelder, D. P. and Palmer, R. E.. SUNY Press, 2151.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. 1990a. Gesammelte Werke, vol. 1: Hermeneutik I: Wahrheit und Methode: Grundzüge einer philosophischen Hermeneutik. J. C. B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. 1990b. “Reply to my critics.” Trans. Leiner, G. H.. In The Hermeneutic Tradition from Ast to Ricoeur. Ed. Ormiston, G. and Schrift, A.. SUNY Press, 273–97.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. 1993. Gesammelte Werke, vol. 2: Hermeneutik II: Wahrheit und Methode: Ergänzugen, Register. J. C. B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. 1997. “Reflections on my philosophical journey.” Trans. Palmer, R. E.. In The Philosophy of Hans-Georg Gadamer. Ed. Hahn, L. E.. Open Court, 363.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. 2004 [1960]. Truth and Method, 2nd revised edition. Trans. Weinsheimer, J. and Marshall, D. G.. Continuum.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. 2007. “Hermeneutics tracking the trace.” Trans. Palmer, R. E.. In The Gadamer Reader: A Bouquet of the Later Writings. Ed. Palmer, R. E.. Northwestern University Press, 372406.Google Scholar
Galison, P. 1987. How Experiments End. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Gallie, W. B. 1964. Philosophy and the Historical Understanding. Chatto and Windus.Google Scholar
Gandy, R. 1996. “Human versus mechanical intelligence,” in Millican, P. and Clark, A. J. (eds.), Machines and Thought: The Legacy of Alan Turing. Oxford University Press, 125–36.Google Scholar
Ganeri, J. 2001a. Indian Logic: A Reader. Routledge.Google Scholar
Ganeri, J. 2001b. Philosophy in Classical India. Routledge.Google Scholar
Ganeri, J. 2007. The Concealed Art of the Soul: Theories of Self and Practices of Truth in Indian Ethics and Epistemology. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ganeri, J. 2012. The Self: Naturalism, Consciousness, and the First-Person Stance. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Garber, D. 2005. “What’s philosophical about the history of philosophy?” in Sorell, T. and Rogers, G. A. J. (eds.), Analytic Philosophy and History of Philosophy. Oxford University Press,, 129–46.Google Scholar
Garber, D. and Ayers, M. (eds.). 1998. The Cambridge History of Seventeenth-Century Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gardiner, P. 1952. The Nature of Historical Explanation. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Gardiner, P. (ed.). 1959. Theories of History. The Free Press.Google Scholar
Gardiner, P. (ed.). 1974. The Philosophy of History. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gardiner, S. 2006. “A perfect moral storm: intergenerational ethics and the problem of moral corruption,” Environmental Values 15(3):397413.Google Scholar
Gardner, S. 2007. “The limits of naturalism and the metaphysics of German idealism,” in Hammer, E. (ed.), German Idealism: Contemporary Perspectives. Routledge, 1949.Google Scholar
Garfield, J. L. 1990. “Epoche and śūnyatā: skepticism east and west,” Philosophy East and West 40(3):285307.Google Scholar
Garfield, J. L. 2002. Empty Words: Buddhist Philosophy and Cross-Cultural Interpretation. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Garfield, J. L. and Priest, G.. 2003. “Nāgārjuna and the limits of thought,” Philosophy East and West 53(1):121.Google Scholar
Garfield, J. L. and Van Norden, B.. 2016. “If philosophy won’t diversify let’s call it what it really is,”The New York Times. www.nytimes.com/2016/05/11/opinion/if-philosophy-wont-diversify-lets-call-it-whatit-really-is.html?smid=fb-share&_r=1.Google Scholar
Garrison, J. 1999. “John Dewey’s theory of practical reasoning,” Educational Philosophy and Theory 31(3): 291312.Google Scholar
Garrison, J. 2006. “The ‘permanent deposit’ of Hegelian thought in Dewey’s theory of inquiry,” Educational Theory 56(1):138.Google Scholar
Garrison, J. 2017. “Wittgenstein and classical pragmatism,” in Peters, M. A. and Stickney, J. (eds.), A Companion to Wittgenstein on Education: Pedagogical Investigations. Springer Nature, 321–8.Google Scholar
Garrison, J., Neubert, S., and Reich, K.. 2012. John Dewey’s Philosophy of Education: An Introduction and Recontextualization for Our Times. Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Gascoigne, N. 2002. Scepticism. Acumen.Google Scholar
Gatens, M. 1996. Imaginary Bodies: Ethics, Power and Corporeity. Routledge.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. 1996. Justificatory Liberalism: An Essay on Epistemology and Political Theory. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. 2011. The Order of Public Reason: A Theory of Freedom and Morality in a Diverse and Bounded World. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. 2016. “The commonwealth of bees: on the impossibility of justice-through-ethos,” Social Philosophy and Policy 33(1–2):96121.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. and Thrasher, J.. 2015. “Rational choice and the original position: the (many) models of Rawls and Harsanyi,” in Hinton, T. (ed.), The Original Position. Cambridge University Press, 3958.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. and Van Schoelandt, C.. 2017. “Consensus on what? Convergence for what? Four models of political liberalism,” Ethics 128(1):145–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaus, G. and Van Schoelandt, C.. 2015. “‘Public reason’,” in International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, 2nd edition. Elsevier.Google Scholar
Gaut, B. 2000. “‘Art’ as a cluster concept,” in Carroll, N. (ed.), Theories of Art Today. University of Wisconsin Press, 2544.Google Scholar
Gaut, B. 2005. Art, Emotion, and Ethics. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gaut, B. 2010. A Philosophy of Cinematic Art. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gaut, B. and Lopes, D. M.. 2013. The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics, 3rd edition. Routledge.Google Scholar
Geach, P. 1956. “Good and evil,” Analysis 17(2):3342.Google Scholar
Gellner, E. 1998. Language and Solitude: Wittgenstein, Malinowski, and the Hapsburg Dilemma. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
George, A. (ed.). 1989. Reflections on Chomsky. Blackwell.Google Scholar
George, T. 2009. “Günter Figal’s hermeneutics,” Philosophy Compass 4(6):904–12.Google Scholar
George, T. 2010. “Objectivity and finite transcendence: a brief overview of Günter Figal’s new direction in hermeneutics,” in Figal, G., Objectivity: The Hermeneutical and Philosophy. Trans. George, T.. State University of New York Press, xixxvi.Google Scholar
George, T. 2016. “Gadamer and German idealism,” in Keane, N. and Lawn, C. (eds.),The Blackwell Companion to Hermeneutics. John Wiley & Sons, 5462.Google Scholar
Gertler, B. 2012. “Understanding the internalism–externalism debate: what is the boundary of the thinker?Philosophical Perspectives 26:5175.Google Scholar
Gettier, E. 1963. “Is justified true belief knowledge?Analysis 23(6):121–3.Google Scholar
Geuss, R. 1994. “Nietzsche and genealogy,” European Journal of Philosophy 2(3):274–92.Google Scholar
Giere, R. 1988. Explaining Science. University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Gillies, T. 2007. “Counterfactual scorekeeping,” Linguistics and Philosophy 30:329–60.Google Scholar
Gilligan, C. 1982. In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Gillon, B. S. 1997. “Negative facts and knowledge of negative facts,” in Bilimoria, P. and Mohanty, J. (eds.), Relativism, Suffering and Beyond: Essays in Memory of Bimal K. Matilal. Oxford, 128–49.Google Scholar
Gilson, E. 2011. “Vulnerability, ignorance, and oppression,” Hypatia 26(2):308–32.Google Scholar
Ginet, C. 1990. On Action. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Giroux, H. A. 2003. “Public pedagogy and the politics of resistance: notes on a critical theory of educational struggle,” Educational Philosophy and Theory 35(1):516.Google Scholar
Giunti, M. 1997. Computation, Dynamics, and Cognition. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gjesdal, K. 2009. Gadamer and the Legacy of German Idealism. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Glendinning, S. 2004. “Philosophy as nomadism,” in Carel, H. and Gamez, D. (eds.), What Philosophy Is. Continuum, 155–67.Google Scholar
Glendinning, S. 2007. In the Name of Phenomenology. Routledge.Google Scholar
Glock, H.-J. 1996. A Wittgenstein Dictionary. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Glock, H.-J. 2008. What Is Analytic Philosophy? Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Glymour, C. 1970. “Theoretical equivalence and theoretical realism,” Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 275–88.Google Scholar
Glymour, C. 1980. Theory and Evidence. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Glymour, C., Scheines, R., Spirtes, P., and Kelly, K. T.. 1987. Discovering Causal Structure: Artificial Intelligence, Philosophy of Science and Statistical Modeling. Academic Press.Google Scholar
Gödel, K. 1931. “On formally undecidable propositions of Principia Mathematica and related systems I,” in Feferman, S., Dawson, J. W. Jr., Kleene, S. C., Moore, G., Solovay, R. N., and van Heijenoort, J. (eds.), Kurt Gödel, Collected Works, vol. 1. Clarendon Press, 144–95.Google Scholar
Gödel, K. 1940. Consistency of the Continuum Hypothesis. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gödel, K. 1948. “What is Cantor’s continuum problem?American Mathematical Monthly 9:515–25.Google Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. 2009. Darwinian Populations and Natural Selection. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. 2016. Other Minds: The Octopus, the Sea, and the Deep Origins of Consciousness. Macmillan.Google Scholar
Godlovitch, S. 1998. Musical Performance: A Philosophical Study. Routledge.Google Scholar
Godman, M. 2015. “The special science dilemma and how culture solves it,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 93(3):491508.Google Scholar
Goehr, L. 1992. The Imaginary Museum of Musical Works: An Essay in the Philosophy of Music. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Gold, E. M. 1967. “Language identification in the limit,” Information and Control 10:447–74.Google Scholar
Goldberg, S. 2003. “Anti-individualism, conceptual omniscience, and skepticism,” Philosophical Studies 116(1):5378.Google Scholar
Goldblatt, R. 2006. “Mathematical modal logic: a view of its evolution,” Journal of Applied Logic 1:309–92.Google Scholar
Goldie, P. 2010. “Virtues of art,” Philosophy Compass 5:830–9.Google Scholar
Goldie, P. and Schellekens, E.. 2009. Who’s Afraid of Conceptual Art? Routledge.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alan. 1995. Aesthetic Value. Westview Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alan. 2013. Philosophy and the Novel. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin. 1967. “A causal theory of knowing,” Journal of Philosophy 64(12):357–72.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin. 1970. A Theory of Human Action. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin. 1976. “Discrimination and perceptual knowledge,” Journal of Philosophy 73(20):771–91.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin. 1979. “What is justified belief?” in Pappas, G. (ed.), Justification and Knowledge. Reidel, 123.Google Scholar
Golomb, J. and Wistrich, R. S. (eds.). 2002. Nietzsche, Godfather of Fascism? On the Uses and Abuses of a Philosophy. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Goodman, N. 1955. Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Goodman, N. 1967. “The epistemological argument,” Synthese 17(1):23–8.Google Scholar
Goodman, N. 1968. Languages of Art. Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Goodpaster, K. 1978. “On being morally considerable,” Journal of Philosophy 75(6):308–25.Google Scholar
Gordon, C. 1994. “Introduction,” in Foucault’s Essential Works, vol. 3. Ed. Faubion, J.. The Free Press.Google Scholar
Gordon, C. 2009. “Foreword: pedagogy, psychagogy, demagogy,” in Peters, M. A., Besley, A. C., Olssen, M. E. H., Maurer, S., and Weber, S. (eds.), Governmentality Studies in Education. Sense, xixxvi.Google Scholar
Gore, J. 1992. “What we can do for you! What can ‘we’ do for ‘you’? Struggling over empowerment in critical and feminist pedagogy,” in Luke, C. and Gore, J. (eds.), Feminisms and Critical Pedagogy. Routledge, 5473.Google Scholar
Goto-Jones, C. 2005. Political Philosophy in Japan: Nishida, the Kyoto School, and Co-Prosperity. Routledge.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. 1983. “The hardening of the modern synthesis,” in Grene, M. (ed.), Dimensions of Darwinism. Cambridge University Press, 7193.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. and Lewontin, R. C.. 1979. “The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist programme,”Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences 205(1161):581–98.Google Scholar
Gracia, J. E. (ed.). 1986. Latin American Philosophy for the 20th Century: Man, Values, and the Search for Philosophical Identity. Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
Gracia, J. E. 1992. Philosophy and Its History: Issues in Philosophical Historiography. State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Gracyk, T. 1996. Rhythm and Noise: An Aesthetics of Rock Music. Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Gracyk, T. 2001. I Wanna Be Me: Rock Music and the Politics of Identity. Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Gracyk, T. 2007. Listening to Popular Music: Or, How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Led Zeppelin. University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Graham, A. C. 1989. Disputers of the Tao. Open Court.Google Scholar
Graham, L. 2009. “The Special Branch: governing mentalities through alternative-site placement,” in Peters, M. A., Besley, A. C., Olssen, M. E. H., Maurer, S., and Weber, S. (eds.), Governmentality Studies in Education. Sense, 355–68.Google Scholar
Gray, J. 2000. Two Faces of Liberalism. Polity Press.Google Scholar
Greco, J. 1999. “Agent reliabilism,” Philosophical Perspectives 13:273–96.Google Scholar
Greco, J. 2003. “Knowledge as credit for true belief,” in DePaul, M. and Zagzebski, L. (eds.), Intellectual Virtue. Oxford University Press, 111–34.Google Scholar
Greco, J. 2010. Achieving Knowledge: A Virtue-Theoretic Account of Epistemic Normativity. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Green, K. 1996. “Two distinctions in environmental goodness,” Environmental Values 51(1):3146.Google Scholar
Green, T. 1968. “A topology of the teaching concept,” in MacMillan, C. J. B. and Nelson, T. W. (eds.), Concepts of Teaching. Rand McNally, 71–8.Google Scholar
Gregor, M. 1963. The Laws of Freedom. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Gregory, R. 1987. “In defence of artificial intelligence – a reply to John Searle,” in Blakemore, C. and Greenfield, S. (eds.), Mindwaves. Blackwell, 235–46.Google Scholar
Grenberg, J. 2013. Kant’s Defense of Common Moral Experience: A Phenomenological Account. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Grene, M. 1958. “Two evolutionary theories,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 9(34):110–27.Google Scholar
Grene, M. 1968. Approaches to a Philosophical Biology. Basic Books.Google Scholar
Grene, M. 1989. “Interaction and evolution,” in Ruse, M. (ed.), What the Philosophy of Biology Is: Essays Dedicated to David Hull. Reidel, 6773.Google Scholar
Grene, M. 1990. “Evolution, typology, and population thinking,” American Philosophical Quarterly 27:237–44.Google Scholar
Grene, M. and Depew, D.. 2004. The Philosophy of Biology: An Episodic History. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Grice, P. 1967. Logic and Conversation, the William James Lectures at Harvard University. Reprinted in Grice 1989.Google Scholar
Grice, P. 1989. Studies in the Way of Words. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Grice, P. and Strawson, P. F.. 1956. “In defense of a dogma,” Philosophical Review 65(2):141–58.Google Scholar
Griffiths, Paul. 1986. On Being Mindless: Buddhist Meditation and the Mind–Body Problem. Open Court.Google Scholar
Griffiths, Paul E. 1999. “Squaring the circle: natural kinds with historical essences,” in Wilson, R. A. (ed.), Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays. The MIT Press, 209–28.Google Scholar
Griffiths, Paul E. and Gray, R. D.. 1994. “Developmental systems and evolutionary explanation,” Journal of Philosophy 91(6):277304.Google Scholar
Grondin, J. 1993. The Philosophy of Gadamer. Trans. Plant, K.. McGill-Queen’s University Press.Google Scholar
Grondin, J. 1994. Introduction to Philosophical Hermeneutics. Trans. Weinsheimer, J.. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Grondin, J. 2003. Hans-Georg Gadamer: A Biography. Trans. Weinsheimer, J.. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Grondin, J. 2015. “Ricoeur: the long way of hermeneutics,” in Malpas, J. and Gander, H.-H. (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Hermeneutics. Routledge, 149–59.Google Scholar
Grosz, E. 1993. Volatile Bodies. Routledge.Google Scholar
Grosz, E. 2017. The Incorporeal: Ontology, Ethics, and the Limits of Materialism. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Gruen, L. 2015. Entangled Empathy: An Alternative Ethic for Our Relationships with Animals. Lantern Books.Google Scholar
Grünbaum, A. 1963. Philosophical Problems of Space and Time. Reidel.Google Scholar
Guarino, T. 2009. Vattimo and Theology. T & T Clark.Google Scholar
Guay, R. 2006. “The philosophical function of genealogy,” in Pearson, K. A. (ed.), A Companion to Nietzsche. Blackwell, 353–71.Google Scholar
Guignon, C. 2008. “Authenticity,” Philosophy Compass 3(2):277–90.Google Scholar
Guignon, C. and Aho, K.. 2017. “Alienation and belongingness,” in Polt, R. and Fried, G. (eds.), After Heidegger? Rowman & Littlefield, 169–78.Google Scholar
Guignon, C. and Pereboom, D. (eds.). 1995. Existentialism: Basic Writings. Hackett.Google Scholar
Gupta, B. 2003. CIT: Consciousness. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gutting, G. 1989. Michel Foucault’s Archaeology of Scientific Reason. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Guyer, P. 1987. Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: Critical Essays. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Guyer, P. 2000. Kant on Freedom, Law, and Happiness. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Guyer, P. 2007. Kant’s Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals: A Reader’s Guide. Continuum.Google Scholar
Guyer, P. 2014. A History of Modern Aesthetics. Cambridge University Press, 3 vols.Google Scholar
Haakonssen, K. (ed.). 2006. The Cambridge History of Eighteenth-Century Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. 1979. Communication and the Evolution of Society. Trans. McCarthy, T.. Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. 1984. The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. 1: Reason and the Rationalization of Society. Trans. McCarthy, T.. Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. 1989. The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. 2: Lifeworld and System. Trans. McCarthy, T.. Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. 1990a. “The hermeneutic claim to universality.” Trans. Leiner, G. H.. In Ormiston, G. and Schrift, A. (eds.), The Hermeneutic Tradition from Ast to Ricoeur. SUNY Press, 245–72.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. 1990b. Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Trans. Lenhardt, C. and Nicholson, S. Weber. Polity Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. 1992a. Autonomy and Solidarity. Verso.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. 1992b. Postmetaphysical Thinking: Philosophical Essays. Trans. Hohengarten, W.. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. 1993. Justification and Application: Remarks on Discourse Ethics. Trans. Cronin, C.. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. 1995. “Reconciliation through the public use of reason: remarks on John Rawls’s political liberalism,” Journal of Philosophy 92:109–31.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. 1997. “Modernity: an unfinished project,” in d’Entréves, M. P. and Benhabib, S. (eds.), Habermas and the Unfinished Project of Modernity. The MIT Press, 3857.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. 1998. Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Trans. Rehg, W.. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. 2011. “A reply to my critics,” in Finlayson, G. and Freyenhagen, F. (eds.), Habermas and Rawls: Disputing the Political. Routledge, 320.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. 1993. Wittgenstein, Meaning and Mind. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. 1975. The Emergence of Probability. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. (ed.). 1981. Scientific Revolutions. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. 1983. Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural Science. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. 1990. The Taming of Chance. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. 1999. The Social Construction of What? Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hagberg, G. L. 1994. Meaning and Interpretation: Wittgenstein, Henry James, and Literary Knowledge. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Hahn, H. 1933. Logik, Mathematik und Naturerkennen. Gerold. Trans. Pap, A. as “Logic, mathematics, and knowledge of nature,” in Ayer, 1959: 147–61.Google Scholar
Hailwood, S. 2015. Alienation and Nature in Environmental Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hajek, A. MS. “Most counterfactuals are false.”Google Scholar
Hájek, P. and Pudlák, P.. 1993. Metamathematics of First-Order Arithmetic. Springer.Google Scholar
Hall, E. 2015. “Bernard Williams and the basic legitimation demand: a defence,” Political Studies 63:466–80.Google Scholar
Hallward, P. and Peden, K. (eds.). 2012. Concept and Form, vol. 1: Key Texts from the “Cahiers pour l’Analyse. Verso.Google Scholar
Hamilton, A. 2007. Aesthetics and Music. Continuum.Google Scholar
Hamilton, J. R. 2008. Art of Theater. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hamilton, W. D. 1964. “The genetical evolution of social behaviour II,” Journal of Theoretical Biology 7(1):1752.Google Scholar
Hamlyn, D. W. 1970. “Status of the mental,” Times Literary Supplement 2 December, 152; published anonymously.Google Scholar
Hamlyn, D. W. 1992. Being a Philosopher: The History of a Practice. Routledge.Google Scholar
Hampshire, S. 1959. Thought and Action. Chatto and Windus.Google Scholar
Hanke, L. 1994. All Mankind Is One: A Study of the Disputation between Bartolomé de Las Casas and Juan Ginés de Sepúlveda in 1550 on the Intellectual and Religious Capacity of the American Indians. Northern Illinois University Press.Google Scholar
Hanks, P. 2015. Propositional Content. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hansen, C. 1992. A Daoist Theory of Chinese Thought. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hansen, D. T. 2010. “Cosmopolitanism and education: a view from the ground,” Teachers College Record 112(1):130.Google Scholar
Hanson, N. E. 1958. Patterns of Discovery. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Haraway, D. 1991. Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention of Nature. Free Association Books. (Includes the 1985 essay: “A cyborg manifesto: science, technology, and socialist-feminism in the late twentieth century.”)Google Scholar
Hardin, C. L. and Rosenberg, A.. 1982. “In defence of convergent realism,” Philosophy of Science 49:604–15.Google Scholar
Harding, S. G. (ed.). 1976. Can Theories Be Refuted? Springer.Google Scholar
Harding, S. G. 1986. “Women, reason and nature,” International Studies in Philosophy 18(1):101–2.Google Scholar
Harding, S. G. and Hintikka, M. B. (eds.). 2003. Discovering Reality: Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science. Kluwer Academic.Google Scholar
Hare, C. 2013. The Limits of Kindness. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1952. The Language of Morals. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1960. “A school for philosophers,” Ratio 2(2):107–20.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1981. Moral Thinking: Its Levels, Method, and Point. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Harker, D. 2008. “On the predilections for predictions,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 59:429–53.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1965. “Inference to the best explanation,” Philosophical Review 74:8895.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1973. Thought. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Harman, G. (ed). 1974. On Noam Chomsky: Critical Essays. Anchor.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1975. “Reasons,” Crítica 7(21):317.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1990a. “Immanent and transcendent approaches to the theory of meaning,” in Gibson, R. and Barrett, R. B. (eds.), Perspectives on Quine. Blackwell, 144–57. Reprinted as ‘Immanent and transcendent approaches to meaning and mind’ in Harman 1999.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1990b. “The intrinsic quality of experience,” in Tomberlin, J. (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, vol. 4: Action Theory and the Philosophy of Mind. Ridgeview, 3152.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1996. “Analyticity regained?Noûs 30:392400.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1999. Reasoning, Meaning, and Mind. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Harrington, L. A., Morley, M. D., Cedrov, A., and Simpson, S. G. (eds.). 1985. Harvey Friedman’s Research on the Foundations of Mathematics. Elsevier.Google Scholar
Harris, Z. S. 1951. Methods in Structural Linguistics. University of Chicago Press. (Republished 1960 as Structural Linguistics.)Google Scholar
Harris, Z. S. 1954. “Transfer grammar,” International Journal of American Linguistics 20:259–70.Google Scholar
Harrison, C. and Wood, P. (eds.). 2003. Art in Theory 1900–2000: An Anthology of Changing Ideas, 2nd edition. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Harttman, H. 1979. “The unhappy marriage of Marxism and feminism: towards a more progressive union,” Capital and Class 3(2):133.Google Scholar
Hasker, W. 1989. God, Time, and Knowledge. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Hatab, L. 2000. Ethics and Finitude: Heideggerian Contributions to Moral Philosophy. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Haugeland, J. 1978. “The nature and plausibility of cognitivism,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1:215–26.Google Scholar
Haugeland, J. 1985. Artificial Intelligence: The Very Idea. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Haugeland, J. 1995. “Mind embodied and embedded,” in Young, T.-H. and Ho, J.-C. (eds.), Mind and Cognition. Academia Sinica, 338.Google Scholar
Haugeland, J. 1996. “Body and world: a review of What Computers Still Can’t Do (Hubert L. Dreyfus),” Artificial Intelligence 80:119–28.Google Scholar
Haugeland, J. 1998a. Having Thought: Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Haugeland, J. 1998b. “The intentionality all-stars,” in Haugeland 1998a: 127–70.Google Scholar
Hawking, S. 2002. On the Shoulders of Giants: The Great Works of Physics and Astronomy. Penguin.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, J. 2004. Knowledge and Lotteries. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, J. 2005. “The case for closure,” in Sosa, E. and Steup, M. (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology. Blackwell, 2643.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, J. 2006. “Direct reference and dancing qualia,” in Alter, T. and Walter, S. (eds.), Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism. Oxford University Press, 195209.Google Scholar
Hayes, R. 1988. Dignāga on the Interpretation of Signs. Kluwer Academic.Google Scholar
Heal, J. 1986. “Replication and functionalism,” in Butterfield, J. (ed.), Language, Mind, and Logic. Cambridge University Press, 135–50. Reprinted in Heal 2003: 11–27.Google Scholar
Heal, J. 2003. Mind, Reason, and Imagination. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Heath, S. 1981. Questions of Cinema. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. 1977 [1807]. Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit. Trans. Miller, A. V.. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1959. Discourse on Thinking: A Translation of Gelassenheit. Trans. Anderson, J. and Freund, E.. Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1962a [1927]. Being and Time. Trans. Macquarrie, J. and Robinson, E.. SCM Press.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1962b. Die Technik und die Kehre. Günther Neske.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1969 [1957]. Identity and Difference. Trans. Stambough, J.. Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1971. On the Way to Language. Trans. Hertz, P. D.. Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1976a. Gesamtausgabe, vol. 9: Wegmarken. Vittorio Klostermann. Trans. McNeill, W., Pathmarks. Cambridge University Press, 1998.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1976b [1963]. “My way to phenomenology,” in Heidegger, M., On Time and Being. Ed. Stambaugh, J.. Harper & Row, 7482.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1977a. Gesamtausgabe, vol. 5: Holzwege. Vittorio Klostermann. Trans. J. Young and K. Haynes, Off the Beaten Track. Cambridge University Press, 2002.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1977b. The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays. Trans. Lovitt, W.. Harper.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1978. Gesamtausgabe, vol. 26: Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Logik im Ausgang von Leibniz. Vittorio Klostermann. Trans. M. Heim, The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic. Indiana University Press, 1984.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1981a. Gesamtausgabe, vol. 4: Erläuterungen zu Hölderlins Dichtung. Vittorio Klostermann. Trans. K. Hoeller, Elucidations of Hölderlin’s Poetry. Humanity Books, 2000.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1981b [1931]. Gesamtausgabe, vol. 33: Aristoteles, Metaphysik Theta 1–3. Von Wesen und Wirklichkeit der Kraft. Ed. Hüni, H.. Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1981c. “Only a God can save us,” trans. Richardson, W. J.. In Sheehan, T. (ed.), Heidegger: The Man and the Thinker. Transaction, 4567.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1982 [1941–2]. Gesamtausgabe, vol. 52: Hölderlins Hymne “Andenken.” Ed. Ochwaldt, C.. Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1983 [1935/53]. Gesamtausgabe, vol. 40: Einführung in die Metaphysik. Ed. Jaeger, P.. Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1987. Nietzsche: The Will to Power as Knowledge and as Metaphysics. Ed. Krell, D. F., trans. Stambaugh, J., Krell, D. F., and Capuzzi, F.. Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1994a [1923–24]. Gesamtausgabe, vol. 17: Einführung in die phänomenologische Forschung. Ed. von Herrmann, F.-W.. Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1994b. Gesamtausgabe, vol. 79: Bremer und Freiburger Vorträge. Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1995a. Aristotle’s Metaphysics Theta 1–3: On the Essence and Actuality of Force. Trans. by Brogan, W. and Warnek, P.. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1995b. Gesamtausgabe, vol. 60: Phänomenologie des religiösen Lebens. Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1996a [1927]. Being and Time. Trans. Stambaugh, J.. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1996b [1936–39]. Gesamtausgabe, vol. 6.1: Nietzsche I. Ed. Schillbach, B.. Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1997a [1939–46]. Gesamtausgabe, vol. 6.2: Nietzsche: Zweiter Band. Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1997b. The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays. Trans. Lovitt, W.. Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1998. Pathmarks. Ed. McNeill, W.. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 2000a. Gesamtausgabe, vol. 7: Vorträge und Aufsätze. Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 2000b. Gesamtausgabe, vol. 75: Zu Hölderlin. Griechenlandreisen. Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 2001. Poetry, Language, Thought. Trans. Hofstadter, A.. Harper.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 2002 [1946]. Off the Beaten Track. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 2002 [1951–52]. Gesamtausgabe, vol. 8: Was Heißt Denken? Ed. Coriando, P.-L.. Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 2003 [1924–25]. Plato’s Sophist. Trans. Rojcewicz, R. and Schuwer, A.. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 2010 [1944–45]. Country Path Conversations. Trans. Davis, Bret W.. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. 2012. Bremen and Freiburg Lectures. Trans. Mitchell, A.. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Hein, H. and Korsmeyer, C. (eds.). 1993. Aesthetics in Feminist Perspective. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Heine, S. 2008. Zen Skin, Zen Marrow: Will the Real Zen Buddhism Please Stand Up? Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Heisig, J. W. 2001. Philosophers of Nothingness: An Essay on the Kyoto School. University of Hawai‘i Press.Google Scholar
Heisig, J. W., Kasulis, T., and Maraldo, J. C. (eds.). 2011. Japanese Philosophy: A Sourcebook. University of Hawai‘i Press.Google Scholar
Heisig, J. W. and Maraldo, J. C. (eds.). 1995. Rude Awakenings: Zen, the Kyoto School, and the Question of Nationalism. University of Hawai‘i Press.Google Scholar
Held, V. 2006. The Ethics of Care: Personal, Political, and Global. Oxford University Press on Demand.Google Scholar
Hellie, B. 2005. “Noise and perceptual indiscriminability,” Mind 114:481508.Google Scholar
Hellie, B. 2010. “An externalist’s guide to inner experience,” in Nanay, B. (ed.), Perceiving the World. Oxford University Press, 97145.Google Scholar
Hellie, B. 2013. “Against egalitarianism,” Analysis 73:304–20.Google Scholar
Hellie, B. 2014. “Love in the time of cholera,” in Brogaard, B. (ed.), Does Perception Have Content? Oxford University Press, 242–62.Google Scholar
Hellie, B. 2016. “Rationalization and the Ross Paradox,” in Charlow, N. and Chrisman, M. (eds.), Deontic Modality. Oxford University Press, 283323.Google Scholar
Hellie, B. 2017. “David Lewis and the kangaroo: graphing philosophical progress,” in Blackford, R. and Broderick, D. (eds.), Philosophy’s Future: The Problem of Philosophical Progress. John Wiley & Sons, 213–26.Google Scholar
Hellie, B. 2018. “Praxeology, imperatives, and shifts of view,” in Stout, R. (ed.), Process, Action, and Experience. Oxford University Press, 185209.Google Scholar
Hellie, B. forthcoming. “Semantic gaps and protosemantics,” in de Barros, A. and Montemayor, C. (eds.), Quanta and Mind. Springer.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. 1942. “The function of general laws in history,” Journal of Philosophy 39(2):3548. Reprinted in Gardiner 1959: 344–56.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. 1945. “Studies in the logic of confirmation,” Mind 54(213):126.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. 1950. “Problems and changes in the empiricist criterion of meaning,” Revue Internationale de Philosophie 41:4163. Reprinted in Ayer 1959: 60–81.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. 1952. Fundamentals of Concept Formation in Empirical Science. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. 1963. “Implications of Carnap’s work for the philosophy of science,” in Schilpp 1963: 685–709.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. 1965. Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. 1966. Philosophy of Natural Science. Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. and Oppenheim, P.. 1948. “Studies in the logic of explanation,” Philosophy of Science 15:135–75.Google Scholar
Henne, P., Pinillos, A., and De Brigard, F.. 2017. “Cause by omission and norm: not watering plants,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95(2):270–83.Google Scholar
Herman, B. 1981. “On the value of acting from the motive of duty,” Philosophical Review 90:359–82. Reprinted in Herman 1996: 1–22.Google Scholar
Herman, B. 1996. The Practice of Moral Judgment. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Herman, B. 2007. Moral Literacy. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hershock, P. 1999. Reinventing the Wheel: A Buddhist Response to the Information Age. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Hershock, P. 2014. Public Zen, Personal Zen: A Buddhist Introduction. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Hershowitz, R. 2000. “A mere modus vivendi?” In Davion, V. and Wolfe, C. (eds.), The Idea of a Political Liberalism. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Hess, A. 2017. “How a fractious women’s movement came to lead the Left,” The New York Times Sunday Magazine, 7 February.Google Scholar
Hesse, M. 1961. Forces and Fields. Philosophical Library.Google Scholar
Hesse, M. 1963. Models and Analogies in Science. Sheed and WardGoogle Scholar
Hesse, M. 1980. “A revised regularity view of scientific laws,” in Mellor, D. H. (ed.), Science, Belief and Behaviour. Cambridge University Press, 87104.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. C. 2001. Good Knowledge, Bad Knowledge. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hetherington, S. C. 2016. Knowledge and the Gettier Problem. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Heyes, C. 2012. “Grist and mills: on the cultural origins of cultural learning,” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 367(1,599):2,181–91.Google Scholar
Heyting, A. 1930. “Die formalen Regeln der intuitionistichen Logik,” Sitzungsberichte der Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften I , II, III:4256, 57–71, 158–69.Google Scholar
Hick, J. 1960. “Theology and verification,” Theology Today 17(1):1231.Google Scholar
Hick, J. 1964. The Existence of God. Macmillan.Google Scholar
Hick, J. 1966. Evil and the God of Love. Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Hick, J. 1970. Classical and Contemporary Readings in the Philosophy of Religion. 2nd edition. Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Hickman, L. A. 1998. Reading Dewey: Interpretations for a Postmodern Generation. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Hickman, L. A. 2007. Pragmatism as Post-Postmodernism: Lessons from John Dewey. Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
Hickman, L., Neibert, S., and Reich, K. (eds.). 2009. John Dewey between Pragmatism and Constructivism. Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
Higginbotham, J. 1991. “Remarks on the metaphysics of linguistics,” Linguistics and Philosophy 14(5):555–66.Google Scholar
Higgins, K. M. 1991. The Music of Our Lives. Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Higgins, K. M. 2012. The Music between Us. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hill, A. A. 1962. Third Texas Conference on Problems of Linguistic Analysis in English. University of Texas.Google Scholar
Hill, T. E. Jr. 1991. Autonomy and Self-Respect. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hill, T. E. Jr. 1992. Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant’s Moral Theory. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Hill, T. E. Jr. 2000. Respect, Pluralism, and Justice: Kantian Perspectives. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hill, T. E. Jr. 2008. “Kantian virtue and ‘virtue ethics’,” in Betzler, 2008: 29–60.Google Scholar
Hill, T. E. Jr. 2012. Virtue, Rules, and Justice: Kantian Aspirations. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hill, T. E. Jr. and Zweig, A. (eds.). 2003. Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hintikka, J. 1961. “Modalities and quantification,” Theoria 27:119–28.Google Scholar
Hirsch, E.D. Jr. 1967. Validity in Interpretation. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Hirst, P. 1965. “Liberal education and the nature of knowledge,” in Archamabult, R. D. (ed.), Philosophical Analysis and Education. The Humanities Press, 113–38.Google Scholar
Hirst, P. 1971. “What is teaching?Journal of Curriculum Studies 3(1):518.Google Scholar
Hirst, P. and Peters, R. S.. 1970. The Logic of Education. Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Hitchcock, C. 2001. “The intransitivity of causation revealed in equations and graphs,” Journal of Philosophy 98:273–99.Google Scholar
Hitchcock, C. 2007. “Three concepts of causation,” Philosophy Compass 2(3):508–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hitchcock, C. 2011. “Trumping and contrastive causation,” Synthese 181(2):227–40.Google Scholar
Hobbs, C. A. 2008. “Dewey, Wittgenstein, and contextualist epistemology,” Southwest Philosophy Review 24(2):7185.Google Scholar
Hockett, C. F. 1948. “A note on ‘structure’,” International Journal of American Linguistics 14:269–71. Reprinted in Joos 1957: 279–80.Google Scholar
Hockett, C. F. 1954. “Two models of grammatical description,” Word 10:210–31. Reprinted in Joos 1957: 386–99.Google Scholar
Hockett, C. F. 1958. A Course in Modern Linguistics. Macmillan.Google Scholar
Hoefer, C. and Rosenberg, A.. 1994. “Empirical equivalence, underdetermination, and systems of the world,” Philosophy of Science 61(4):592607.Google Scholar
Hoerl, C., McCormack, T., and Beck, S. R. (eds.). 2012. Understanding Counterfactuals, Understanding Causation: Issues in Philosophy and Psychology. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Höffe, O. (ed.). 1989. “Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten”: Ein Kooperativer Kommentar. Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Hofweber, T. 2009. “Ambitious, yet modest, metaphysics,” in Chalmers, D., Manley, D., and Wasserman, R. (eds.), Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Oxford University Press, 260–89.Google Scholar
Honenberger, P. 2015. “Grene and Hull on types and typological thinking in biology,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science (Part C) 50:1325.Google Scholar
Honig, B. 1993. Political Theory and the Displacement of Politics. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Honneth, A. 1995. The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts. Trans. Anderson, J.. Polity Press.Google Scholar
Honneth, A. 2007. Disrespect: The Normative Foundations of Critical Theory. Polity Press.Google Scholar
Honneth, A. 2010. The Pathologies of Individual Freedom: Hegel’s Social Theory. Trans. Löb, L.. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Honneth, A. 2012. The I in We: Studies in the Theory of Recognition. Trans. Ganahl, J.. Polity Press.Google Scholar
Honneth, A. 2014. Freedom’s Right: The Social Foundations of Democratic Life. Trans. Ganahl, J.. Polity Press.Google Scholar
Hook, S. (ed.). 1963. Philosophy and History: A Symposium. New York University Press.Google Scholar
Hooker, B. 2000. Ideal Code, Real World: A Rule-Consequentialist Theory of Morality. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hooker, B. 2014. “Utilitarianism and fairness,” in Eggleston, B. and Miller, D. (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Utilitarianism. Cambridge University Press, 280302.Google Scholar
hooks, bell. 1994. “Engaged pedagogy,” in Teaching to Transgress: Education as the Practice of Freedom. Routledge, 1322.Google Scholar
hooks, bell. 2000. “Black women: shaping feminist theory,” in James, J. and Sharpley-Whiting, T. D. (eds.), The Black Feminism Reader. Blackwell, 131–45.Google Scholar
Hookway, C. 1988. Quine. Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Hookway, C. 2016. “Pragmatism,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Zalta, E. N.. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2016/entries/pragmatism/.Google Scholar
Hopkins, R. 1998. Picture, Image, and Experience: A Philosophical Inquiry. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. 1993. “From supervenience to superdupervenience: meeting the demands of a material world,” Mind 102:555–86.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. and Tienson, J.. 2002. “The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality,” in Chalmers, D. (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. Oxford University Press, 4355.Google Scholar
Horkheimer, M. 1947. Eclipse of Reason. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Horkheimer, M. 1974. Eclipse of Reason. Continuum.Google Scholar
Horkheimer, M. 1982. Critical Theory: Selected Essays. Various trans. Continuum.Google Scholar
Horkheimer, M. 1993. Between Philosophy and Social Science: Selected Early Writings. Trans. Hunter, G. Frederick, Kramer, M. S., and Torpey, J.. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Horkheimer, M. and Adorno, T.. 2002 [1947]. Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments. Ed. Jephcott, E., trans. Noerr, G. S.. Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Hornsby, J. 1980. Actions. Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Hornsby, J. 1998. “Dualism in action,” Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 43:377401.Google Scholar
Hornsby, J. 2012. “Actions and activity,” Philosophical Issues. A Supplement to Noûs, Action Theory, 233–45.Google Scholar
Horton, J. 2003. “Rawls, public reason, and the limits of liberal justification,” Contemporary Political Theory 2:523.Google Scholar
Horton, J. 2010. “Realism, liberal moralism and a political theory of modus vivendi,” European Journal of Political Theory 9:431–48.Google Scholar
Horwich, P. 1982. Probability and Evidence. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Horwich, P. 2008. “Being and truth,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 32:258–73. Reprinted in E. J. Lowe and A Rami (eds.), Truth, Meaning, and Reality. McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2009, 185–200.Google Scholar
Householder, F. 1952. “Review of Zellig Harris, Methods in Structural Linguistics,” International Journal of American Linguistics 18(4):260–8.Google Scholar
Howard-Snyder, D. 1996. The Evidential Argument from Evil. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Howard-Snyder, D. and Moser, P. (eds.). 2002. Divine Hiddenness: New Essays. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Howson, C. and Urbach, P.. 1989. Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach. Open Court.Google Scholar
Hrdy, S. 1986. “Empathy, polyandry, and the myth of the coy female,” in Bleier, Ruth (ed.), Feminist Approaches to Science. Pergamon Press, 119–46.Google Scholar
Hu, S. 1919. Outline of the History of Chinese Philosophy. Beijing.Google Scholar
Hubbard, J. and Swanson, P. L.. 1997. Pruning the Bodhi Tree: The Storm over Critical Buddhism. University of Hawai‘i Press.Google Scholar
Hull, D. L. 1965. “The effect of essentialism on taxonomy – two thousand years of stasis (I),” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 15(60):314–26.Google Scholar
Hull, D. L. 1976. “Are species really individuals?Systematic Zoology 25(2):174–91.Google Scholar
Hull, D. L. 1988. Science as a Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social and Conceptual Development of Science. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1975 [1738]. A Treatise of Human Nature. Ed. Selby-Bigge, L. A.. 2nd edition revised by Nidditch, P. H.. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hunter, I. 1994. Rethinking the School: Subjectivity, Bureaucracy, Criticism. George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Hurka, T. 2001. Virtue, Vice and Value. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hurka, T. 2014. British Ethical Theorists from Sidgwick to Ewing. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hurley, P. 2009. Beyond Consequentialism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hursthouse, R. 1999. On Virtue Ethics. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hursthouse, R. 2007. “Environmental virtue ethics,” in Walker, R. L. and Ivanhoe, P. J. (eds.), Environmental Ethics. Oxford University Press, 155–72.Google Scholar
Hursthouse, R. 2011. “What does the Aristotelian phronimos know?” in Jost, L. and Wuerth, J. (eds.), Perfecting Virtue: New Essays on Kantian Ethics and Virtue Ethics. Cambridge University Press, 3857.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. 2001 [1900–1]. Logical Investigations, vols. 1 and 2. Trans. Findlay, J. N., ed. and revised Moran, D.. Routledge.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. 2014 [1913]. Ideas for a Pure Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy, First Book: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. Trans. Dahlstrom, D. O.. Hackett.Google Scholar
Hylton, P. 1990. Russell, Idealism and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hylton, P. 1993. “Hegel and analytic philosophy,” in Beiser, F. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Hegel. Cambridge University Press, 445–85.Google Scholar
Hylton, P. 2007. Quine. Routledge.Google Scholar
Hyman, J. 1999. “How knowledge works,” Philosophical Quarterly 49:433–51.Google Scholar
Hyman, J. 2006. The Objective Eye: Colour, Form and Reality in the Theory of Art. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hyman, J. 2015. Action, Knowledge, and Will. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ihde, D. 1990. Technology and the Lifeworld. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Ihde, D. 1993. Postphenomenology: Essays in the Postmodern Context. Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Ihde, D. 1998. Expanding Hermeneutics: Visualism in Science. Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Ihde, D. 2009. Postphenomenology and Technoscience: The Peking University Lectures. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Ihde, D. 2010a. Embodied Technics. Automatic Press/VIP.Google Scholar
Ihde, D. 2010b. Heidegger’s Technologies: Postphenomenological Perspectives. Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
Ihde, D. 2012. Experimental Phenomenology: Multistabilities, expanded 2nd edition. State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Ihde, D. 2015. Acoustic Technics. Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Ihde, D. 2016. Husserl’s Missing Technologies. Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
Ihde, D. and Selinger, E.. 2003. Chasing Technoscience: Matrix for Materiality. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Imai, Y. 2003. “Walter Benjamin and John Dewey: the structure of difference between their thoughts on education,” Journal of Philosophy of Education 37:109–25.Google Scholar
Ingarden, R. 1986. The Work of Music and the Problem of Its Identity. Trans. Czerniawski, A.. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Ingarden, R. 1989. Ontology of the Work of Art. Trans. Meyer, R. with Goldthwait, J. T.. Ohio University Press.Google Scholar
Irigaray, L. 1985. This Sex Which Is Not One. Trans. Porter, C.. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Irigaray, L. 1993. An Ethics of Sexual Difference. Trans. Burke, C. and Gill, G. C.. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Irigaray, L. 1999. The Forgetting of Air in Martin Heidegger. Trans. Mader, M. B.. University of Texas Press.Google Scholar
Irvin, S. (ed.). 2016. Body Aesthetics. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Irzik, G. and Meyer, E.. 1987. “Causal modeling: new directions for statistical explanation,” Philosophy of Science 54:495514.Google Scholar
Iseminger, G. 2004. The Aesthetic Function of Art. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Itkonen, E. 1978. Grammatical Theory and Metascience. Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Ivanhoe, P. J. 2000. Confucian Moral Self Cultivation. Hackett.Google Scholar
Izutsu, Toshihiko. 1983. Sufism and Taoism: A Comparative Study of Key Philosophical Concepts. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Izutsu, Toshihiko. 2001. Toward a Philosophy of Zen Buddhism. Shambhala Publications.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. 1977. Perception: A Representative Theory. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. 1982. “Epiphenomenal qualia,” Philosophical Quarterly 32:127–36.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. 1986. “What Mary didn’t know,” Journal of Philosophy 83:191–5.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. 1998. From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defense of Conceptual Analysis. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. 2004. “Mind and illusion,” in Ludlow, P., Nagasawa, Y., and Stoljar, D. (eds.), There’s Something about Mary: Essays on Phenomenal Consciousness and Frank Jackson’s Knowledge Argument. The MIT Press, 421–42.Google Scholar
Jaeggi, R. 2009. “Rethinking ideology,” in de Bruin, B. and Zurn, C. F. (eds.), New Waves in Political Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, 6386.Google Scholar
James, William. 1975 [1907]. Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking, in The Works of William James, 18 vols. Ed. Burkhard, F. H. et al. Harvard University Press. vol. 1.Google Scholar
Jamieson, D. 2007. “When utilitarians should be virtue ethicists,” Utilitas 19(2):160–83.Google Scholar
Jammer, M. 1974. The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics. Wiley.Google Scholar
Janzen, G. 2008. The Reflexive Nature of Consciousness. John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Javier-Castellanos, A. 2014. “Some challenges to a contrastive treatment of grounding,” Thought 3(3):184–92.Google Scholar
Jaynes, E. T. 1968. “Prior probabilities,” IEEE Transactions on Systems and Cybernetics 3:227–41.Google Scholar
Jaynes, E. T. 2003. Probability Theory: The Logic of Science. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R. 1983. The Logic of Decision. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Jenkins, C. 2011. “Is metaphysical grounding irreflexive?The Monist 94(2):267–76.Google Scholar
Jensen, A. K. 2013. Nietzsche’s Philosophy of History. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Jesperson, B. 2010. “How hyper are hyper propositions?Language and Linguistics Compass 39:296–30.Google Scholar
Jesperson, B. 2012. “Recent work on structured meaning and propositional unity,” Philosophy Compass 7:620–30.Google Scholar
Jesperson, B. 2015. “Should propositions proliferate?Thought 4(4):243–51.Google Scholar
Johnson, H. M. 2003. “Unspeakable conversations,” The New York Times Magazine, 16 February.Google Scholar
Johnson, R. 2008. “Was Kant a virtue ethicist?” in Betzler, 2008: 61–76.Google Scholar
Johnson, R. 2011. Self-Improvement: An Essay in Kantian Ethics. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jonas, H. 1984. The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Jonas, H. 2014. “Toward a philosophy of technology,” in Scharff, R. C. and Dusek, V. (eds.), Philosophy of Technology: The Technological Condition: An Anthology, 2nd edition. John Wiley & Sons, 191204.Google Scholar
Jones, D. S. 2012. Masters of the Universe: Hayek, Friedman and the Birth of Neoliberal Politics. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Joos, M. (ed.). 1957. Readings in Linguistics I: The Development of Descriptive Linguistics in America 1925–56. American Council of Learned Societies. 2nd edition, University of Chicago Press, 1966.Google Scholar
Josephson, J. Ā. 2012. The Invention of Religion in Japan. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Jost, L. and Wuerth, J. (eds.). 2011. Perfecting Virtue: New Essays on Kantian Ethics and Virtue Ethics. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. 1999. The Foundations of Causal Decision Theory. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. 2010. “Causal reasoning and backtracking,” Philosophical Studies 147(1):139–54.Google Scholar
Juhl, C. and Loomis, E.. 2010. Analyticity. Routledge.Google Scholar
Kagan, S. 1989. The Limits of Morality. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kagan, S. 2012. The Geometry of Desert. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kajiyama, Y. 1973. “Three kinds of affirmation and two kinds of negation,” Wiener Zeitschrift für die Kunde Südasiens 17:161–75.Google Scholar
Kamm, F. 1992. “Non-consequentialism, the person as an end-in-itself, and the significance of status,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 21:354–89.Google Scholar
Kamm, F. 1993. Morality, Mortality, vols. 1 and 2. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kamm, F. 2007. Intricate Ethics: Rights, Responsibilities, and Permissible Harm. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kamp, H. 1971. “Formal properties of ‘now’,” Theoria 37:227–73.Google Scholar
Kamtekar, R. 2004. “Situationism and virtue ethics on the content of our character,” Ethics 114:458–91.Google Scholar
Kanamori, A. 2012a. “Set theory from Cantor to Cohen,” in Gabbay, , Kanamori, , and Woods, 2012: 1–71.Google Scholar
Kanamori, A. 2012b. “Large cardinals with forcing,” in Gabbay, , Kanamori, , and Woods, 2012: 359–413.Google Scholar
Kane, R. 2002. The Oxford Handbook of Free Will. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kane, R. 2011. The Oxford Handbook of Free Will, 2nd edition. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. 1929 [1781/7]. Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. Smith, N. K.. Macmillan.Google Scholar
Kant, I. 1991 [1784]. “An answer to the question, ‘What is Enlightenment?’” in Immanuel Kant, Political Writings. Ed Reiss, Hans. Cambridge University Press, 6192.Google Scholar
Kant, I. 1996 [1785]. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, in Practical Philosophy. Ed. Gregor, M. J.. Cambridge University Press, 37108.Google Scholar
Kant, I. 1997. Critique of Pure Reason. Ed. and trans. Guyer, P. and Wood, A.. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. 1998. Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason and Other Writings. Ed. Wood, A. and di Giovanni, G.. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kaplan, D. 1989. “Demonstratives,” in Themes from Kaplan. Oxford University Press, 481563.Google Scholar
Kasulis, T. 1981. Zen Action/Zen Person. University of Hawai‘i Press.Google Scholar
Kasulis, T. 2003. “Japanese philosophy,” in Baldwin, T. (ed.), The Cambridge History of Philosophy 1870–1945. Cambridge University Press, 513–19.Google Scholar
Katsafanas, P. 2013. Agency and the Foundations of Ethics: Nietzschean Constitutivism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Katz, C. E. 2014. An Introduction to Modern Jewish Philosophy. I. B. Tauris.Google Scholar
Katz, J. J. 1964. “Mentalism in linguistics,” Language 40:124–37.Google Scholar
Katz, J. J. 1980. “Chomsky on meaning,” Language 56(1):141.Google Scholar
Katz, J. J. 1981. Language and Other Abstract Objects. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Katz, J. J. 1990a. “The refutation of indeterminacy,” in Barrett, R. and Gibson, R. (eds.), Perspectives on Quine. Blackwell, 177–97.Google Scholar
Katz, J. J. 1990b. The Metaphysics of Meaning. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Katz, J. J. 1998. Realistic Rationalism. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kaufmann, W. 1950. Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kaufmann, W. 1956. Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre. World Publishing.Google Scholar
Kazepides, T. 2010. Education as Dialogue: Its Prerequisites and Its Enemies. McGill-Queen’s University Press.Google Scholar
Keane, N. and Lawn, C. (eds.). 2016. The Blackwell Companion to Hermeneutics. John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Kearney, R. 2004. On Paul Ricoeur: The Owl of Minerva. Routledge.Google Scholar
Keller, E. F. 1985. Reflections on Gender and Science. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Kellner, B. 2011. “Self-awareness (svasaṃvedaṇa) and infinite regress: a comparison of arguments by dignāga and dharmakīrit,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 39:411–26.Google Scholar
Kellner, B. 2014. “Changing frames in Buddhist thought: the concept of ākāra in Abhidharma and in Buddhist epistemological analysis,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 42(2–3):275–95.Google Scholar
Kellner, B. and McClintock, S.. 2014. “Ākāra in Buddhist philosophical and soteriological analysis: introduction,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 42(4):427–32.Google Scholar
Kelly, K. 1996. The Logic of Reliable Inquiry. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kelly, S. D. 2002. “Merleau-Ponty on the body: the logic of motor intentional activity,” Ratio 15:376–91.Google Scholar
Kelly, S. D. 2005. “Seeing things in Merleau-Ponty,” in Carman, T. and Hansen, M. (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Merleau-Ponty. Cambridge University Press, 291317.Google Scholar
Kenny, A. 1963. Action, Emotion and Will. Routledge.Google Scholar
Kenny, A. 1975. Will, Freedom and Power. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Kerstein, S. 2002. Kant’s Search for the Supreme Principle of Morality. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Khoo, J. 2017. “Backtracking counterfactuals revisited,” Mind 126(503):841910.Google Scholar
Kieran, M. 2005. Revealing Art. Routledge.Google Scholar
Kieran, M. 2010. “The vice of snobbery: aesthetic knowledge, justification and virtue in art appreciation,” Philosophical Quarterly 60(239):243–63.Google Scholar
Kieran, M. 2011. “The fragility of aesthetic knowledge: aesthetic psychology and appreciative virtues,” in Schellekens, E. and Goldie, P. (eds.), The Aesthetic Mind: Philosophy and Psychology. Oxford University Press, 3243.Google Scholar
Kieran, M. 2014. “Creativity as a virtue of character,” in Paul, E. S. and Kaufman, S. B. (eds.), The Philosophy of Creativity. Oxford University Press, 125–44.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. 2006. Fear and Trembling. Trans. Walsh, S.. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. 2009. Concluding Unscientific Postscript. Trans. Hannay, A.. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kieseppä, I. A. 1997. “Akaike information criterion, curve-fitting, and the philosophical problem of simplicity,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48:2148.Google Scholar
Kim, Hee-Jin. 1987. Dōgen Kigen: Mystical Realist. University of Arizona Press.Google Scholar
Kim, Hee-Jin. 2006. Dōgen on Meditation and Thinking: A Reflection on His View of Zen. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Kim, J. 1988. “What is naturalized epistemology?Philosophical Perspectives 2:381405.Google Scholar
Kim, J. 1993. Supervenience and Mind: Selected Philosophical Essays. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
King, J. C. 2007. The Nature and Structure of Content. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
King, J. C., Soames, S., and Speaks, J.. 2014. New Thinking about Propositions. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
King, W. L. 1967. “Zen and the death of God,” Japanese Religions 5(Dec.):121.Google Scholar
Kirby, S. 2001. “Spontaneous evolution of linguistic structure: an iterated learning model of the emergence of regularity and irregularity,” IEEE Transactions on Evolutionary Computation 5(2):102–10.Google Scholar
Kirk, R. 1974. “Zombies v materialists,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 48:135–52.Google Scholar
Kirloskar-Steinbach, M., Ramana, G., and Maffie, J.. 2014. “Introducing confluence: a thematic essay,” Confluence 1:763.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. 1981. “Explanatory unification,” Philosophy of Science 48:507–31.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. 1984. “Species,” Philosophy of Science 51(2):308–33.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. 1989. “Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world,” in Kitcher, P. and Salmon, W. C. (eds.), Scientific Explanation. University of Minnesota Press, 410505.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. 1993.The Advancement of Science: Science without Legend, Objectivity without Illusions. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kittay, E. F. 2013. Love’s Labor: Essays on Women, Equality and Dependency. Routledge.Google Scholar
Kittay, E. F. and Carlson, L. (eds.). 2010. Cognitive Disability and Its Challenge to Moral Philosophy. John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Kivy, P. 1980. The Corded Shell. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kivy, P. 1989. Sound Sentiment. Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Kivy, P. 1990. Music Alone: Philosophical Reflection on the Purely Musical Experience. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Kivy, P. 1993. The Fine Art of Repetition: Essays in the Philosophy of Music. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kivy, P. 2006. The Performance of Reading: An Essay in the Philosophy of Literature. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Klein, P. 2008. “Useful false beliefs,” in Smith, Q. (ed.), Epistemology: New Essays. Oxford University Press, 2563.Google Scholar
Klosko, G. 2000. Democratic Procedures and Liberal Consensus. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kluge, F. 2002. Etymologisches Wörterbuch der deutschen Sprache, 24th edition. Ed. Seebold, Elmar. Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Kment, B. 2014. Modality and Explanatory Reasoning. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Knobe, J. and Nichols, S. (eds.). 2008 and 2013. Experimental Philosophy, vols. 1 and 2. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Knowles, D. (ed.). 1990. Explanation and Its Limits. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kohlberg, L. 1984. The Psychology of Moral Development: The Nature and Validity of Moral Stages. Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Köhnke, C. 1991. The Rise of Neo-Kantianism: German Academic Philosophy between Idealism and Positivism. Trans. Hollingdale, R. J.. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Koopman, C. 2013. Genealogy as Critique: Foucault and the Problems of Modernity. Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Kopf, G. 2001. Beyond Personal Identity: Dōgen, Nishida, and the Phenomenology of No-Self. Curzon Press.Google Scholar
Kornblith, H. 2008. “Knowledge needs no justification,” in Smith, Q. (ed.), Epistemology: New Essays. Oxford University Press, 523.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. M. 1996a. Creating the Kingdom of Ends. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. M. 1996b. The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. M. 2008. The Constitution of Agency: Essays on Practical Reason and Moral Psychology. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. M. 2009. Self-Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Korsmeyer, C. 1999. Making Sense of Taste: Food and Philosophy. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Korsmeyer, C. 2004. Gender and Aesthetics: An Introduction. Routledge.Google Scholar
Korsmeyer, C. 2011. Savoring Disgust: The Foul and the Fair in Aesthetics. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Koselleck, R. 1972. “Einleitung,” in Brunner, , Conze, , and Koselleck, 1972–97: vol. 1, xxii–xxiii.Google Scholar
Koselleck, R. 1979. Vergangene Zukunft: Zur Semantik geschichtlicher Zeiten. Suhrkamp. Trans. K. Tribe as Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time. Columbia University Press, 2004.Google Scholar
Koslicki, K. 2012. “Varieties of ontological dependence,” in Correia, F. and Schnieder, B. (eds.), Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality. Cambridge University Press, 186213.Google Scholar
Koslicki, K. 2015. “The coarse-grainedness of grounding,” in Bennett, K. and Zimmerman, D. W. (eds.), Oxford Studies in Metaphysics. Oxford University Press, 306–44.Google Scholar
Koslicki, K. 2016. “Where grounding and causation part ways: comments on Schaffer,” Philosophical Studies 173(1):101–12.Google Scholar
Kraft, V. 1953 [1950]. The Vienna Circle. Trans. Pap, Arthur. Philosophical Library.Google Scholar
Krämer, S. 2013. “A simpler puzzle of ground,” Thought 2(2):85–9.Google Scholar
Krasser, H. 1999. “Dharmakīrti and Kumārila on the refutation of the existence of God,” in Katsura, S. (ed.), Dharmakīrti’s Thought and Its Impact on Indian and Tibetan Philosophy: Proceedings of the Third International Dharmakīrti Conference, Hiroshima, November 4–6. Verlag der Österreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften: Beiträge zur Kultur- und Geistesgeschichts Asias, 215–23.Google Scholar
Krausz, M. 2000. Limits of Rightness. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 2011. Against Absolute Goodness. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Krell, D. F. 1996. Infectious Nietzsche. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Kriegel, U. 2002. “Phenomenal content,” Erkenntnis 57:175–98.Google Scholar
Kriegel, U. 2009. Subjective Consciousness: A Self-Representational Theory. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. 1959. “A completeness theorem in modal logic,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 24:114.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. 1963a. “Semantical analysis of modal logic,” Zeitschrift fur Mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 9:6796.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. 1963b. “Semantical considerations on modal logic,” Acta Philosophica Fennica 16:8394.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. 1972. “Naming and necessity,” in Davidson, Donald and Harman, Gilbert (eds.), Semantics of Natural Languages. Reidel, 253355.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. 1975. “Outline of a theory of truth,” Journal of Philosophy 72:690716.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. 1979. “A puzzle about belief,” in Margalit, Avishai (ed.), Meaning and Use. Reidel, 239–83.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. 1982. Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kristjánsson, K. 2006. “‘Emotional intelligence’ in the classroom? An Aristotelian critique,” Educational Theory 56:39.Google Scholar
Kroes, P. A., Franssen, M., and Bucciarelli, L. L.. 2009. “Rationality in engineering design,” in Meijers, A. (ed.), Philosophy of Technology and Engineering Sciences. Handbook of the Philosophy of Science 9. North-Holland, 565600.Google Scholar
Kroes, P. and Meijers, A. (eds.). 2006. “The dual nature of technical artifacts,” Special Issue of Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 37:1158.Google Scholar
Kruks, S. 2017. “Beauvoir and the Marxism question,” in Baur, N. and Hengehold, L. (eds.), A Companion to Simone de Beauvoir. Wiley Blackwell, 236–49.Google Scholar
Krummel, J. 2015. Nishida Kitarō’s Chiasmic Chorology: Place of Dialectic, Dialectic of Place. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. 1957. The Copernican Revolution. Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd edition 1970. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. 1977. The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Shūzō, Kuki. 1997. Reflections on Japanese Taste: The Structure of Iki. Trans. Clark, John. Power Publications.Google Scholar
Shūzō, Kuki. 2004. The Structure of Detachment: The Aesthetic Vision of Kuki Shūzō. Trans. Nara, Hiroshi. University of Hawai‘i Press.Google Scholar
Kukla, A. 1993. “Laudan, Leplin, empirical equivalence, and underdetermination,” Analysis 53(1):17.Google Scholar
Kuklick, B. 2001. A History of Philosophy in America 1720–2000. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kulvicki, J. 2006. On Images: Their Structure and Content. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kunst, A. 1968. “Somatism: a basic concept in India’s philosophical speculations,” Philosophy East and West 18(4):261–75.Google Scholar
Kuusela, O. 2008. The Struggle against Dogmatism: Wittgenstein and the Concept of Philosophy. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kuzminski, A. 2007. “Pyrrhonism and mādhyamaka,” Philosophy East and West 57(4):482511.Google Scholar
Kymlicka, W. and Donaldson, S.. 2011. Zoopolis: A Political Theory of Animal Rights. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lacan, J. 1977 (1973). The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis. Ed. Miller, J.-A., trans. Sheridan, A.. W. W. Norton & Co.Google Scholar
Laerke, M. 2016. “[Review of Piaia and Santinello 2015],” Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews: http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/67971-models-of-the-history-of-philosophy-vol-iii-the-second-enlightenment-and-the-kantian-age.Google Scholar
Laerke, M., Smith, J. E. H., and Schliesser, E. (eds.). 2013. Philosophy and Its History: Aims and Methods in the Study of Early Modern Philosophy. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
LaFleur, W. R. 1985. Dōgen Studies. University of Hawai‘i Press.Google Scholar
Lakatos, I. 1970. “History of science and its rational reconstructions,” Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1970:91–136. Reprinted in Lakatos 1978: 102–38.Google Scholar
Lakatos, I. 1978. The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes, Philosophical Papers, vol. 1. Ed. Worrall, J. and Currie, G.. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Laland, K. N. and Sterelny, K.. 2006. “Perspective: seven reasons (not) to neglect niche construction,” Evolution, 60(9):1,751–62.Google Scholar
Lalander, R. 2014. “Rights of nature and the indigenous peoples in Bolivia and Ecuador: a straitjacket for progressive development politics?Iberoamerican Journal of Development Studies 3(2):148–73.Google Scholar
Lamarque, P. 1996. Fictional Points of View. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Lamarque, P. 2009. The Philosophy of Literature. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lamarque, P. 2010. Work and Object: Explorations in the Metaphysics of Art. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lamarque, P. 2014. The Opacity of Narrative. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Lamarque, P. and Olsen, S. H.. 1994. Truth, Fiction, and Literature: A Philosophical Perspective. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Lance, M. 2008. “Placing in a space of norms: neo-Sellarsian philosophy in the twenty-first century,” in Misak, C. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of American Philosophy. Oxford University Press, 403–29.Google Scholar
Lange, M. 2009. Laws and Lawmakers. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Langer, S. K. 1942. Philosophy in a New Key. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Langer, S. K. 1953. Feeling and Form. Scribner’s.Google Scholar
Lao, Si-guang. 1982. Xin Bian Zhong Guo Zhe Xue Shi [A New Account of the History of Chinese Philosophy], 3 vols. Sanmin.Google Scholar
Lasch, C. 1978. The Culture of Narcissism: American Life in an Age of Diminishing Expectations. W. W. Norton & Co.Google Scholar
Latour, B. and Woolgar, S.. 1986. Laboratory Life: The Construction of Scientific Facts. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. 1977. Progress and Its Problems. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. 1984. Science and Values: The Aims of Science and Their Role in Scientific Debate. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. and Leplin, J.. 1991. “Empirical equivalence and underdetermination,” Journal of Philosophy 88(9):449–72.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. and Leplin, J.. 1993. “Determination underdeterred.” Analysis 53(1):816.Google Scholar
Lavin, D. 2015. “Action as a form of temporal unity,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 45:609–29.Google Scholar
Lear, J. 2011. A Case for Irony. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lebens, S. 2017. “Russell and Bradley: revisiting the creation narrative of analytic philosophy,” Journal for the History of Analytic Philosophy 5(7):120.Google Scholar
Leddy, T. 2011. The Extraordinary in the Ordinary: The Aesthetics of Everyday Life. Broadview.Google Scholar
Lee, G. 2014. “Temporal experience and the temporal structure of experience,” Philosophers’ Imprint 14(3).Google Scholar
Lees, R. B. 1957. “Review of Noam Chomsky, Syntactic Structures,” Language 33:375408.Google Scholar
Leftow, B. 1991. Time and Eternity. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Lehnert, W. G. 1978. The Process of Question Answering. Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Lehrer, K. and Paxson, T.. 1969. “Knowledge: undefeated justified true belief,” Journal of Philosophy 66(8):225–37.Google Scholar
Leiter, B. (ed.). 2004. The Future for Philosophy. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Leopold, A. 1987 [1949]. A Sand County Almanac and Sketches Here and There. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lepore, E. and McLaughlin, B. (eds.). 1985. Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Leuenberger, S. 2014. “Grounding and necessity,” Inquiry 57(2):151–74.Google Scholar
Levi, P. 1989. The Drowned and the Saved. Vintage.Google Scholar
Levi, P. 1996. Survival in Auschwitz. Touchstone.Google Scholar
Levin, Y. 2016. The Fractured Republic: Renewing America’s Social Contract in the Age of Individualism. Basic Books.Google Scholar
Levinas, E. 1947. Time and the Other. Trans. Cohen, R. A.. Duquesne University Press, 1987. Originally Le temps et l’autre. Fata Morgana, 1979. First published in J. Wahl (ed.), Le choix, le monde, l’existence. B. Arthaud, 1947.Google Scholar
Levinas, E. 1969 [1961]. Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority. Duquesne University Press, 1969. Originally Totalité et infini: essais sur l’extériorité. Phaenomenologica 8. Martinus Nijhoff, 1961.Google Scholar
Levinas, E. 1978 [1974]. Otherwise than Being or Beyond Essence. Trans. Lingis, A.. Kluwer Academic. Trans. by A. Lingis. 2nd edition 1981. Originally Autrement qu’être ou au-delà de l’essence. Phaenomenologica 54. Martinus Nijhoff, 1974.Google Scholar
Levinas, E. 1985. Ethics and Infinity. Trans. Cohen, R. A.. Duquesne University Press.Google Scholar
Levinas, E. 1990 [1934]. “Reflections on the philosophy of Hitlerism,” Critical Inquiry 17:6371. Trans. S. Hand. University of Chicago Press, 1990. Originally published as “Quelques réflexions sur la philosophie de l’hitlérisme,” Esprit 2:199–208, 1934.Google Scholar
Levinas, E. 1990. Nine Talmudic Readings. Trans. Aronowicz, A.. Indiana University Press. This translation regroups the lectures Quatre lectures talmudiques. Les Éditions de Minuit, 1968 and Du sacré au saint: cinq nouvelles lectures talmudiques. Les Éditions de Minuit, 1977.Google Scholar
Levine, J. 1983. “Materialism and qualia: the explanatory gap,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64:354–61.Google Scholar
Levine, J. 2006. “Conscious awareness and (self)-representation,” in Uriah, K. and Williford, K. (eds.), Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness. The MIT Press, 173–98.Google Scholar
Levine, S. 2016. “Sellars and nonconceptual content,” European Journal of Philosophy. doi:10.1111/ejop.12127.Google Scholar
Levins, R. 1968. Evolution in Changing Environments. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Levinson, J. 1990. Music, Art, and Metaphysics. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Levinson, J. 1997. Music in the Moment. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Levy, N. 2014. Addiction and Self-Control: Perspectives from Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Levy, N. and McKenna, M.. 2009. “Recent work on free will and moral responsibility,” Philosophy Compass 3:96133.Google Scholar
Lewens, T. 2015. Cultural Evolution: Conceptual Challenges. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, C. I. 1923. “A pragmatic conception of the a priori,” Journal of Philosophy 20(7):169–77.Google Scholar
Lewis, C. I. 1956 [1929]. Mind and the World Order: An Outline of a Theory of Knowledge. Dover.Google Scholar
Lewis, C. I. 1968. “Autobiography,” in Schlipp, P., The Philosophy of C. I. Lewis. Open Court.Google Scholar
Lewis, C. I. 1970 [1930]. “Pragmatism and current thought,” in Goheen, J. D. and Mothershead, J. L. Jr. (eds.), Collected Papers of Clarence Irving Lewis. Stanford University Press, 7886.Google Scholar
Lewis, C. I. 1971 [1946]. An Analysis of Knowledge and Evaluation. Open Court.Google Scholar
Lewis, C. I. and Langford, C. H.. 1932. Symbolic Logic. Century.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1966. “An argument for the identity theory,” Journal of Philosophy 63:1725. Reprinted in Lewis 1983a: 99–107.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1970a. “Anselm and actuality,” Noûs 4:175–88. Reprinted in Lewis 1983a: 10–25.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1970b. “How to define theoretical terms,” Journal of Philosophy 67(13):427–46.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1973. Counterfactuals. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1979a. “Attitudes de dicto and de se,” Philosophical Review 88:513–43. Reprinted in Lewis 1983a: 513–43.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1979b. “Counterfactual dependence and time’s arrow,” Noûs 13(4):455–76.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1980. “Mad pain and Martian pain,” in Block, N. (ed.), Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology, vol. 1. Harvard University Press, 216–32. Reprinted in Lewis 1983a: 122–32.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1983a. Philosophical Papers, vol. 1. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1983b. “Postscript to ‘Mad pain and Martian pain’,” in Lewis, 1983a: 130–2.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1986. On the Plurality of Worlds. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1988. “What experience teaches,” Proceedings of the Russellian Society 13:2957. Reprinted in Lewis 1999a: 262–90.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1995. “Should a materialist believe in qualia?Australasian Journal of Philosophy 73:140–4. Reprinted in Lewis 1999a: 325–31.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1996. “Elusive knowledge,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74:549–67.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1999a. Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1999b. “New work for a theory of universals,” in Lewis 1999a: 8–55.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 2000. “Causation as influence,” Journal of Philosophy 97:182–97Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 2004. “Void and object,” in Collins, J., Hall, N, and Paul, L. A (eds.), Causation and Counterfactuals. The MIT Press, 277–90.Google Scholar
Lewis, K. 2016. “Elusive counterfactuals,” Noûs 50(2):286313.Google Scholar
Lewis, K. forthcoming. “Counterfactual discourse in context,” Noûs.Google Scholar
Lewis, L. J. 1963. “Fichte and Śaṃkara,” Philosophy East and West 12(4):301–17.Google Scholar
Chenyang, Li. 2000. The Sage and the Second Sex: Confucianism, Ethics, and Gender. Open Court.Google Scholar
Light, A. and Katz, E. (eds.). 1996. Environmental Pragmatism. Routledge.Google Scholar
Lippert-Rasmussen, K. 1996. “Moral status and the impermissibility of minimizing violations,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 25:333–51.Google Scholar
Lipstadt, D. 2011. The Eichmann Trial. Penguin.Google Scholar
Lipton, P. 1991. Inference to the Best Explanation. Routledge.Google Scholar
List, C. and Pettit, P.. 2011. Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate Agents. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lister, A. 2013. Public Reason and Political Community. Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Litland, J. E. 2013. “On some counterexamples to the transitivity of grounding,” Essays in Philosophy 14(1):1932.Google Scholar
Litland, J. E. 2017. “Grounding ground,” Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 10:279316.Google Scholar
Livengood, J. and Rose, D.. 2016. “Experimental philosophy and causal attribution,” in Sytsma, J. and Buckwalter, W. (eds.), A Companion to Experimental Philosophy. Blackwell, 434–49.Google Scholar
Livingston, P. 2005a. Art and Intention: A Philosophical Study. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Livingston, P. 2009. Cinema, Philosophy, Bergman: On Film as Philosophy. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Livingston, P. M. 2004. Philosophical History and the Problem of Consciousness. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Livingston, P. M. 2005b. “Functionalism and logical analysis,” in Smith, and Thomasson, 2005: 19–40.Google Scholar
Livingston, P. M. 2011. The Politics of Logic: Badiou, Wittgenstein, and the Consequences of Formalism. Routledge.Google Scholar
Lloyd, E. 2005. The Case of the Female Orgasm: Bias in the Science of Evolution. Harvard University Press,Google Scholar
Lloyd, E. and Gould, S. J.. 1993. “Species selection on variability,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 90(2):595–9.Google Scholar
Lloyd, G. 1993. The Man of Reason: “Male” and “Female” in Western Philosophy. University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Logue, H. 2013. “Visual experience of natural kind properties: is there any fact of the matter?Philosophical Studies 162:112.Google Scholar
Lomasky, L. E. 2005. “Libertarianism at Twin Harvard,” Social Philosophy and Policy 22(1):178–99.Google Scholar
Longino, H. E. 1990. Science as Social Knowledge: Values and Objectivity in Scientific Inquiry. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Longworth, G. 2012. “John Langshaw Austin,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Zalta, E. N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/austin-jl/.Google Scholar
Lopes, D. M. 1996. Understanding Pictures. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Lopes, D. M. 2005. Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lopes, D. M. 2010. A Philosophy of Computer Art. Routledge.Google Scholar
Lopes, D. M. 2014. Beyond Art. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Louden, R. B. 1984. “On some vices of virtue ethics,” American Philosophical Quarterly 21(3):227–36.Google Scholar
Louden, R. 1986. “Kant’s virtue ethics,” Philosophy 61:473–89.Google Scholar
Louis, É. 2017. The End of Eddy. Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. 1998. The Possibility of Metaphysics. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Loy, D. (ed.). 1996. Healing Deconstruction: Postmodern Thought in Buddhism and Christianity. Scholars Press.Google Scholar
Loy, Hui-chieh 2014. “Classical Confucianism as virtue ethics,” in van Hooft, S. (ed.), Handbook of Virtue Ethics. Routledge, 285–93.Google Scholar
Luntley, M. 2003. Wittgenstein, Meaning and Judgment. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Luntley, M. 2007. “Learning, empowerment and judgement,” Educational Philosophy and Theory 39(4):418–31.Google Scholar
Luntley, M. 2008. “Training and learning. [Response to Jeff Stickney],” Educational Philosophy and Theory 40(5):695711.Google Scholar
Luper-Foy, S. (ed.). 1987. The Possibility of Knowledge. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Lusthaus, D. 2002. Buddhist Phenomenology: A Philosophical Investigation of Yogācāra Buddhism and the Ch’eng Wei-shih lun. Routledge.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. G. 1996. Consciousness and Experience. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. G. 2006. “On the Gettier problem problem,” in Hetherington, S. C. (ed.), Epistemology Futures. Oxford University Press, 148–68.Google Scholar
Lyons, D. 1965. Forms and Limit of Utilitarianism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lyotard, J.-F. 1988 [1983]. The Differend: Phrases in Dispute. Trans. van Den Abbeele, G.. University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Lyotard, J.-F. 1990 [1988]. Heidegger and “the Jews.” Trans. Michel, A. and Roberts, M.. University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Lyotard, J.-F. 1994. The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Trans. Bennington, G. and Massumi, B.. University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Ma, L. 2007. Heidegger on East–West Dialogue: Anticipating the Event. Routledge.Google Scholar
Macarthur, D. 2008. “Quinean naturalism in question,” Philo 11(1):114.Google Scholar
Macarthur, D. 2017. “Metaphysical quietism and everyday life,” in D’Oro, G. and Overgaard, S. (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Philosophical Methodology. Cambridge University Press, 270–96.Google Scholar
MacDowell, J. 2009. “Gadamer and Davidson on understanding and relativism,” in The Engaged Intellect: Philosophical Essays. Harvard University Press, 134–51.Google Scholar
Machamer, P. K., Darden, L., and Craver, C. F.. 2000. “Thinking about mechanisms,” Philosophy of Science 67:125.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, A. 1999. Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues. Carus.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, A. 2007 [1981]. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory, 3rd edition. University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Mackenzie, M. D. 2007. “The illumination of consciousness: approach to self-awareness in the Indian and Western traditions,” Philosophy East and West 57(2):4062.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1955. “Evil and omnipotence,” Mind 64(254):200–12.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1965. “Causes and conditions,” American Philosophical Quarterly 2(4):254–64.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1980. The Cement of the Universe. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1982. The Miracle of Theism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mackie, P. 2014. “Counterfactuals and the fixity of the past,” Philosophical Studies 168(2):119.Google Scholar
MacKinnon, C. 2017. Butterfly Politics. Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Macmillan, C. J. B. 1995. “How not to learn: reflections on Wittgenstein and learning,” in Marshall, J. and Smeyers, P. (eds.), Philosophy and Education: Accepting Wittgenstein’s Challenge. Kluwer Academic, 3746.Google Scholar
Maes, H. (ed.). 2011. Pornographic Art and the Aesthetics of Pornography. Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Maffie, J. 2015. Aztec Philosophy: Understanding a World in Motion. University Press of Colorado.Google Scholar
Maher, C. 2012. The Pittsburgh School of Philosophy: Sellars, McDowell, Brandom. Routledge.Google Scholar
Makeham, J. (ed.). 2012. Learning to Emulate the Wise: The Genesis of Chinese Philosophy as an Academic Discipline in Twentieth-Century China. Chinese University Press.Google Scholar
Makkreel, R. A. 2011. “Hermeneutics,” in Tucker, 2011: 529–39.Google Scholar
Makkreel, R. A. 2012. “Editorial reflections – expanding beyond canonical figures and periods,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 25(3):309–13.Google Scholar
Makkreel, R. A. 2015. Orientation and Judgment in Hermeneutics. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Malcolm, N. 1942. “Moore and ordinary language,” in Schilpp, P. A. (ed.), The Philosophy of G. E. Moore. Northwestern University Press, 345–68.Google Scholar
Malcolm, N. 1960. “Anselm’s ontological arguments,” Philosophical Review 69(1):4162.Google Scholar
Malcolm, N. 1971. “The myth of cognitive structures and processes,” in Mischel, T. (ed.), Cognitive Development and Epistemology. Academic Press, 385–92.Google Scholar
Malpas, J. (ed.). 2011. Dialogues with Davidson: Acting, Interpreting, Understanding. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Malpas, J. 2012. “Existentialism as literature,” in Crowell, 2012a: 291–321.Google Scholar
Malpas, J. 2017. “Placing understanding/understanding place,” Sophia 56(3):379–91.Google Scholar
Malpas, J. and Gander, H.-H. (eds.). 2015. The Routledge Companion to Hermeneutics. Routledge.Google Scholar
Mameli, M. 2004. “Nongenetic selection and nongenetic inheritance,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55(1):3571.Google Scholar
Mandelbaum, M. 1961. “Historical explanation: the problem of ‘covering laws’,” History and Theory 1(3):229–42. Reprinted in Gardiner 1974: 51–65.Google Scholar
Mandelbaum, M. 1963. “Objectivism in history,” in Hook, 1963: 43–56.Google Scholar
Marcano, D-D. 2010. “The difference that difference makes: black feminism and philosophy,” in del Guadalupe Davidson, M., Gines, K. T., and Marcano, D-D. (eds.), Convergences: Black Feminism and Continental Philosophy, SUNY Press, 5365.Google Scholar
Marcel, G. 1954. The Decline of Wisdom. The Harvill Press.Google Scholar
Marcel, G. 1962. Man against Mass Society. Trans. Fraser, G. S.. Henry Regnery.Google Scholar
Marcel, G. 1968. The Philosophy of Existentialism. The Citadel Press.Google Scholar
Marcel, G. 1983. The Mystery of Being, 2 vols. University Press of America.Google Scholar
Marcus, R. 1946. “A functional calculus of first order based on strict implication,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 11:116.Google Scholar
Marcus, R. 1961. “Modalities and intensional languages,” Synthese 13(4):303–22.Google Scholar
Marcuse, H. 1964. One-Dimensional Man: Studies in the Ideology of Advanced Industrial Society. Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Marcuse, H. 1966. Eros and Civilization: A Philosophical Inquiry into Freud. Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Marcuse, H. 1972. Negations: Essays in Critical Theory. Trans. Shapiro, J. J.. Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Marcuse, H. 1978. The Aesthetic Dimension: Toward a Critique of Marxist Aesthetics. Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Marcuse, H. 1991 [1964]. One-Dimensional Man: Studies in the Ideology of Advanced Industrial Society. Routledge.Google Scholar
Marcuse, H. 2011. Philosophy, Psychoanalysis and Emancipation: Collected Papers of Herbert Marcuse, vol. 5. Ed. Kellner, D. and Pierce, C.. Routledge.Google Scholar
Margolis, J. 1980. Art and Philosophy. Humanities Press.Google Scholar
Margolis, J. 1995. Interpreting Radical but not Unruly. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Margolis, J. 1998. “Dewey in dialogue with continental philosophy,” in Hickman, L. (ed.), Reading Dewey: Interpretations for a Postmodern Generation. Indiana University Press, 240.Google Scholar
Margolis, J. 2010. “The point of Hegel’s dissatisfaction with Kant,” in Nuzzo, A. (ed.), Hegel and the Analytic Tradition. Continuum, 1239.Google Scholar
Marquit, E. 1995. “Philosophy of technology,” in Encyclopedia of Applied Physics, vol. 13. VCH Publishers, 417–29.Google Scholar
Marr, D. C. 1976. “Early processing of visual information,” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, B, 275:483524.Google Scholar
Marr, D. C. 1982. Vision: A Computational Investigation into the Human Representation and Processing of Visual Information. W. H. Freeman.Google Scholar
Marra, M. (ed.). 1999. Modern Japanese Aesthetics: A Reader. University of Hawai‘i Press.Google Scholar
Marra, M. 2001. A History of Modern Japanese Aesthetics. University of Hawai’i Press.Google Scholar
Marra, M. 2010. Essays on Japan: Between Aesthetics and Literature. Brill.Google Scholar
Marshall, J. D. 1985. “Wittgenstein on rules: implications for authority and discipline in education,” Journal of Philosophy of Education 19(1):311.Google Scholar
Marshall, J. D. 1995. “Wittgenstein and Foucault: resolving philosophical puzzles,” in Marshall, J. and Smeyers, P. (eds.), Philosophy and Education: Accepting Wittgenstein’s Challenge. Kluwer Academic, 205–20.Google Scholar
Marshall, J. D. 1996. Michel Foucault: Personal Autonomy and Education. Kluwer Academic.Google Scholar
Marshall, J. D. 2001. “A critical theory of the self: Wittgenstein, Nietzsche, Foucault,” Studies in Philosophy and Education 20(1):7591.Google Scholar
Marshall, J. D. (ed.). 2004. Poststructuralism, Philosophy, Pedagogy. Kluwer Academic.Google Scholar
Marshall, J. D. and Smeyers, P.. 1995. Philosophy and Education: Accepting Wittgenstein’s Challenge. Kluwer Academic.Google Scholar
Marshall, J. D., Smeyers, P., and Peters, M. A. (eds.). 2001. Nietzsche’s Legacy for Education: Past and Present Values. Bergin and Garvey.Google Scholar
Martin, J. R. 1985. Reclaiming a Conversation: The Ideal of the Educated Woman. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Martin, M. G. F. 2002. “The transparency of experience,” Mind and Language 17:376425.Google Scholar
Martinich, A. P. and Sosa, D. (eds.). 2001. A Companion to Analytic Philosophy. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Maruyama, Y. 1998. “Wittgenstein’s children: some implications for teaching and otherness,” Paideia: Philosophy of Education, paper presented at the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy. Boston, MA. www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Educ/EducMaru.htm.Google Scholar
Maruyama, Y. 2006a. “The teaching–telling distinction revisited: Scheffler, Kratani and Wittgenstein.” The 21 World Congress of Philosophy Abstracts, 253, August 2003. Proceedings of the Twenty-First World Congress of Philosophy 4:93–7.Google Scholar
Maruyama, Y. 2006b. “Conceptual captivity and emancipation: Wittgenstein’s teaching of philosophy,” Studies in the Philosophy of Education 96.Google Scholar
Marx, K. 1893. Wage Labour and Capital. Trans. Joynes, J.. Twentieth-Century Press.Google Scholar
Masschelein, J. and Simons, M. (eds.). 2011. Rancière, Public Education and the Taming of Democracy. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Matilal, B. K. 1968. The Navya-Nyāya Doctrine of Negation. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Matilal, B. K. 1992. Perception. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Matilal, B. K. 1998. The Character of Logic in India. Ed. Ganeri, J. and Tiwari, H.. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Matilal, B. K. 2015a. Epistemology, Logic, and Grammar in Indian Philosophical Analysis. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Matilal, B. K. 2015b. The Word and the World: India’s Contribution to the Study of Language. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Matravers, D. 1998. Art and Emotion. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Matravers, D. 2014. Fiction and Narrative. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Matthews, R. 1984. “The plausibility of rationalism,” Journal of Philosophy 81:492515. Reprinted in R. Matthews and W. Demopoulos (eds.), Learnability and Linguistic Theory. Foris, 1989, 51–75.Google Scholar
May, T. 2005. Gilles Deleuze: An Introduction. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mayeda, G. 2006. Time, Space, and Ethics in the Philosophy of Martin Heidegger, Watsuji Tetsurō and Kuki Shūzō. Routledge.Google Scholar
Maynard Smith, J. 2000. “The concept of information in biology,” Philosophy of Science 67(2):177–94.Google Scholar
Mayo, C. 2011. “Philosophy of education is bent,” Studies in Philosophy and Education 30(5):471–76.Google Scholar
Mayo, D. 1996. Error and the Growth of Experimental Knowledge. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Mayr, Erasmus. 2011. Understanding Human Agency. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mayr, Ernst. 1969. “The biological meaning of species,” Biological Journal of the Linnean Society 1(3):311–20.Google Scholar
Mays, W. 1952. “Can machines think?Philosophy 27:148–62.Google Scholar
McAleer, S. 2005. “Kant and Aristotle on the difficulty of moral knowledge: lessons from the Doctrine of Virtue,” Studies in the History of Ethics 6:143.Google Scholar
McBride, W. 2012. “Existentialism as a cultural movement,” in Crowell, 2012a: 50–69.Google Scholar
McCarthy, E. 2010. Ethics Embodied: Rethinking Selfhood through Continental, Japanese, and Feminist Philosophies. Lexington.Google Scholar
McCarthy, J. and Hayes, P. J.. 1969. “Some philosophical problems from the standpoint of artificial intelligence,” in Meltzer, B. and Donald, M. Michie, (eds.), Machine Intelligence 4. Edinburgh University Press, 463502.Google Scholar
McCormick, P. J. 1988. Fictions, Philosophies, and the Problems of Poetics. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
McCulloch, W. S. and Pitts, W. H.. 1943. “A logical calculus of the ideas immanent in nervous activity,” Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics 5:115–33. Reprinted in M. A. Boden (ed.), The Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence. Oxford University Press, 1990, 22–39.Google Scholar
McCullough, L. and Schroeder, B. (eds.). 2004. Thinking through the Death of God: A Critical Companion to Thomas J. J. Altizer. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
McCumber, J. 2001. Time in the Ditch: American Philosophy and the McCarthy Era. Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
McCumber, J. 2016. The Philosophy Scare: The Politics of Reason in the Early Cold War. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 1979. “Virtue and reason,” Monist 62(3):331–50.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 1984. “De re senses,” Philosophical Quarterly 34(136):283–94.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 1986. “Singular thought and the extent of ‘inner space’,” in McDowell, John and Pettit, Philip (eds.), Subject, Thought, and Context. Clarendon Press, 137–68.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 1994. Mind and World. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 1995a. “Knowledge and the internal,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55:877–93.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 1995b. “Might there be external reasons?” in Altham, J. E. J. and Harrison, R. (eds.), World, Mind and Ethics: Essays on the Ethical Philosophy of Bernard Williams. Cambridge University Press, 6885.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 2009. “Intentionality as a relation,” in Having the World In View: Essays in Kant, Hegel, and Sellars. Harvard University Press, 4465.Google Scholar
McEvilley, T. 1982. “Pyrrhonism and Mādhyamika,” Philosophy East and West 32(1):335.Google Scholar
McGilvray, J. (ed.). 2005. The Cambridge Companion to Chomsky. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
McGinn, C. 1997. Ethics, Evil and Fiction. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
McGlynn, A. 2014. Knowledge First? Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
McGrath, S. 2005. “Causation by omission: a dilemma,” Philosophical Studies 123:125–48.Google Scholar
McKibben, B. 1990 [1989]. The End of Nature. Viking.Google Scholar
McKinsey, J. C. C. 1941. “A solution of the decision problem for the Lewis Systems S2 and S4,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 6:117–34.Google Scholar
McKinsey, M. 1986. “Mental anaphora,”Synthese 66(1):159–75.Google Scholar
McKinsey, M. 1991a. “The internal basis of meaning,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 72(2):143–69.Google Scholar
McKinsey, M. 1991b. “Anti-individualism and privileged access,” Analysis 51(1):916.Google Scholar
McKinsey, M. 1994. “Individuating beliefs,” Philosophical Perspectives 8:303–30.Google Scholar
McLaren, P. 2000. “The man with the gray beard,” in Che Guevera, Paulo Freire, and the Pedagogy of Revolution. Rowman & Littlefield, 139–82.Google Scholar
McLaren, P. 2007. “The teacher as social and moral agent,” in Life in Schools: An Introduction to Critical Pedagogy in the Foundations of Education, 5th edition. Pearson, 254–6.Google Scholar
McLaughlin, B. and Bennett, K.. 2011. “Supervenience,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Zalta, E. N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/supervenience/.Google Scholar
McLaughlin, B. and Tye, M.. 1998. “Is content-externalism compatible with privileged access?Philosophical Review 107(3):349–80.Google Scholar
McManus, D. 2012. Heidegger and the Measure of Truth. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Medina, J. 2002. The Unity of Wittgenstein’s Philosophy: Necessity, Intelligibility, and Normativity. State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Medina, J. and Wood, D. (eds.). 2005. Truth: Engagements across Philosophical Traditions. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Meggle, G. (ed.). 1998. Actions, Norms, Values: Discussions with Georg Henrik von Wright. Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Melden, A. I. 1961. Free Action. Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Mele, A. 1992. Springs of Action: Understanding Intentional Behaviour. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mele, A. 2009. Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mellor, D. H. 1977. “Natural kinds,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 28:299312.Google Scholar
Mendieta, E. (ed.). 2003. Latin American Philosophy: Currents, Issues, Debates. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Menzies, P. 2004a. “Causal models, token causation, and processes,” Philosophy of Science 71 (Supplement):820–32.Google Scholar
Menzies, P. 2004b. “Difference-making in context,” in Collins, J., Hall, N., and Paul, L. A. (eds.), Causation and Counterfactuals. The MIT Press, 139–80.Google Scholar
Menzies, P. 2014. “Counterfactual theories of causation,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Zalta, E. N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/causation-counterfactual/.Google Scholar
Merchant, C. 1980. The Death of Nature: Women, Ecology and the Scientific Revolution. Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Merleau-Ponty, M. 1962 [1945]. Phenomenology of Perception. Trans. Smith, C.. Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Merleau-Ponty, M. 1966 [1942]. Structure of Behavior, 2nd edition. Trans. Fisher, A. L.. Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Merleau-Ponty, M. 2012 [1945]. Phenomenology of Perception. Trans. Landes, D.. Routledge.Google Scholar
Meskin, A. and Cook, R. T. (eds.). The Art of Comics: A Philosophical Approach. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Metz, T. 2014. “The virtues of African ethics,” in van Hooft, S. (ed.), Handbook of Virtue Ethics. Routledge, 276–84.Google Scholar
Mies, M. and Shiva, V.. 1993. Ecofeminism. Zed Books.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1846. A System of Logic, 2nd edition. John W. Parker.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1979 [1861]. Utilitarianism. Ed. Sher, G.. Hackett.Google Scholar
Miller, A. 1949. Death of a Salesman. Viking Press.Google Scholar
Miller, C. 2013. Moral Character: An Empirical Theory. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, J.-A. 1966. “Suture (elements of the logic of the signifier),” in Hallward, and Peden, 1966: 91–101.Google Scholar
Miller, M. 1993. The Garden as Art. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, R. G. 1984. Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, R. G. 1989. “In defence of proper functions,” Philosophy of Science 56(2):288302.Google Scholar
Millikan, R. G. 1995. White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, R. G. 1999. “Historical kinds and the ‘special sciences’,” Philosophical Studies 95(1):4565.Google Scholar
Millikan, R. G. 2004. “Existence proof for a viable externalism,” in Schantz, R. (ed.), The Externalist Challenge: New Studies on Cognition and Intentionality. Walter de Gruyter, 227–38.Google Scholar
Mills, C. 2000. “Not a mere modus vivendi. The bases for allegiance to the just state,” in Davion, V. and Wolfe, C. (eds.), The Idea of a Political Liberalism. Rowman & Littlefield, 190203.Google Scholar
Mills, C. 2005. “‘Ideal theory’ as ideology,” Hypatia 20:165–83.Google Scholar
Mills, E. 2015. “Jayarāśi’s delightful destruction of epistemology,” Philosophy East and West 65:498541.Google Scholar
Minar, E. 1995. “Feeling at home in language (what makes reading ‘philosophical investigations’ possible?),” Synthese 102:413–52.Google Scholar
Mink, L. O. 1970. Mind, History and Dialectic: Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Mink, L. O. 1987. Historical Understanding. Ed. Fay, B. and Golob, E. O.. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Minsky, M. L. 1965. “Matter, mind, and models,” in Proceedings of the International Federation of Information Processing Congress, vol. 1. Spartan Books, 45–9.Google Scholar
Minsky, M. L. 1979. “The society theory of thinking,” in Winston, P. H. and Brown, R. H. (eds.), Artificial Intelligence: An MIT Perspective. The MIT Press, 421–52.Google Scholar
Minsky, M. L. 1985. The Society of Mind. Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
Minsky, M. L. 2006. The Emotion Machine. Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
Minsky, M. L. and Papert, S. A.. 1969. Perceptrons: An Introduction to Computational Geometry. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Minteer, B. A. 2012. Refounding Environmental Ethics: Pragmatism, Principle and Practice. Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Miracchi, L. 2015. “Competence to know,” Philosophical Studies 172(1):2956.Google Scholar
Misak, C. 2013. The American Pragmatists. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Misak, C. 2016. Cambridge Pragmatism: From Peirce and James to Ramsey and Wittgenstein. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Misak, C. and Price, H. (eds.). 2017. The Practical Turn: Pragmatism in Britain in the Long Twentieth Century. Proceedings of the British Academy. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mishler, B. D. and Brandon, R. N.. 1987. “Individuality, pluralism and the phylogenetic species concept,” Biology and Philosophy 2(4):397414.Google Scholar
Mitcham, C. 1994. Thinking through Technology: The Path between Engineering and Philosophy. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Mitchell, B. (ed.). 1957. Faith and Logic. Routledge.Google Scholar
Mitchell, B. (ed.). 1973. Justification of Religious Belief. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Moltmann, F. 2017. “Attitudinal objects and the distinction between actions and properties,” in Moltmann, F. and Textor, M. (eds.), Act Based Conceptions of Propositional Contents. Oxford University Press, 254–89.Google Scholar
Montague, R. 1960. “Logical necessity, physical necessity, ethics, and quantifiers,” Inquiry 3:259–69. Reprinted in Montague 1974.Google Scholar
Montague, R. 1970. “Pragmatics and intensional logic,” Synthese 22:6894. Reprinted in Montague 1974.Google Scholar
Montague, R. 1974. Formal Philosophy. Ed. with intro. Thomason, R. H.. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1903. “The refutation of idealism,” Mind 12:433–53.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1919–20. “External and internal relations,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 8:3377.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1925. “A defence of common sense,” in Muirhead, J. H. (ed.), Contemporary British Philosophy, 2nd series. George Allen & Unwin, 192233.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1939. “Proof of an external world,” Proceedings of the British Academy 25:273300.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1953. Some Main Problems of Philosophy. George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1993a. “The conception of intrinsic value,” in Moore 1993b: 280–98.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1993b [1903]. Principia Ethica, Revised Edition. Ed. Baldwin, Thomas. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Moran, D. (ed.). 2008. The Routledge Companion to Twentieth Century Philosophy. Routledge.Google Scholar
Moran, K. 2012. Community and Moral Progress in Kant’s Moral Philosophy. The Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Moran, R. 2001. Authority and Estrangement: An Essay on Self-Knowledge. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Morgan, M. S. and Morrison, M. (eds.). 1999. Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Moriyama, S. 2010. “On self-awareness in the Sautrāntika epistemology,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 38(3):261–77.Google Scholar
Morley, M. 1965. “Categoricity in power,” Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 114:514–38.Google Scholar
Morreall, J. 2009. Comic Relief: A Comprehensive Philosophy of Humor. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Morris, C. W. 1938. Foundations of the Theory of Signs. Vol. I, no. 2 of International Encyclopedia of Unified Science. University of Chicago.Google Scholar
Morris, K. 2007. “Wittgenstein’s method: ridding people of philosophical prejudices,” in Kahane, G., Kanterian, E., and Kuusela, O. (eds.), Wittgenstein and His Interpreters. Blackwell, 6687.Google Scholar
Morris, T. V. 1988a. Philosophy and the Christian Faith. University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Morris, T. V. 1988b. Divine and Human Action: Essays in the Metaphysics of Theism. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Morrison, J. 2016. “Perceptual confidence,” Analytic Philosophy 57:1548.Google Scholar
Moss, S. 2012. “On the pragmatics of counterfactuals,” Noûs 46:561–86.Google Scholar
Mostowski, A. 1957. “On a generalization of quantifiers,” Fundamental Mathematicæ 44:1236.Google Scholar
Motherwell, R. 2007. The Writings of Robert Motherwell. Ed. Ashton, D. and Banach, J.. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Mou, Bo (ed.). 2009. History of Chinese Philosophy. Routledge.Google Scholar
Mouffe, C. 1993. The Return of the Political. Verso.Google Scholar
Mouffe, C. 2000. The Democratic Paradox. Verso.Google Scholar
Moyal-Sharrock, D. 2004. Understanding Wittgenstein’s On Certainty. Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Muldoon, R. 2016. Social Contract Theory for a Diverse World: Beyond Tolerance. Routledge.Google Scholar
Mulhall, S. 1990. On Being in the World. Wittgenstein and Heidegger on Seeing Aspects. Routledge.Google Scholar
Mulhall, S. 1998. “Language-games and language: rules, normality conditions and conversation,” in Glock, H. and Hyman, J. (eds.), Wittgenstein and Analytic Philosophy: Essays for P. M. S. Hacker. Oxford University Press, 152–74.Google Scholar
Mulhall, S. 2001. “Seeing aspects,” in Hans-Johann, Glock (ed.), Wittgenstein: A Critical Reader. Blackwell, 246–67.Google Scholar
Muller, H. 2014. “Naturalism and intentionality,” in Bashour, B. and Muller, H. (eds.), Contemporary Philosophical Naturalism and Its Implications. Routledge, 155–81.Google Scholar
Mulligan, K., Simons, P., and Smith, B.. 1984. “Truth-makers,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 44(3):287321.Google Scholar
Mulvey, L. 1975. “Visual pleasure and narrative cinema,” in Braudy, and Cohen, 1975: 833–44.Google Scholar
Mumford, L. 1946. “Gentlemen you are mad,” Saturday Review of Literature, 2 March.Google Scholar
Mumford, L. 1971. The Myth of the Machine, vol. 1: Technics and Human Development. Harvest Books.Google Scholar
Mumford, L. 1974. The Myth of the Machine, vol. 2: Pentagon of Power. Harcourt, Brace Jovanovich.Google Scholar
Mumford, S. 2007. David Armstrong. Acumen.Google Scholar
Murphy, A. V. 2013. Violence and the Philosophical Imaginary. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Murphy, L. 1993. “The demands of beneficence,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 22:267–92.Google Scholar
Murphy, N., Ellis, G., and O’Connor, T. (eds.). 2009. Downward Causation and the Neurobiology of Free Will. Springer.Google Scholar
Musgrave, A. 1974. “Logical versus historical theories of confirmation,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 25:123.Google Scholar
Nadler, S. (ed.). 2002. A Companion to Early Modern Philosophy. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Naess, A. 1973. “The shallow and the deep, long‐range ecology movement. A summary,” Inquiry 16(1–4):95100.Google Scholar
Naess, A. 1986. “The deep ecology movement: some philosophical aspects,” Philosophical Inquiry 8(1–2):1031.Google Scholar
Nagel, E. 1961. The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation. Harcourt, Brace and World.Google Scholar
Nagel, J. 2012. “Intuitions and experiments: a defense of the case method in epistemology,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85(3):495527.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1970. “Armstrong on the mind,” Philosophical Review 79:394403.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1974. “What is it like to be a bat?Philosophical Review 83:435–50. Reprinted in D. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. Oxford University Press, 2002, 219–26.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1986. The View from Nowhere. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1991. Equality and Partiality. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1995. “Personal rights and public space,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 24:83107.Google Scholar
Nanay, B. 2016. Aesthetics as Philosophy of Perception. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nancy, J.-L. 1991 [1985–86]. The Inoperative Community. Trans. Connor, P., Garbus, L., Holland, M., and Sawnhey, S.. University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Nannicelli, T. 2013. A Philosophy of the Screenplay. Routledge.Google Scholar
Nehamas, A. 2007. Only a Promise of Happiness: The Place of Beauty in a World of Art. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Neurath, O. 1959. “Sociology and physicalism” (English translation of an article originally published in German in 1932). In Ayer, A. J. (ed.), Logical Positivism. Macmillan, 282317.Google Scholar
Newell, A. 1980. “Physical symbol systems,” Cognitive Science 4:135–83.Google Scholar
Newell, A., Shaw, J. C., and Simon, H.. 1959. “A general problem-solving program for a computer,” Proceedings of the International Conference on Information Processing, June, 256–64.Google Scholar
Newell, A. and Simon, H.. 1956. “The logic theory machine: a complex information-processing system,” IRE Transactions on Information Theory, IT-2/3:6179.Google Scholar
Newell, A. and Simon, H.. 1961. “GPS – a program that simulates human thought,” in Billing, H. (ed.), Lernende Automaten. Oldenbourg, 109–24. Reprinted in Edward Feigenbaum and Julian Feldman (eds.), Computers and Thought. McGraw-Hill, 1963, 279–93.Google Scholar
Newell, A. and Simon, H.. 1972. Human Problem Solving. Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Newell, A. and Simon, H.. 1976. “Computer science as empirical enquiry: symbols and search,” Communications of the Association for Computing Machinery 19:113–26. Reprinted in M. A. Boden (ed.), The Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence. Oxford University Press, 1990, 105–32.Google Scholar
Newton, A. Z. 2001. The Fence and the Neighbor: Emmanuel Levinas, Yeshayahu Leibowitz, and Israel among the Nations. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Nidditch, P. H. 1968. The Philosophy of Science. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F. 1887. Zur Genealogie der Moral: Eine Streitschrift. Trans. Diethe, C. as On the Genealogy of Morality: A Polemic. Ed. Ansell-Pearson, K.. Cambridge University Press, 1994. Also trans. D. Smith. Oxford University Press, 1996.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F. 1962 [c. 1873]. Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks. Trans. Cowan, M.. Regnery.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F. 1969 [1887]. On the Genealogy of Morals. Trans. Kaufmann, W. and Hollingdale, R. J.. Random House.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F. 1974 [1882/1887]. The Gay Science. Trans. Kaufmann, W.. Random House.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F. 1999 [1872]. The Birth of Tragedy and Other Writings. Trans. Speirs, R.. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F. 2002 [1886]. Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future. Trans. Norman, J.. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. 1998. “Verisimilitude: the third period,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49:129.Google Scholar
Kitarō, Nishida. (Ed.) 1958. Intelligibility and the Philosophy of Nothingness: Three Philosophical Essays. Trans. Shinzinger, R.. East-West Center Press.Google Scholar
Kitarō, Nishida. (Ed.) 1973. Art and Morality. Trans. Dilworth, D. and Viglielmo, V.. University of Hawai’i Press.Google Scholar
Kitarō, Nishida. (Ed.) 1987. Last Writings: Nothingness and the Religious Worldview. Trans. Dilworth, D.. University of Hawai‘i Press.Google Scholar
Kitarō, Nishida. (Ed.) 1990. An Inquiry into the Good. Trans. Abe, Masao and Ives, C.. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Keiji, Nishitani. 1982. Religion and Nothingness. Trans. Van Bragt, J.. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Keiji, Nishitani. 1990. The Self-Overcoming of Nihilism. Trans. Parkes, G. with Aihara, Setsuko. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Noddings, N. 1984. Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics and Moral Education. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Noddings, N. 2013. Caring: A Relational Approach to Ethics and Moral Education. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Noë, A. 2015. Strange Tools: Art and Human Nature. Hill and Wang.Google Scholar
Nolan, D. 1997. “Impossible worlds: a modest approach,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38:535–72.Google Scholar
Nolan, D. 2014. “Hyperintensional metaphysics,” Philosophical Studies 171(1):149–60.Google Scholar
Norcross, A. 1997. “Headaches and human lives,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 26:135–57.Google Scholar
Norcross, A. 2006. “The scalar approach to utilitarianism,” in West, H. (ed.), Blackwell Guide to Mill’s Utilitarianism. Blackwell, 217–32.Google Scholar
Norris, T. 2006. “Hannah Arendt & Jean Baudrillard: pedagogy in the consumer society,” Studies in Philosophy and Education 25(6):457–77.Google Scholar
Norton, B. 1984. “Environmental ethics and weak anthropocentrism,” Environmental Ethics 6(2):131–48.Google Scholar
Norton, B. 1991. Towards Unity among Environmentalists. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Norton, D. F. 2012. “Keeping the Journal alive,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 50(2):153–8.Google Scholar
Nosco, P. 2006. “The National Learning Schools” (introductory material), in de Bary, W. T., Gluck, C., and Tiedemann, A. (eds.), Sources of Japanese Tradition, vol. 2: 1600–2000. Columbia University Press, 481–5.Google Scholar
Novitz, D. 1987. Knowledge, Fiction and Imagination. Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Novitz, D. 1992. The Boundaries of Art. Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. Basic Books.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, C. O. 2007. The Musical Representation: Meaning, Ontology, and Emotion. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, C. O. 2015. Understanding Pornographic Fiction: Sex, Violence, and Self-Deception. Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. 1990. Love’s Knowledge: Essays on Philosophy and Literature. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. 1996. Poetic Justice: The Literary Imagination and Public Life. Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. 1999. “Women and equality: the capabilities approach,” International Labour Review 138(3):227–45.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. 2001. Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. 2009. Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Nationality, Species Membership. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. 2011. “The capabilities approach and animal entitlements,” in Beauchamp, T. and Frey, R. G. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Animal Ethics. Oxford University Press, 228–54.Google Scholar
Oakeshott, M. 1989. The Voice of Liberal Learning. Ed. Fuller, T.. Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Oakley, J. 1996. “Varieties of virtue ethics,” Ratio 9:128–52.Google Scholar
O’Connor, T. 1995. “Agent causation,” in O’Connor, T., Agents, Causes and Events. Essays on Indeterminism and Free Will. Oxford University Press, 173200.Google Scholar
Odin, S. 1987. “Kenosis as a foundation for Buddhist–Christian dialogue: the kenotic Buddhology of Nishida and Nishitani of the Kyoto School in relation to the kenotic Christology of Thomas J. J. Altizer,” Eastern Buddhist 20(1):3461.Google Scholar
Odin, S. 1990. “Derrida and the decentered universe of Chan/Zen Buddhism,” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 17:6186.Google Scholar
Odin, S. 2001. Artistic Detachment in Japan and the West: Psychic Distance in Comparative Aesthetics. University of Hawai‘i Press.Google Scholar
Oger, G. 2005. “France’s polygamy problem,” Deutsche Welle. www.dw.com/en/frances-polygamy-problem/a-1664241, accessed March 19, 2017.Google Scholar
Okasha, S. 2002. “Darwinian metaphysics: species and the question of essentialism,” Synthese 131(2):191213.Google Scholar
Okin, S. M. 1999. Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women? Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Olberding, A. 2013. Moral Exemplars in the Analects: The Good Person Is That. Routledge.Google Scholar
Oliver, A. 1996. “The metaphysics of properties,” Mind 105(417):180.Google Scholar
Oliver, K. 2001. Witnessing: beyond Recognition. University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Oliver, K. 2008. Women as Weapons of War. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Oliver, K. 2009. Animal Lessons: How They Teach Us to Be Human. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Olsen, J. K. B. and Pedersen, S. A.. 2008. Teknologi og Virkelighed: En Antologi om Etik, Eksistens, Fremskridt og Videnskab i den Teknologiske Civilitation. Forlaget Philosophia.Google Scholar
Olson, C. 2000. Zen and the Art of Postmodern Philosophy. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Olssen, M. 2006. Michel Foucault: Materialism and Education. Paradigm.Google Scholar
Olssen, M. 2007. “Invoking democracy: Foucault’s conception (with insights from Hobbes),” in Peters, M. A. and Besley, T. (eds.), Why Foucault? Peter Lang, 205–26.Google Scholar
Olssen, M. and Peters, M. A.. 2005. “Neoliberalism, higher education and the knowledge economy: from the free market to knowledge capitalism,” Journal of Educational Policy 20(3):313–45.Google Scholar
O’Neil, E. 1956. Long Day’s Journey into Night. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
O’Neill, J. 1992. “The varieties of intrinsic value,” The Monist 75(2):119–37.Google Scholar
O’Neill, O. 1975. Acting on Principle. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
O’Neill, O. 1989. Constructions of Reason. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
O’Neill, O. 1996a. “Kant’s virtues,” in Crisp, R. (ed.), How Should One Live? Essays on the Virtues. Oxford University Press, 7797.Google Scholar
O’Neill, O. 1996b. Towards Justice and Virtue. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Oppenheim, P. and Putnam, H.. 1958. “The unity of science as a working hypothesis,” in Feigl, H. and Scriven, M. (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 2. University of Minnesota Press, 326.Google Scholar
Oppy, G. 1995. Ontological Arguments and Belief in God. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Oppy, G. 2006. Arguing about Gods. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Oreskes, N. and Conway, E. M.. 2010. Merchants of Doubt: How a Handful of Scientists Obscured the Truth on Issues from Tobacco Smoke to Global Warming. Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
O’Shaughnessy, B. 1980. The Will: A Dual Aspect Theory. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
O’Shea, J. 2007. Wilfrid Sellars. Polity Press.Google Scholar
O’Shea, J. 2010. “Conceptual thinking and nonconceptual content: a Sellarsian divide,” in O’Shea, J. and Rubinstein, E. (eds.), Self, Language, and World: Problems from Kant, Sellars, and Rosenberg. Ridgeview, 205–28.Google Scholar
O’Shea, J. 2016. “Introduction: origins and legacy of a synoptic vision,” in O’Shea, J. (ed.), Sellars and His Legacy. Oxford University Press, 118.Google Scholar
Otero, C. P. (ed.). 1994. Noam Chomsky: Critical Assessments, vol. 2: Philosophy. Routledge.Google Scholar
Otsuka, M. 2009. “The Kantian argument for consequentialism,” in Suikkanen, J. and Cottingham, J. (eds.), Essays on Derek Parfit’s On What Matters. Wiley-Blackwell, 6178.Google Scholar
Oudart, J-P. 1977. “Cinema and suture,” Screen 18(4):3547.Google Scholar
Overgaard, S. 2010. “Royaumont revisited,” British Journal of the History of Philosophy 18(5): 899924.Google Scholar
Owen, D. 2003. “Genealogy as perspicuous representation,” in Heyes, C. (ed.), The Grammar of Politics: Wittgenstein and Political Philosophy. Cornell University Press, 8296.Google Scholar
Oyama, S., Griffiths, P. E., and Gray, R. D. (eds.). 2001. Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems and Evolution. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Palmer, F. 1992. Literature and Moral Understanding: A Philosophical Essay on Ethics, Aesthetics, Education and Culture. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Papastephanou, M. 2005. “Globalisation, globalism and cosmopolitanism as an educational ideal,” Educational Philosophy and Theory 37(4):533–51.Google Scholar
Papert, S. 1968. The Artificial Intelligence of Hubert L. Dreyfus: A Budget of Fallacies. MIT AI Lab Memo 154. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Papineau, D. 1993. Philosophical Naturalism. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Papineau, D. 1994. “The virtues of randomization,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45(2):437–50.Google Scholar
Papineau, D. (ed.). 1996. The Philosophy of Science. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. 1997. “Reasons and motivation,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, 71: 99129.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. 2011. On What Matters. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Park, Jin Y. 2010. Buddhism and Postmodernity: Zen, Huayan, and the Possibility of Zen Postmodern Ethics. Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Park, P. K. J. 2013. Africa, Asia, and the History of Philosophy: Racism in the Formation of the Philosophical Canon, 1780–1830. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Parker, D. 1995. Ethics, Theory and the Novel. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Parkes, G. (ed.). 1987. Heidegger and Asian Thought. University of Hawai‘i Press.Google Scholar
Parkes, G. (ed.). 1991. Nietzsche and Asian Thought. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Passmore, J. 1974. Man’s Responsibility for Nature: Ecological Problems and Western Traditions. Scribner.Google Scholar
Patil, P. 2009. Against a Hindu God: Buddhist Philosophy of Religion in India. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Paton, H. J. 1947. The Categorical Imperative: A Study in Kant’s Philosophy. Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. 1979. “Deviant causal chains,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4(1):123–55.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. 1983. Sense and Content: Experience, Thought, and Their Relations. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Pearl, J. 2000. Causality: Models, Reasoning, and Inference. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. 1931–58. Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Ed. Hartshorne, C. and Weiss, P. (vols. 1–6), and Burks, A. (vols. 7 and 8). Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. 1955. “The fixation of belief” and “Some consequences of four incapacities,” in Buchler, J. (ed.), Philosophical Writings of Peirce. Dover, 522 and 228–50.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. 1982–. The Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition. General ed. Moore, E.. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Pereda, C. 2008. Los aprendizajes del exilio. Siglo XXI.Google Scholar
Perrett, R. W. 1984. “The problem of induction in Indian philosophy,” Philosophy East and West 34(2):161–74.Google Scholar
Perrett, R. W. 2003. “Intentionality and self-awareness,” Ratio 16(3):222–35.Google Scholar
Perrett, R. W. and Pettigrove, G.. 2015. “Hindu virtue ethics,” in Besser-Jones, L. and Slote, M. (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Virtue Ethics. Routledge, 5162.Google Scholar
Perry, J. 1977. “Frege on demonstratives,” Philosophical Review 86:474–97.Google Scholar
Perry, J. 1979. “The essential indexical,” Noûs 13:321.Google Scholar
Perry, J. 2001a. Knowledge, Possibility, and Consciousness. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Perry, J. 2001b. Reference and Reflexivity. Center for the Study of Language and Information.Google Scholar
Perszyk, K. J. 1984a. “The nyāya and Russell on empty terms,” Philosophy East and West 34(2):131–46.Google Scholar
Perszyk, K. J. 1984b. “Negative entities and negative facts in navya-nyāya,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 12(3):265–75.Google Scholar
Peters, M. A. 1995. “Philosophy and education: ‘after’ Wittgenstein,” in Marshall, J. and Smeyers, P. (eds.), Philosophy and Education: Accepting Wittgenstein’s Challenge. Kluwer Academic, 189204.Google Scholar
Peters, M. A. 1997. “Wittgenstein and post-analytic philosophy of education: Rorty or Lyotard?Educational Philosophy and Theory 29(2):132.Google Scholar
Peters, M. A. 2001. “Wittgensteinian pedagogics: Cavell on the figure of the child in the investigations,” Studies in Philosophy and Education 20(2 March):125–38.Google Scholar
Peters, M. A. (ed.). 2002. Heidegger, Education, and Modernity. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Peters, M. A. 2007. “Neoliberal governmentality: Foucault on the birth of biopolitics,” Review of Contemporary Philosophy 6:3664.Google Scholar
Peters, M. A., Besley, T., Olssen, M., Mauer, S., and Weber, S. (eds.). 2009. Governmentality Studies in Education. Sense.Google Scholar
Peters, M. A., Burbules, N., and Smeyers, P.. 2008. Showing and Doing: Wittgenstein as a Pedagogical Philosopher. Paradigm.Google Scholar
Peters, M. A. and Jandrić, P.. 2015. “Philosophy of education in the age of digital reason,” Review of Contemporary Philosophy 14:162–78.Google Scholar
Peters, M. A. and Marshall, J. D.. 1996. Individualism and Community: Education and Social Policy in the Postmodern Condition. Falmer.Google Scholar
Peters, M. A. and Marshall, J. D.. 1999. Wittgenstein: Philosophy, Postmodernism, Pedagogy. Bergin & Garvey.Google Scholar
Peters, M., Tesar, M., and Locke, K.. 2013. “Philosophy of education,” in Pritchard, D. (ed.), Oxford Bibliographies in Philosophy. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Peters, R. S. 1963. Authority, Responsibility and Education. George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Peters, R. S. 1965. “Education as initiation,” in Archamabult, R. D. (ed.), Philosophical Analysis and Education. The Humanities Press, 87111.Google Scholar
Peters, R. S. 1968. Ethics and Education, 5th edition. George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Peters, R. S. (ed.). 1973. The Philosophy of Education. London.Google Scholar
Peters, R. S. 1983. “Philosophy of education,” in Hirst, P. H. (ed.), Educational Theory and its Foundation Disciplines. London, 3061.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. 1997. “The consequentialist perspective,” in Pettit, P., Baron, M., and Slote, M., Three Methods of Ethics: A Debate. Blackwell, 92174.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. 2004. “Existentialism, quietism, and the role of philosophy,” in Leiter 2004: 304–27.Google Scholar
Pfister, L. 2002. “Feng Youlan’s new principle learning and his histories of Chinese philosophy,” in Cheng, and Bunnin, 2002: 165–87.Google Scholar
Phemister, P. 2016. Leibniz and the Environment. Routledge.Google Scholar
Phillips, D. C. 2014. “Rationality,” in Peters, M. A. (ed.), Encyclopedia of Educational Theory and Philosophy, 2 vols. Springer.Google Scholar
Phillips, D. C. and Siegel, H.. 2015. “Philosophy of education,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Zalta, E. N.. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2015/entries/education-philosophy/.Google Scholar
Phillips, I. 2010. “Perceiving temporal properties,” European Journal of Philosophy 18:176202.Google Scholar
Phillips, S. 2001. “There’s nothing wrong with raw perception: a response to Chakrabarti’s attack on nyāya’s nirvikalpaka pratyaksa,” Philosophy East and West 51(1):104–13.Google Scholar
Phillips, S. 2012. Epistemology in Classical India: The Knowledge Sources of the Nyāya School. Routledge.Google Scholar
Piaia, G. and Santinello, G. (eds.). 1979–2004. Storia delle storie generali della filosofia, 5 vols. La Scuola.Google Scholar
Piaia, G. and Santinello, G. (eds.). 1993. Models of the History of Philosophy, vol. 1: From Its Origins in the Renaissance to the “Historia Philosophica.” Kluwer.Google Scholar
Piaia, G. and Santinello, G. (eds.). 2011. Models of the History of Philosophy, vol. 2: From the Cartesian Age to Brucker. Trans. Siddons, H. and Weston, G.. Springer.Google Scholar
Piaia, G. and Santinello, G. (eds.). 2015. Models of the History of Philosophy, vol. 3: The Second Enlightenment and the Kantian Age. Springer.Google Scholar
Piercey, R. 2016. “Paul Ricoeur,” in Keane, N. and Lawn, C. (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Hermeneutics. John Wiley & Sons, 412–16.Google Scholar
Piketty, T. 2013. Capital in the 21st Century. Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Pinkard, T. 2006. “Sellars the post-Kantian?” in Wolf, M. P. and Lance, M. (eds.), The Self-Correcting Enterprise. Rodopi, 2152.Google Scholar
Pinkard, T. 2008. “What is a ‘shape of spirit’?” in Moyar, D. and Quante, M. (eds.), Hegel’s Phenomenology: A Critical Guide. Cambridge University Press, 112–29.Google Scholar
Pinker, S. and Prince, A.. 1988. “On language and connectionism: analysis of a parallel distributed model of language acquisition,” Cognition 28:73193.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. 1989. Hegel’s Idealism: The Satisfactions of Self-Consciousness. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. 2012a. Fatalism in American Film Noir: Some Cinematic Philosophy. University of Virginia Press.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. 2012b. Hollywood Westerns and American Myth: The Importance of Howard Hawks and John Ford for Political Philosophy. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. 2013. “Le grand imagier of George Wilson,” European Journal of Philosophy 21(2): 334–41.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. 2016. “Minds in the dark: cinematic experience in the Dardennes’ Dans l’obscurité,” nonsite.org, http://nonsite.org/article/minds-in-the-dark-2.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. 2017. The Philosophical Hitchcock: The Anxieties of Unknowingness. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Pitt, D. 2004. “The phenomenology of cognition or what is it like to think that P?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69:136.Google Scholar
Pitt, J. C. 2000. Thinking about Technology: Foundations of the Philosophy of Technology. Seven Bridges.Google Scholar
Pitts, W. H. and McCulloch, W. S.. 1965 [1947]. “How we know universals: the perception of auditory and visual forms,” in McCulloch, W. S., Embodiments of Mind. Ed. Papert, S.. The MIT Press, 4666. Originally published 1947 in Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics 9:127–47.Google Scholar
Place, U. T. 1954. “The concept of heed,” British Journal of Psychology 45:243–55.Google Scholar
Place, U. T. 1956. “Is consciousness a brain process?British Journal of Psychology 47:4450.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1963. “Analytic philosophy and Christianity,” Christianity Today 8:1720.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. (ed.). 1965. The Ontological Argument: From St. Anselm to Contemporary Philosophers. Doubleday Anchor.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1967. God and Other Minds. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1974. The Nature of Necessity. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1979. “Is belief in God rational?” in Delaney, C. F. (ed.), Rationality and Religious Belief. University of Notre Dame Press, 727.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1981a. “Is belief in God properly basic?Noûs 15:4152.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1981b. “The reformed objection to natural theology,” Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 15:4962.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1993a. Warrant: The Current Debate. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. 1993b. Warrant and Proper Function. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. 2011. Where the Conflict Really Lies: Science, Religion, and Naturalism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. and Wolterstorff, N. (eds.). 1983. Faith and Rationality: Reason and Belief in God. University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Plumwood, V. 1993. Feminism and the Mastery of Nature. Routledge.Google Scholar
Plumwood, V. 2002. Environmental Culture: The Ecological Crisis of Reason. Routledge.Google Scholar
Pnueli, A. 1977. “The temporal logic of programs,” Proceedings of the 18th IEEE Symposium on the Foundations of Computer Science. Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers, 4657.Google Scholar
Polanyi, M. 1946. Science, Faith and Society. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Polanyi, M. 1958. Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy. Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Poliakov, L. 1951. Bréviaire de la haine: le IIIe Reich et les juifs [trans. as Breviary of Hate: The Third Reich and the Jews]. Calmann-Lévy.Google Scholar
Popkewitz, T. S. 1998. Struggling for the Soul: The Politics of Education and the Construction of the Teacher. Teachers College Press.Google Scholar
Popkewitz, T. S. 1999a. “Dewey, Vygotsky, and the social administration of the individual: constructivist pedagogy as systems of ideas in historical spaces,” American Educational Research Journal 35(4):535–70.Google Scholar
Popkewitz, T. S. 1999b. “A social epistemology of educational research,” in Popkewitz, T. S. and Fendler, L. (eds.), Critical Theories in Education: Changing Terrains of Knowledge and Politics. Routledge, 1744.Google Scholar
Popkewitz, T. S. 2009. “Why the desire for university–school collaboration and the promise of pedagogical content knowledge may not matter as much as we think,” in Peters, et al. 2009: 217–34.Google Scholar
Popkin, R. H. 1960. The History of Scepticism from Erasmus to Descartes. Humanities Press. Revised edition 1964.Google Scholar
Popkin, R. H. 2002. “Founding editor’s note,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 40(4):417–19.Google Scholar
Popper, K. 1935. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Routledge.Google Scholar
Popper, K. 1959. The Logic of Scientific Discovery, 2nd edition. RoutledgeGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. 1963. Conjectures and Refutations. Routledge.Google Scholar
Port, R. F. and van Gelder, T. (eds.). 1995. Mind as Motion: Explorations in the Dynamics of Cognition. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Portilla, M. L. 1990 [1963]. Aztec Thought and Culture: A Study of the Ancient Nahuatl Mind. Trans. Davis, Jack Emory. University of Oklahoma Press.Google Scholar
Portmore, D. 2009. “Rule-consequentialism and irrelevant others,” Utilitas 21:368–76.Google Scholar
Potter, K. 1975. “The background of skepticism, East and West,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 3(3–4):299313.Google Scholar
Potter, K. 1984. “Does Indian epistemology concern justified true belief?Journal of Indian Philosophy 12(4):307–27.Google Scholar
Potter, N. 1996. “Kant and the moral worth of actions,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 34:225–41.Google Scholar
Power, F. C. and Lapsley, D. K. (eds.). 1992. The Challenge of Pluralism: Education, Politics, and Values. University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Power, M. 1997. The Audit Society: Rituals of Verification. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Prado, C. G. 2003. “A conversation with Richard Rorty,” Symposium 7(2):227–31.Google Scholar
Press, G. A. 2012. “Digital transitions,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 25(4):471–6.Google Scholar
Preston, J. and Bishop, M. (eds.). 2002. Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Price, H. 1992. “Agency and causal asymmetry,” Mind 101(403):501–20.Google Scholar
Price, H. 1996. Time’s Arrow and Archimedes’ Point: New Directions for the Physics of Time. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Price, H. 2013. “Prospects for global expressivism,” in Expressivism, Pragmatism, and Representationalism. Cambridge University Press, 147–94.Google Scholar
Prichard, H. A. 1949. Moral Obligation. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Prichard, H. A. 2002a [1928]. “Duty and interest,” in MacAdam, J. (ed.), Moral Writings. Oxford University Press, 2149.Google Scholar
Prichard, H. A. 2002b [1928]. “Manuscript on morals,” in MacAdam, J. (ed.), Moral Writings. Oxford University Press, 114–62.Google Scholar
Priest, G. 1979. “The logic of paradox,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 8:219–91.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. 2016. “Genealogies of morals: Nietzsche’s method compared,” Journal of Nietzsche Studies 47(2):180201.Google Scholar
Prior, A. N. 1957. Time and Modality. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Prior, A. N. 1967. Past, Present, and Future. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. H. 2002. “Recent work on radical skepticism,” American Philosophical Quarterly 39:215–57.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. H. 2005a. Epistemic Luck. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. H. 2005b. “The structure of sceptical arguments,” Philosophical Quarterly 55:3752.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. H. 2008. “McDowellian Neo-Mooreanism,” in Haddock, A. and Macpherson, F. (eds.), Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge. Oxford University Press, 283310.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. H. 2011. “Wittgenstein on scepticism,” in Kuusela, O. and McGinn, M. (eds.), Oxford Handbook on Wittgenstein. Oxford University Press, 521–47.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. H. 2012a. Epistemological Disjunctivism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. H. 2012b. “Wittgenstein and the groundlessness of our believing,” Synthese 189:255–72.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. H. 2014. “Sceptical intuitions,” in Rowbottom, D. and Booth, A. (eds.), Intuitions. Oxford University Press, 213–31.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. H. 2015. Epistemic Angst: Radical Skepticism and the Groundlessness of Our Believing. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. H. 2017. “Wittgenstein on hinges and radical scepticism in On Certainty,” in Johann-Glock, H. and Hyman, J. (eds.), Blackwell Companion to Wittgenstein. Blackwell, 563–75.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. H. 2018. “Epistemic Angst,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 96:70–90.Google Scholar
Proops, I. 2003. “Kant’s legal metaphor and the nature of a deduction,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 41(2):209–29.Google Scholar
Pryor, J. 2000. “The skeptic and the dogmatist,” Noûs 34:517–49.Google Scholar
Psillos, S. 1999. Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth. Routledge.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1960. “Minds and machines,” in Hook, S. (ed.), Dimensions of Mind: A Symposium. New York University Press, 138–64.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1962a. “The analytic and the synthetic,” Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 3:358–97. Reprinted in Putnam 1975c: 33–69.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1962b. “It ain’t necessarily so,” Journal of Philosophy 59(22):658–71. Reprinted in Putnam 1975b: 237–49.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1967a. “The ‘innateness hypothesis’ and explanatory models in linguistics,” Synthese 17(1):1222.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1967b. “The nature of mental states,” in Capitan, W. H. and Merrill, D. D. (eds.), Art, Mind, and Religion. University of Pittsburgh Press, 197203. Reprinted in Putnam 1975c: 429–40.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1967c. “Psychological predicates,” in Capitan, W. H. and Merrill, D. (eds.), Art, Mind, and Religion. University of Pittsburgh Press, 3748. Reprinted as “The mental life of some machines,” in H.-N. Castaneda (ed.), Intentionality, Minds and Perception. Wayne State University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1969. “On properties,” in Rescher, N. et al. (eds.), Essays in Honour of Carl Hempel. Springer, 235–54.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1975a. “The meaning of ‘meaning’,” in Putnam, 1975c: 215–71.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1975b. Philosophical Papers, vol 1: Mathematics, Matter, and Method. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1975c. Philosophical Papers, vol. 2: Mind, Language, and Reality. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1975d. “It ain’t necessarily so,” in Putnam, 1975b: 237–49.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1979. “Analyticity and apriority: beyond Wittgenstein and Quine,” in French, P. and Wettstein, H. (eds.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 4. University of Minnesota Press. Reprinted in Putnam 1983c: 115–38.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1980. “Models and reality,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 45:464–82.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1981a. “Brains in a vat,” in Putnam, H., Reason, Truth, and History. Cambridge University Press, 121.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1981b. “Quantum mechanics and the observer,” Erkenntnis 16(2):193219.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1982. “Why there isn’t a ready-made world,” Synthese 51:141–67.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1983. “Why reason can’t be naturalized,” in Philosophical Papers, vol. 3: Realism and Reason. Cambridge University Press, 229–47.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1988a. Representation and Reality. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1988b. “Much ado about not very much,” Daedelus 117(1):269–81.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1992. Renewing Philosophy. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1994. “Rethinking mathematical necessity,” in Conant, J. (ed.), Words and Life. Harvard University Press, 245–63.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1997. “Functionalism: cognitive science or science fiction?” in Johnson, D. M. and Erneling, C. (eds.), The Future of the Cognitive Revolution. Oxford University Press, 3244.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 2002. The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy and Other Essays. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 2015. “Intellectual autobiography,” in Auxier, , Anderson, , and Hahn, 2015: 3–110.Google Scholar
Putnam, R. A. 2017. “Democracy as a way of life,” in Putnam, H. (ed.), Pragmatism as a Way of Life: The Lasting Legacy of William James and John Dewey. Harvard University Press, 439–54.Google Scholar
Pyle, A. 2000. “The rationality of the chemical revolution,” in Nola, R. and Sankey, H. (eds.), After Popper, Kuhn and Feyerabend. Australasian Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 15. Springer.Google Scholar
Quijano, A. 2007. “Coloniality and modernity/rationality,” Cultural Studies 21:168–78.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1936. “Truth by convention,” in Philosophical Essays for Alfred North Whitehead. Ed. Lee, O. H.. New York; 2nd edition, 1967. Reprinted in Quine, The Ways of Paradox, 2nd edition. Harvard University Press, 1976, 91–106.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1950. Methods of Logic. Holt.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1951. “Two dogmas of empiricism,” Philosophical Review 60:2043.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1953a. “Two dogmas of empiricism,” in Quine, 1953b: 20–46.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1953b. From a Logical Point of View. Harvard University Press; 3rd edition, 1980.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1953c. “On mental entities,” Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences 80:198203.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1960. Word and Object. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1961. From a Logical Point of View, revised 2nd edition. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1963. “Carnap and logical truth,” in Schilpp, 1963: 385–406.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1969. Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1972. “Methodological reflections on current linguistic theory,” in Davidson, D. and Harman, G. (eds.), Semantics of Natural Language. Reidel, 442–54.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1980 [1953]. “Reference and modality,” in From a Logical Point of View. Harvard University Press, 3rd edition, 139–59.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1981. Theories and Things. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1986. “Intellectual autobiography,” in Hahn, L. E. and Schilpp, P. A. (eds.), The Philosophy of W. V. Quine. Open Court, 346.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1990. Pursuit of Truth. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1994. “Exchange between Donald Davidson and W. V. Quine following Davidson’s lecture,” Theoria 60:226–31.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1998. From Stimulus to Science. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Quinn, W. 1989a. “Actions, intentions, and consequences: the doctrine of doing and allowing,” Philosophical Review 98:287312.Google Scholar
Quinn, W. 1989b. “Actions, intentions, and consequences: the doctrine of double effect,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 18:334–51.Google Scholar
Quinn, W. 1993. “Putting rationality in its place,” reprinted in Quinn, Morality and Action. Cambridge University Press, 228–55.Google Scholar
Quong, J. 2010. Liberalism without Perfection. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Quong, J. 2013. “Public reason,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Zalta, E. N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/public-reason/.Google Scholar
Rachels, S. 2011. “Vegetarianism,” in Beauchamp, T. and Frey, R. G. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Animal Ethics. Oxford University Press, 877905.Google Scholar
Radford, C. 1975. “How can we be moved by the fate of Anna Karenina?Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supp. vol. 49:6780.Google Scholar
Railton, P. 1984. “Alienation, consequentialism, and the demands of morality,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 133:134–71.Google Scholar
Rainer, Y. 1976. Film About a Woman Who … October 2:3967.Google Scholar
Rainer, Y. 1989. The Films of Yvonne Rainer. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Raju, P. T. 1953. Idealist Thought in India. George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Raju, P. T. 1955. “Idealisms: Eastern and Western,” Philosophy East and West 5(3):211–34.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. 1925. “The foundations of mathematics,” Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society 25:338–84.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. 1990a [1929]. “Philosophy,” in Ramsey, 1990b: 1–7.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. 1990b. Philosophical Papers. Ed Mellor, D. H.. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. 1991 [1929]. Notes on Philosophy, Probability and Mathematics. Ed. Galavotti, M. C.. Bibliopolis.Google Scholar
Ramsey, W. M. 2007. Representation Reconsidered. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rancière, J. 1991. The Ignorant Schoolmaster. Five Lessons in Intellectual Emancipation. Trans. Ross, K.. Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Rancière, J. 1995 [1992]. On the Shores of Politics. Trans. Heron, L.. Verso.Google Scholar
Rancière, J. 1999 [1995]. Disagreement: Politics and Philosophy. Trans. Rose, J.. University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Rao, K. R. 2012. “Complementarity of advaita non-dualism and yoga dualism in Indian psychology,” Journal of Consciousness Studies 19(9–10):121–42.Google Scholar
Raven, M. 2009. “Ontology, from a fundamentalist point of view.” Ph.D. thesis, New York University.Google Scholar
Raven, M. 2010. “Review of D. Chalmers, D. Manley, and R. Wasserman, eds. Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology,” Philosophy in Review 30(3):173–5.Google Scholar
Raven, M. 2012. “In defence of ground,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90(4):687701.Google Scholar
Raven, M. 2013. “Is ground a strict partial order?American Philosophical Quarterly 50(2):191–9.Google Scholar
Raven, M. 2015. “Ground,” Philosophy Compass 10(5):322–33.Google Scholar
Raven, M. 2016. “Fundamentality without foundations,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 93(3):607–26.Google Scholar
Raven, M. 2017. “New work for a theory of ground,” Inquiry 60(6):625–55.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1951. “Outline of a decision procedure for ethics,” Philosophical Review 60(2):177–97.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1955. “Two concepts of rules,” Philosophical Review 64:332.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1980. “Kantian constructivism in moral theory,” Journal of Philosophy 77:515–72.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1993. Political Liberalism. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1995. “Political liberalism: reply to Habermas,” Journal of Philosophy 92:132–80.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1996. Political Liberalism, revised edition. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1999a. A Theory of Justice: Revised. Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1999b. “Outline of a decision procedure for ethics,” in Collected Papers. Harvard University Press, 119.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1999c. “The domain of the political and overlapping consensus,” in Collected Papers. Ed. Freeman, S.. Harvard University Press, 473–96.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1999d. “The idea of an overlapping consensus,” in Collected Papers. Ed. Freeman, S.. Harvard University Press, 421–48.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 2001a. “The domain of the political and overlapping consensus,” in Collected papers. Ed. Freeman, S.. Harvard University Press, 473–96.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 2001b. “The idea of public reason revisited,” in Collected Papers. Ed. Freeman, S., 2nd edition. Harvard University Press, 573615.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 2001c. Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Ed. Kelly, E.. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 2005. Political Liberalism (expanded edition). Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1975. Practical Reason and Norms. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1990. “Facing diversity: the case of epistemic abstinence,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 19:346.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1999. Engaging Reason. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Reath, A. 2006. Agency and Autonomy in Kant’s Moral Theory. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Reath, A. and Timmermann, J. (eds.). 2010. Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason: A Critical Guide. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Recanati, F. 2010. “Singular thought, in defense of acquaintance,” in Jeshion, R. (ed.), New Essays on Singular Thought. Oxford University Press, 141–89.Google Scholar
Reck, E. H. (ed.). 2013. The Historical Turn in Analytic Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Redding, P. 2007. Analytic Philosophy and the Return of Hegelian Thought. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Redding, P. 2013. “The necessity of history for philosophy – even analytic philosophy,” Journal of the Philosophy of History 7(3):299325.Google Scholar
Redhead, M. 1987. Incompleteness, Nonlocality, and Realism: A Prolegomenon to the Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Regan, T. 2004. The Case for Animal Rights. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. 1938. Experience and Prediction: An Analysis of the Foundations and the Structure of Knowledge. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. 1956. The Direction of Time. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. 1958. The Philosophy of Space and Time. Trans. Reichenbach, M. and Freund, J.. Dover. Originally published in 1928.Google Scholar
Reid, T. 2010 [1788]. Essays on the Active Powers of Man. Ed. Haakonssen, K. and Harris, J. A.. Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Reiner, H. 1983. Duty and Inclination. Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Reisner, A. 2015. “Normative conflicts and the structure of normativity,” in Hirose, I. and Reisner, A. (eds.), Weighing and Reasoning. Oxford University Press, 189206.Google Scholar
Rescher, N. 1984. “Editorial statement,” History of Philosophy Quarterly 1(1):2.Google Scholar
Restall, G. 2000. Substructural Logic. Routledge.Google Scholar
Rhees, R. 2006. Wittgenstein and the Possibility of Discourse. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Rich, B. R. 1981. “Yvonne Rainer: an introduction,” in Rainer, 1989: 1–23.Google Scholar
Richardson, W. 1965. “Heidegger and God – and Professor Jonas,” Thought 40(1):1340.Google Scholar
Ricoeur, P. 1970. Freud and Philosophy: An Essay on Interpretation. Trans. Savage, D.. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Ricoeur, P. 1974. “Existence and hermeneutics,” in The Conflict of Interpretations: Essays in Hermeneutics. Trans. McLaughlin, K., ed. Ihde, D.. Northwestern University Press, 324.Google Scholar
Ricoeur, P. 1981. Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ricoeur, P. 1984–8. Time and Narrative, 3 vols. Trans. Blamey, K. and Pellauer, D.. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ricoeur, P. 1990. “Hermeneutics and the critique of ideology.” Trans. Thompson, J. B.. In Ormiston, G. and Schrift, A. (eds.),The Hermeneutic Tradition from Ast to Ricoeur. SUNY Press, 298334.Google Scholar
Ricoeur, P. 1995. Figuring the Sacred: Religion, Narrative, and Imagination. Trans. Wallace, M. I.. Fortress Press.Google Scholar
Riley, J. 1988. Liberal Utilitarianism: Social Choice Theory and J. S. Mill’s Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Risser, J. 1997. Hermeneutics and the Voice of the Other: Re-reading Gadamer’s Philosophical Hermeneutics. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Roberts, J. 2008. The Law-Governed Universe. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Roberts, R. C. and Wood, W. J.. 2007. Intellectual Virtues: An Essay in Regulative Epistemology. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Robinson, A. 1966. Non-Standard Analysis. North Holland.Google Scholar
Robinson, J. 2005. Deeper than Reason: Emotion and Its Role in Literature, Music, and Art. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rodman, J. 1977. “The liberation of nature?Inquiry 20:83131.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. 2002. Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. 2015. “Grounding is not a strict order,” Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1(3):517–34.Google Scholar
Rogers, J. 2013. “An editor’s reflections,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 21(6):1021–9.Google Scholar
Rohkrämer, T. 2007. A Single Communal Faith? Berghahn.Google Scholar
Rolston, H. III 2003. “Value in nature and the nature of value,” in Light, A. and Rolston, H. III (eds.), Environmental Ethics an Anthology. Blackwell, 143–53.Google Scholar
Rolston, H. III 2012. A New Environmental Ethics: The Next Millennium for Life on Earth. Routledge.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. (ed.). 1967. The Linguistic Turn: Essays in Philosophical Method. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. (ed.). 1979. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. 1980. “A reply to Dreyfus and Taylor,” Review of Metaphysics 34(1):3946.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. 1984. “The historiography of philosophy: four genres,” in Rorty, , Schneewind, , and Skinner, 1984: 49–75.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. 1989. Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. 1991. Objectivity, Relativism and Truth. Philosophical Papers, vol. 1. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. 1995. “Response to Richard Bernstein,” in Saatkamp, H. J. (ed.), Rorty and Pragmatism: The Philosopher Responds to His Critics. Vanderbilt University Press, 6871.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. 1996. “Something to steer by,” London Review of Books 18 (12 June):78.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. 1997a. “Introduction” to Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. 1997b. Philosophical Papers, vol. 4: Philosophy as Cultural Politics. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. 1998. Achieving Our Country: Leftist Thought in Twentieth-Century America. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. 1999. Philosophy and Social Hope. Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. 2006. Take Care of Freedom and Truth Will Take Care of Itself: Interviews with Richard Rorty. Ed. Mendieta, E.. Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, R., Schneewind, J. B., and Skinner, Q. (eds.). 1984. Philosophy in History. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rose, N. 1999. Powers of Freedom: Reframing Political Thought. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rosemont, H. Jr. 2015. Against Individualism: A Confucian Rethinking of the Foundations of Morality, Politics, Family, and Religion. Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Rosen, G. 2010. “Metaphysical dependence: grounding and reduction,” in Hale, B. and Hoffman, A. (eds.), Modality: Metaphysics, Logic, and Epistemology. Oxford University Press, 109–36.Google Scholar
Rosen, G. 2015. “Real definition,” Analytic Philosophy 56(3):189209.Google Scholar
Rosen, S. 2002. The Elusiveness of the Ordinary. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, A. 2014. “Disenchanted naturalism,” in Bashour, B. and Muller, H. (eds.), Contemporary Philosophical Naturalism and Its Implications. Routledge, 1736.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, J. 2007a. “Sellars and Quine: compare and contrast,” in Wilfrid Sellars: Fusing the Images. Oxford University Press, 3346.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, J. 2007b. “Sellarsian picturing,” in Wilfrid Sellars: Fusing the Images. Oxford University Press, 104–26.Google Scholar
Rosenberger, R. and Verbeek, P. P.. 2015. “A field guide to postphenomenology,” in Rosenberger, R. and Verbeek, P. P. (eds.), Postphenomenological Investigations: Essays on Human–Technology Relations. Lexington Books, 941.Google Scholar
Rosenblatt, F. 1958. “The perceptron: a probabilistic model for information storage and organization in the brain,” Psychological Review 65:386408.Google Scholar
Rosenbloom, P. 1950. The Elements of Mathematical Logic. Dover.Google Scholar
Rosenlee, L. L. 2007. Confucianism and Women: A Philosophical Interpretation. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Rosenthal, D. M. 1986. “Two concepts of consciousness,” Philosophical Studies 49:329–59.Google Scholar
Roski, S. and Schnieder, B. (eds.) forthcoming. Bernard Bolzano’s Philosophy of Grounding. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ross, S. 1998. What Gardens Mean. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. 2002 [1930]. The Right and the Good, 2nd edition. Ed. Stratton-Lake, P.. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. 1954. Kant’s Ethical Theory. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rossi, E. 2010. “Modus vivendi, consensus, and (realist) liberal legitimacy,” Public Reason 2:2139.Google Scholar
Rossi, E. 2013a. “Can tolerance be grounded in equal respect?European Journal of Political Theory 12:240–52.Google Scholar
Rossi, E. 2013b. “Consensus, compromise, justice and legitimacy,” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 16(4):557–72.Google Scholar
Rossi, E. 2014. “Legitimacy, democracy and public justification: Rawls’ political liberalism versus Gaus’ justificatory liberalism,” Res Publica 20:925.Google Scholar
Rossi, E. and Sleat, M.. 2014. “Realism in normative political theory,” Philosophy Compass 9/10:689701.Google Scholar
Routley, R. 1973. “Is there a need for a new environmental ethic?Proceedings of the XVth World Congress of Philosophy 17th–22nd September 1973, Varna, Bulgaria. Sofia Press, 205–10.Google Scholar
Rowe, W. L. 1975. The Cosmological Argument. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Rowe, W. L. 1978. Philosophy of Religion: An Introduction. Wadsworth.Google Scholar
Rowe, W. L. 1979. “The problem of evil and some varieties of atheism,” American Philosophical Quarterly 16:335–41.Google Scholar
Ruben, D. 1990. Explaining Explanation. Routledge.Google Scholar
Ruben, D. (ed.). 1993. Explanation. Oxford University Press,Google Scholar
Rud, A. G., Garrison, J., and Stone, L. (eds.). 2009. John Dewey at 150: Reflections for a New Century. Purdue University Press.Google Scholar
Ruitenberg, C. W. 2010. “Queer politics in schools: a Rancièrean reading,” Educational Philosophy and Theory 42(5–6):618–34.Google Scholar
Rumelhart, D. E. and McClelland, J. L.. 1986. “On learning the past tenses of English verbs,” in Rumelhart, , McClelland, , and the PDP Research Group 1986: 216–71.Google Scholar
Rumelhart, D. E., McClelland, J. L., and the PDP Research Group. 1986. Parallel Distributed Processing: Explorations in the Microstructure of Cognition, vol. 1: Foundations. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Rundle, B. 1997. Mind in Action. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Russell, B. 1900. A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz; 2nd edition, Allen, George & Unwin, , 1937. Reprinted Routledge, 1992.Google Scholar
Russell, B. 1905. “On denoting,” Mind 14:479–93.Google Scholar
Russell, B. 1910. “The monistic theory of truth,” in Philosophical Essays. George Allen & Unwin, 131–46.Google Scholar
Russell, B. 1910–11. “Knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 11:108–28. Reprinted in Russell 1992.Google Scholar
Russell, B. 1914. Our Knowledge of the External World. Open Court.Google Scholar
Russell, B. 1917. “On the scientific method in philosophy,” in Mysticism and Logic. George Allen & Unwin, 7593. Originally published in Hibbert Journal, 1914.Google Scholar
Russell, B. 1918–19. “The philosophy of logical atomism,” The Monist 28, 29: 495527, 32–63, 190–222, 345–80. Reprinted as The Philosophy of Logical Atomism. Open Court, 1985.Google Scholar
Russell, B. 1945. A History of Western Philosophy. George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Russell, B. 1948. Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits. George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Russell, B. 1989 [1959]. Wisdom of the West. Crescent Books.Google Scholar
Russell, B. 1992. Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell, vol. 6. Routledge.Google Scholar
Russell, B. 2009 [1914]. Our Knowledge of the External World. Routledge.Google Scholar
Russell, B. and Copleston, F. C.. 1970. “The existence of God,” in Hick, J. (ed.), Classical and Contemporary Readings in the Philosophy of Religion, 2nd edition. Prentice Hall, 282301.Google Scholar
Russell, B. and Whitehead, A. N.. 1910. Principia Mathematica, vol. 1. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Russell, Bill and Branch, T.. 1979. Second Wind: The Memoirs of an Opinionated Man. Random House.Google Scholar
Russell, D. C. 2009. Practical Intelligence and the Virtues. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Russell, G. 2008. Truth in Virtue of Meaning. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ryan, A. 1997. John Dewey and the High Tide of American Liberalism. Norton.Google Scholar
Ryle, G. 1950. “‘If’, ‘so’, and ‘because’,” in Black, M. (ed.), Philosophical Analysis. Cornell University Press, 323–40. Reprinted in Ryle 2009: 234–49.Google Scholar
Ryle, G. 1953. Dilemmas. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ryle, G. 2002 [1949]. The Concept of Mind. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ryle, G. 2009. Collected Essays 1929–1968, vol. 2 of Collected Papers. Routledge.Google Scholar
Saito, N. 2006. The Gleam of Light: Moral Perfectionism and Education in Dewey and Emerson. Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
Saito, Y. 1997. “The Japanese aesthetics of imperfection and insufficiency,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 55(4):377–85.Google Scholar
Saito, Y. 1999. “Japanese aesthetics of packaging,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 57(2):257365.Google Scholar
Saito, Y. 2007. Everyday Aesthetics. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, N. 1986. Frege’s Puzzle. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. C. 1984. Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. C. 1999. “Scientific explanation,” in Salmon, W. C. et al. (eds.), Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Hackett, 741.Google Scholar
Samuel, A. L. 1959. “Some studies in machine learning using the game of checkers,” IBM Journal of Research and Development 3:211–29. Reprinted in E. Feigenbaum and J. Feldman (eds.), Computers and Thought. McGraw-Hill, 1963, 71–108.Google Scholar
Sandis, C. 2012. The Things We Do and Why We Do Them. Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Santas, G. X. 1993. “Does Aristotle have a virtue ethics?Philosophical Inquiry 15(3–4):132. Reprinted in D. Statman (ed.), Virtue Ethics. Edinburgh University Press, 1997, 260–85.Google Scholar
Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1943. L’être et le néant. Gallimard.Google Scholar
Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1946. L’existentialisme est un humanisme. Éditions Nagel.Google Scholar
Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1956 [1943]. Being and Nothingness: A Phenomenological Essay on Ontology. Trans. Barnes, H.. Philosophical Library.Google Scholar
Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1963. Saint Genet: Actor and Martyr. Trans. Frechtman, B.. Pantheon.Google Scholar
Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1964. The Words. Trans. Frechtman, B.. Vintage.Google Scholar
Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1981, 1987, 1989. The Idiot of the Family: Gustave Flaubert, 1821–1857, 3 vols. Trans. Cosman, C.. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1994. Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions. Trans. Mairet, P.. Routledge.Google Scholar
Sartre, Jean-Paul. 2001 [1946]. “Existentialism is a humanism.” Trans. Frechtman, B.. In Guignon, C. and Pereboom, D. (eds.), Existentialism: Basic Writings. Hackett, 290308.Google Scholar
Sartre, Jean-Paul. 2018. Being and Nothingness: An Essay in Phenomenological Ontology. Trans. Richmond, S.. Routledge.Google Scholar
Saussure, F. de. 1916. Cours de linguistique générale. Payot. (Reconstructed by C. Bally, A. Sechehaye, and A. Riedlinger.)Google Scholar
Savage, L. J. 1972. The Foundations of Statistics, 2nd edition. Dover.Google Scholar
Savickey, B. 1999. Wittgenstein’s Art of Investigation. Routledge.Google Scholar
Sawyer, S. 1998. “Privileged access to the world,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76(4):523–33.Google Scholar
Sawyer, S. 2001. “The epistemic divide,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 39(3):385401.Google Scholar
Sayre, K. M. 1965. Recognition: A Study in the Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence. University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Sayre, K. M. 1969. Consciousness: A Philosophic Study of Minds and Machines. Random House.Google Scholar
Sayre, K. M. 1973. “Machine recognition of handwritten words: a project report,” Pattern Recognition 5:213–28.Google Scholar
Sayre, K. M. 1976. Cybernetics and the Philosophy of Mind. Humanities Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 1982. “Contractualism and utilitarianism,” in Sen, A. and Williams, B. (eds.), Utilitarianism and Beyond. Cambridge University Press, 103–28.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 2014. Being Realistic about Reasons. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Scerri, E. R. and McIntyre, L.. 1997. “The case for the philosophy of chemistry,” Synthese 111:213–32.Google Scholar
Schacht, R. (ed.). 1994. Nietzsche, Genealogy, and Morality: Essays on Nietzsche’s Genealogy of Morality. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Schacht, R. 2012. “Nietzsche: after the death of God,” in Crowell, 2012a: 111–36.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. 2000a. “Trumping preemption,” Journal of Philosophy 9:165–81.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. 2000b. “Causation by disconnection,” Philosophy of Science 67:285300.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. 2004. “Causes need not be physically connected to their effects: the case for negative causation,” in Hitchcock, C. (ed.), Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Science. Blackwell, 197216.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. 2005. “Contrastive causation,” Philosophical Review 114:297328.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. 2009. “On what grounds what,” in Chalmers, D., Manley, D., and Wasserman, R. (eds.), Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Oxford University Press, 347–83.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. 2012a. “Grounding, transitivity, and contrastivity,” in Correia, F. and Schnieder, B. (eds.), Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality. Cambridge University Press, 122–38.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. 2012b. “Disconnection and responsibility,” Legal Theory 18:399435.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. 2016. “Grounding in the image of causation,” Philosophical Studies 173(1):49100.Google Scholar
Scharff, R. C. 2014. How History Matters to Philosophy: Reconsidering Philosophy’s Past after Positivism. Routledge.Google Scholar
Schechner, R. 2010. “The conservative avant-garde,” New Literary History 41:895913.Google Scholar
Scheffler, I. 1954. “Toward an analytic philosophy of education,” Harvard Educational Review 24(4):223–30.Google Scholar
Scheffler, I. 1965. The Language of Education. Charles C. Thomas.Google Scholar
Scheffler, I. 1966. Philosophy and Education: Modern Readings.: Allyn and Bacon.Google Scholar
Scheffler, I. 1978. Conditions of Knowledge: An Introduction to Epistemology and Education. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Scheffler, S. 1982. The Rejection of Consequentialism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schellekens, E. 2007. Aesthetics and Morality. Continuum.Google Scholar
Schellekens, E. and Goldie, P. (eds.). 2011. The Aesthetic Mind: Philosophy and Psychology. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schellenberg, J. 1993. Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Schier, F. 1987. Deeper into Pictures. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schiffer, S. 1987. Remnants of Meaning. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Schiffer, S. 1996. “Contextualist solutions to skepticism,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (new series) 96:317–33.Google Scholar
Schiffer, W. 1980. Theorien der Geschichtsschreibung und ihre erzähltheoretische Relevanz. Metzler.Google Scholar
Schilpp, P. A. (ed.). 1963. The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. Open Court.Google Scholar
Schilpp, P. A. and Hahn, L. E. (eds.). 1984. The Philosophy of Gabriel Marcel. Open Court.Google Scholar
Schiølin, K. H. 2015. “Teknologipessimisme.” Ph.D. thesis, Aarhus University.Google Scholar
Schleiermacher, F. D. E. 1998 [1834]. Hermeneutics and Criticism. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schlick, M. 1979 [1932]. “Form and content,” in Philosophical Papers, vol. 2. Reidel, 285369.Google Scholar
Schmaltz, T. M. 2012. “JHP and history of philosophy today,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 25(4):477–81.Google Scholar
Schneewind, J. B. 1990. “The misfortunes of virtue,” Ethics 101(1):4263.Google Scholar
Schneewind, J. B. 1996. “Baier’s theory of morality: a historical introduction,” in Schneewind, J. B. (ed.), Reason, Ethics, and Society: Themes from Kurt Baier, with His Responses. Open Court, 119.Google Scholar
Schneider, A. and Woolf, D. (eds.). 2011. The Oxford History of Historical Writing, vol. 5: Historical Writing since 1945. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schnieder, B. 2006a. “Troubles with truth-making: necessitation and projection,” Erkenntnis 64(1):6174.Google Scholar
Schnieder, B. 2006b. “A certain kind of trinity: dependence, substance, explanation,” Philosophical Studies 129(2):393419.Google Scholar
Schnieder, B. 2011. “A logic for ‘because’,” Review of Symbolic Logic 4:445–65.Google Scholar
Scholz, B. C. 1990. “Kripke’s Wittgensteinian paradox.” Ph.D. thesis, Ohio State University, Columbus.Google Scholar
Scholz, B. C. and Pullum, G. K.. 2006. “Irrational nativist exuberance,” in Stainton, R. J. (ed.), Contemporary Debates in Cognitive Science. Blackwell, 5980.Google Scholar
Schönbaumsfeld, G. 2016. The Illusion of Doubt. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schönecker, D. and Wood, A.. 2015. Immanuel Kant’s Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals: A Commentary. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Schopenhauer, A. 1966 [1818–19]. The World as Will and Representation. Trans Payne, E. F. J.. Dover.Google Scholar
Schrӧdinger, E. 1952. “Are there quantum jumps?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 3:109–23 and 233–42.Google Scholar
Schroeder, S. 2001. “Are reasons causes? A Wittgensteinian response to Davidson,” in Schroeder, S. (ed.), Wittgenstein and Contemporary Philosophy of Mind. Palgrave Macmillan, 150–70.Google Scholar
Schueler, G. F. 1995. Desire: Its Role in Practical Reason and the Explanation of Action. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Schueler, G. F. 2003. Reasons and Purposes: Human Rationality and the Teleological Explanation of Action. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schutte, O. 1993. Cultural Identity and Social Liberation in Latin American Thought. State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Sclove, R. E. 1995. Democracy and Technology. The Guilford Press.Google Scholar
Sclove, R. E. 2001. Interview: “The democratic uses of technology,” The NEA Higher Education Journal. www.nea.org/assets/img/PubThoughtAndAction/TAA_98Spr_01.pdf.Google Scholar
Scott, J. W. 2007. The Politics of the Veil. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Scruton, R. 1974. Art and Imagination. Methuen.Google Scholar
Scruton, R. 2009. Beauty. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Searle, J. 1980. “Minds, brains, and programs,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3:417–57. (Includes peer-commentaries, and reply.)Google Scholar
Searle, J. 1982. “The Chinese Room revisited: response to further commentaries on ‘Minds, Brains, and Programs’,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5:345–8.Google Scholar
Searle, J. 1983. Intentionality. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Searle, J. 1987. “Indeterminacy, empiricism, and the first person,” Journal of Philosophy 84(3):123–46.Google Scholar
Searle, J. 1990. “Is the brain’s mind a computer program?” Scientific American (January):20–5.Google Scholar
Searle, J. 1992. The Rediscovery of the Mind. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Searle, J. 2004. Mind: A Brief Introduction. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Segerberg, K. 1973. “Two-dimensional modal logic,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 2:7796.Google Scholar
Sehon, S. 2000. “An argument against the causal theory of action,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60:6785.Google Scholar
Sehon, S. 2016. Free Will and Action Explanation. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Seibt, J. 2016. “How to naturalize sensory consciousness and intentionality within a process monism with a normativity gradient: a reading of Sellars,” in O’Shea, J. (ed.), Sellars and His Legacy. Oxford University Press, 186222.Google Scholar
Selfridge, Oliver. 1955. “Pattern recognition and modern computers,” in Proceedings of the 1955 Western Joint Computer Conference, March, 91–3.Google Scholar
Selfridge, Oliver. 1956. “Pattern recognition and learning,” in Cherry, C. (ed.), Proceedings of the Third London Symposium on Information Theory. Academic Press, 345–53.Google Scholar
Selfridge, Oliver. 1959. “Pandemonium: a paradigm for learning,” in Blake, D. V. and Uttley, A. M. (eds.), The Mechanization of Thought Processes, 2 vols. Her Majesty’s Stationery Office, vol. 1, 511–29.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. 1949. “Language, rules and behavior,” in Hook, S. (ed.), John Dewey: Philosopher of Science and Freedom. The Dial Press, 289315.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. 1963a. “Empiricism and the philosophy of mind,” in Science, Perception, and Reality. Ridgeview, 127–96.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. 1963b. “Some reflections on language games,” in Science, Perception, and Reality. Ridgeview, 321–58.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. 1967. Science and Metaphysics. Ridgeview.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. 1997 [1956]. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, A. 1982. “Rights and agency,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 11:339.Google Scholar
Sen, A. 1992. Inequality Reexamined. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Sen, A. 2001. Development as Freedom. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, I. 1957. “Sri Aurobindo as a world philosopher,” Philosophy East and West 7(3/4):131–41.Google Scholar
Setiya, K. 2007. Reasons without Rationalism. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Shakespeare, W. 1970 [1599–1602?] The Tragical History of Hamlet Prince of Denmark. Penguin.Google Scholar
Shapere, D. 1982. “The concept of observation in science and philosophy,” Philosophy of Science 49(4):485525.Google Scholar
Shapiro, T. 2009. “The nature of inclination,” Ethics 119:229–56.Google Scholar
Sharp, H. and Taylor, C. (eds.). 2016. Feminist Philosophies of Life. McGill-Queen’s University Press.Google Scholar
Sharpe, R. A. 2000. Music and Humanism: An Essay in the Aesthetics of Music. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Shaw, J. L. 2016. The Collected Writings of Jaysankar Lal Shaw: Indian Analytic and Anglophone Philosophy. Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Shelah, S. 1982. Proper Forcing. Springer.Google Scholar
Shelah, S. 1986. Around Classification Theory of Models. Springer.Google Scholar
Sherman, N. 1997. Making a Necessity of Virtue. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shields, J. M. 2011. Critical Buddhism: Engaging with Modern Japanese Buddhist Thought. Routledge.Google Scholar
Shiner, L. 2001. The Invention of Art: A Cultural History. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Shiu-Hwa Tsu, P. 2010. “Can morality be codified?Australian Journal of Professional and Applied Ethics 11(1&2):145–54.Google Scholar
Shklar, J. 1989. “The liberalism of fear,” in Rosenblum, N. (ed.), Liberalism and the Moral Life. Harvard University Press, 2138.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 1975a. “Functionalism and qualia,” Philosophical Studies 27:292315.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 1975b. “Phenomenal Similarity,” Critica 7:337.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 1982. “The inverted spectrum,” Journal of Philosophy 79:357–81.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 1991. “Qualia and consciousness,” Mind 100:507–24.Google Scholar
Shrivastava, S. N. L. 1956. “The absolute in Bradley and Śaṃkara,” Philosophy East and West 6(2):99111.Google Scholar
Shun, Kwong-loi and Wong, D. (eds.). 2004. Confucian Ethics: A Comparative Study of Self, Autonomy, and Community. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shusterman, R. 2008. Body Consciousness: A Philosophy of Mindfulness and Somaesthetics. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sibley, F. 2001. Approach to Aesthetics: Collected Papers on Philosophical Aesthetics. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Sider, T. 2001. Four-Dimensionalism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sider, T. 2011. Writing the Book of the World. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sider, T. 2013. “Replies to Dorr, Fine, and Hirsch,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 87(3):733–54.Google Scholar
Siderits, M. 1991. Indian Philosophy of Language. Kluwer Academic.Google Scholar
Siderits, M. 2003. Personal Identity and Buddhist Philosophy: Empty Persons. Ashgate.Google Scholar
Siderits, M., Thompson, E., and Zahavi, D. (eds.). 2011. Self, No Self? Perspective from Analytical, Phenomenological, & Indian Traditions. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Siderits, M., Tillemans, T. J. F., and Chakrabarti, A. (eds.). 2011. Apoha: Buddhist Nominalism and Human Cognition. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Sidgwick, H. 1907. The Method of Ethics, 7th edition. Macmillan.Google Scholar
Sidorkin, A. [Sasha] M. 1999a. “The fine art of sitting on two stools: multicultural education between postmodernism and critical theory,” Studies in Philosophy and Education 18(3):143–56.Google Scholar
Sidorkin, A. 1999b. Beyond Discourse: Education, the Self, and Dialogue. State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Siegel, H. 1985. “Educating reason: critical thinking, informal logic, and the philosophy of education. Part two: philosophical questions underlying education for critical thinking,” Philosophy Articles and Papers 14. http://scholarlyrepository.miami.edu/philosophy_articles/14.Google Scholar
Siegel, H. 1987. Relativism Refuted: A Critique of Contemporary Epistemological Relativism. Springer.Google Scholar
Siegel, H. 1988. Educating Reason: Rationality, Critical Thinking, and Education. Routledge.Google Scholar
Siegel, H. 1997. Rationality Redeemed? Further Dialogues on an Educational Ideal. Routledge.Google Scholar
Siegel, H. 1998. “Knowledge, truth and education,” in Carr, D. (ed.), Education, Knowledge, and Truth: Beyond the Postmodern Impasse. Routledge, 1936.Google Scholar
Siegel, H. and Biro, J.. 2006. “In defense of the objective epistemic approach to argumentation,” Informal Logic 25(3):91101.Google Scholar
Siegel, S. 2004. “Indiscriminability and the phenomenal,” Philosophical Studies 120:90112.Google Scholar
Siegel, S. 2006. “Which properties are represented in perception?” in Szabó Gendler, T. and Hawthorne, J. (eds.), Perceptual Experience. Oxford University Press, 481503.Google Scholar
Siewert, C. 1998. The Significance of Consciousness. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Siewert, C. 2004. “Is experience transparent?Philosophical Studies 117:1541.Google Scholar
Siewert, C. 2005. “Attention and sensorimotor intentionality,” in Smith, and Thomasson, 2005: 270–94.Google Scholar
Siewert, C. 2011. “Phenomenal thought,” in Bayne, and Montague, 2011: 236–67.Google Scholar
Silverstein, M. 2016. “Teleology and normativity,” in Shafer-Landau, R. (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics 11. Oxford University Press, 214–40.Google Scholar
Sinnerbrink, R. 2011. New Philosophies of Film: Thinking Images. Continuum.Google Scholar
Sim, M. 2015. “Why Confucius’ ethics is a virtue ethics,” in Besser-Jones, L. and Slote, M. (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Virtue Ethics. Routledge, 6376.Google Scholar
Simon, H. A. 1962. “The architecture of complexity,” Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 106:467–82.Google Scholar
Simons, M. 1999. Beauvoir and the Second Sex: Feminism, Race, and the Origins of Existentialism. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Simpson, G. G. 1961. Principles of Animal Taxonomy. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Simpson, S. 1982. Subsystems of Second-Order Arithmetic. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Singer, P. 2009. Animal Liberation. HarperCollins.Google Scholar
Sircello, G. 1975. A New Theory of Beauty. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Skiles, A. 2015. “Against grounding necessitarianism,” Erkenntnis 80(4):717–51.Google Scholar
Skinner, B. F. 1957. Verbal Behavior. Appleton-Century-Crofts.Google Scholar
Skinner, Q. 1969. “Meaning and understanding in the history of ideas,” History and Theory 8(1):353. Abbreviated and revised in Skinner 2002: 57–89.Google Scholar
Skinner, Q. 2002. Visions of Politics, vol. 1: Regarding Method. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sklar, L. 1967. “Types of inter-theoretic reduction,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 18(2):109–24.Google Scholar
Sklar, L. 1974. Space, Time, and Spacetime. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Sklar, L. (ed.). 2000. Explanation, Law and Cause. Routledge.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. 1990. The Dynamics of Rational Deliberation. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. 2004. The Stag Hunt and the Evolution of Social Structure. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sleat, M. 2010. “Bernard Williams and the possibility of a realist political theory,” European Journal of Political Theory 9:485503.Google Scholar
Slingerland, E. 2014. Trying Not to Try: Ancient China, Modern Science, and the Power of Spontaneity. Crown.Google Scholar
Sloman, A. 1971. “Interactions between philosophy and AI: the role of intuition and non-logical reasoning in intelligence,” Artificial Intelligence 2:209–25.Google Scholar
Sloman, A. 1978 et seq. The Computer Revolution in Philosophy: Philosophy, Science, and Models of Mind. Harvester Press. Available and continually updated at www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/cogaff/crp/.Google Scholar
Sloman, A. 1979. “The primacy of non-communicative language,” in Macafferty, M. and Gray, K. (eds.), The Analysis of Meaning, Informatics 5 Proceedings ASLIB/BCS Conference, Oxford (March):115.Google Scholar
Sloman, A. 1987. “Motives, mechanisms, and emotions,” Cognition and Emotion 1:217–33. Reprinted in M. A. Boden (ed.), The Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence. Oxford University Press, 1990, 231–47.Google Scholar
Sloman, A. 1993. “The mind as a control system,” in Hookway, C. and Peterson, D. (eds.), Philosophy and the Cognitive Sciences. Cambridge University Press, 69110.Google Scholar
Sloman, A. 2000. “Architectural requirements for human-like agents both natural and artificial (what sorts of machine can love?),” in Dautenhahn, K. (ed.), Human Cognition and Social Agent Technology: Advances in Consciousness Research. John Benjamins, 163–95.Google Scholar
Sloman, A. 2010. “Phenomenal and access consciousness and the ‘hard’ problem: a view from the designer stance,” International Journal of Machine Consciousness 2(1):117–69. Also available at www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/cogaff/crp/.Google Scholar
Sloman, A. and Chrisley, R.. 2003. “Virtual machines and consciousness,” Journal of Consciousness Studies 10:113–72.Google Scholar
Slote, M. 1989 [1983]. Goods and Virtues. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Slote, M. 1992. From Morality to Virtue. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Slote, M. 1997. “Virtue ethics,” in Baron, M., Pettit, P., and Slote, M., Three Methods of Ethics: A Debate. Blackwell, 175238.Google Scholar
Slote, M. 2001. Morals from Motives. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. 1956. “Extreme and restricted utilitarianism,” Philosophical Quarterly 6:344–54.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. 1959. “Sensations and brain processes,” Philosophical Review 68:141–56.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. 1973. “An outline of a system of utilitarian ethics,” in Smart, and Williams, 1973: 3–74.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. and Williams, B. A. O.. 1973. Utilitarianism: For and Against. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Smeyers, P. 1993. “Some radical consequences for educational research from a Wittgensteinian point of view or does almost anything go?” Philosophy of Education Society Yearbook, 139–47.Google Scholar
Smeyers, P. 1995. “Initiation and newness in education and child-rearing,” in Smeyers, P. and Marshall, J. (eds.), Philosophy and Education: Accepting Wittgenstein’s Challenge. Kluwer, 105–25.Google Scholar
Smeyers, P. 2008. “Images and pictures: seeing and imagining,” in Peters, M. A, Burbules, N., and Smeyers, P. (eds.), Saying and Doing: Wittgenstein as a Pedagogical Philosopher. Paradigm Press.Google Scholar
Smeyers, P. and Burbules, N.. 2005. “‘Practice’: a central educational concept,” in Howe, K. et al. (eds.), Philosophy of Education. Philosophy of Education Society, 336–43.Google Scholar
Smeyers, P. and Peters, M. A. (eds.). 2006. Postfoundationalist Themes in the Philosophy of Education. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Smeyers, P., Smith, R., and Standish, P.. 2007. The Therapy of Education: Philosophy, Happiness and Personal Growth. Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Smith, B. C. 1986. On the Origin of Objects. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Smith, B. C. (ed.). 2007. Questions of Taste: The Philosophy of Wine. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, D. W. 1986. “The structure of (self-)consciousness,” Topoi 5(2):149–56.Google Scholar
Smith, D. W. 1995. “Mind and body,” in Smith, D. W. and Smith, B. (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Husserl. Cambridge University Press, 323–93.Google Scholar
Smith, D. W. 2004. Mind World: Essays in Phenomenology and Ontology. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, D. W. 2013. Husserl. Routledge, 2nd edition. 1st edition 2007.Google Scholar
Smith, D. W. and McIntyre, R.. 1971. “Intentionality via intensions,” Journal of Philosophy 68:541–61.Google Scholar
Smith, D. W. and McIntyre, R.. 1982. Husserl and Intentionality: A Study of Mind, Meaning, and Language. Reidel.Google Scholar
Smith, D. W. and Thomasson, A. L. (eds.). 2005. Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, M. 1994. The Moral Problem. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Smith, N. H. 2015. “Hermeneutics and critical theory,” in Malpas, J. and Gander, H.-H. (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Hermeneutics. Routledge, 600–11.Google Scholar
Smith, R. D. and Burbules, N.. 2005. “What it makes sense to say: Wittgenstein, rule-following and the nature of education,” Educational Philosophy and Theory 37(3):417–22.Google Scholar
Smuts, B. B. 1985. Sex and Friendship in Baboons. Transaction.Google Scholar
Snapper, J. W. 1985. “Responsibility for computer-based errors,” Metaphilosophy 16:289–95.Google Scholar
Snow, N. E. 2010. Virtue as Social Intelligence. Routledge.Google Scholar
Snowdon, P. 1980/81. “Perception, vision, and causation,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 81:175–92.Google Scholar
Snyder, L. J. 1994. “Is evidence historical?” in Achinstein, P. and Snyder, L. J. (eds.), Scientific Methods: Conceptual and Historical Problems. Krieger, 95117.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 1987. “Direct reference, propositional attitudes, and semantic content,” Philosophical Topics 15:4487. Reprinted in Soames 2009b: 33–71.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 1991. “The necessity argument,” Linguistics and Philosophy 14:575–80.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2002. Beyond Rigidity. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2003a. Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, vol. 1. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2003b. Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, vol. 2. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2005a. Reference and Description. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2005b. “Naming and asserting,” in Szabo, Z. Gendler (ed.), Semantics versus Pragmatics. Oxford University Press, 356–82. Reprinted in Soames 2009a: 251–77.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2005c. “Why incomplete descriptions do not defeat Russell’s theory of descriptions,” Teorema 24:730. Reprinted in Soames 2009a: 377–99.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2006. “Understanding assertion,” in Thomson, J. J. and Byrne, A. (eds.), Content and Modality: Themes from the Philosophy of Robert Stalnaker. Oxford University Press, 222–50. Reprinted in Soames 2009b: 211–42.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2007. “What we know now that we didn’t know then,” Philosophical Studies 135:461–78.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2008a. “Drawing the line between meaning and implicature – and relating both to assertion,” Noûs 42:529–54. Reprinted in Soames 2009a: 298–325.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2008b. “Truth and meaning – in perspective,” in P. French (ed.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31:119. Reprinted in Soames 2009a: 225–47.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2008c. “Why propositions can’t be sets of truth-supporting circumstances,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 37:267–76. Reprinted in Soames 2009b: 72–80.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2009a. Philosophical Essays, vol. 1. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2009b. Philosophical Essays, vol. 2. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2009c. “The gap between meaning and assertion: why what we literally say often differs from what our words literally mean,” in Soames, 2009a: 278–97.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2010a. What Is Meaning? Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2010b. Philosophy of Language. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2013. “Quine’s position in the history of analytic philosophy,” in Harman, G. and Lepore, E. (eds.), A Companion to W. V. O. Quine. Wiley-Blackwell, 232–64.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2014. The Analytic Tradition in Philosophy, vol. I. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2015a. Rethinking Language, Mind, and Meaning. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2015b. “Reply to critics (Beaney, Kelly, McGrath, and Pigden) of The Analytic Tradition in Philosophy, Vol. I,” Philosophical Studies 172:1,681–96.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 2018. The Analytic Tradition in Philosophy, vol. 2: A New Vision. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Soare, R. 1996. “Computability and recursion,” Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2:284321.Google Scholar
Sober, E. 1980. “Evolution, population thinking, and essentialism,” Philosophy of Science 47(3):350–83.Google Scholar
Sober, E. 2000. “Quine,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supplementary volume 74:237–80.Google Scholar
Sober, E. and Wilson, D. S.. 1998. Unto Others. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sokal, A. and Bricmont, J.. 1998. Fashionable Nonsense: Postmodern Intellectuals’ Abuse of Science. Picador.Google Scholar
Solomon, D. 1988. “Internal objections to virtue ethics,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 13(1):428–41.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. (ed.). 1975. Causation and Conditionals. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. 1980. “The raft and the pyramid: coherence versus foundations in the theory of knowledge,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5(1):326.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. 1991. Knowledge in Perspective. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. 1999. “How to defeat opposition to Moore,” Philosophical Perspectives 13:141–53.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. 2007. A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. 2011. Knowing Full Well. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. 2015. Judgment and Agency. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Speaks, J. 2009. “Transparency, intentionalism, and the nature of perceptual content,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79:539–73.Google Scholar
Spector, J. J. 1973. The Aesthetics of Freud: A Study in Psychoanalysis and Art. Praeger.Google Scholar
Sperber, D. and Wilson, D.. 1986. Relevance. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Spirtes, P., Glymour, C., and Scheines, R.. 2000. Causation, Prediction, and Search, 2nd edition. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Spitz, E. H. 1991. Image and Insight: Essays in Psychoanalysis and the Arts. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Staal, F. 1988. Universals: Studies in Indian Logic and Linguistics. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Stainton, R. J. 2014. Philosophy of Linguistics. Oxford Handbooks Online.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. 1984. Inquiry. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. 1999 [1970]. “Pragmatics,” Synthese 22:272–89. Reprinted in Stalnaker Context and Content. Oxford University Press, 1999, 1–46.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. 2008. Our Knowledge of the Internal World. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stambaugh, J. 1990. Impermanence Is Buddha-Nature: Dōgen’s Understanding of Temporality. University of Hawai‘i Press.Google Scholar
Stampe, D. 1977. “Toward a causal theory of linguistic representation,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 2(1):4263.Google Scholar
Standaert, N. 1995. “The discovery of the center through the periphery: a preliminary study of Fung Youlan’s History of Chinese Philosophy (New Version),” Philosophy East and West 45(4):569–90.Google Scholar
Standaert, N. and Giever, B.. 2003. “Feng Youlan (Fung Yu-lan): works on the history of Chinese philosophy,” in Cua, 2003: 261–7.Google Scholar
Standish, P. 1992. Beyond the Self: Wittgenstein, Heidegger, and the Limits of Language. Avebury.Google Scholar
Standish, P. 2002. “Essential Heidegger: poetics of the unsaid,” in Peters, M. A. (ed.), Heidegger, Education, and Modernity. Rowman & Littlefield, 151–70.Google Scholar
Standish, P. 2008. “Levinas and the language of the curriculum,” in Egéa-Kuehne, D. (ed.), Levinas and Education: At the Intersection of Faith and Reason. Routledge, 5666.Google Scholar
Standish, P. 2012. Beyond the Self: Wittgenstein, Heidegger, Levinas, and the Limits of Language. Hosei University Press.Google Scholar
Standish, P., Smeyers, P., and Smith, R.. 2006. The Therapy of Education: Philosophy, Happiness and Personal Growth. Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Stanley, J. 2005. Knowledge and Practical Interests. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stecker, R. 1997. Artworks: Definition, Meaning, Value. Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
Stecker, R. 2003. Interpretation and Construction: Art, Speech, and the Law. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Stengel, B. S. 2009. “More than ‘mere ideas’: Deweyan tools for the contemporary philosopher,” in Rud, A., Garrison, J., and Stone, L. (eds.), John Dewey at 150: Reflections for a New Century. Purdue University Press, 7383.Google Scholar
Sterelny, K. 2006. “The evolution and evolvability of culture,” Mind & Language 21(2):137–65.Google Scholar
Sterelny, K. and Griffiths, P.. 1999. Sex and Death: An Introduction to Philosophy of Biology. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Stern, D. G. 2004. Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations: An Introduction. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stern, D. N. 2000. The Interpersonal World of the Infant: A View from Psychoanalysis and Developmental Psychology. Basic Books.Google Scholar
Stern, D. N. 2009. The First Relationship. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Steward, H. 2012. “Actions as processes,” Philosophical Perspectives 26:373–88.Google Scholar
Stewart, J. (ed.). 1998. The Debate between Sartre and Merleau-Ponty. Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Stickney, J. 2005. “Teaching and learning in Wittgenstein’s philosophic method,” in Howe, K. (ed.), Philosophy of Education Society Yearbook. Philosophy of Education Society, 299308.Google Scholar
Stickney, J. 2008a. “Wittgenstein’s ‘relativity’: agreement in forms of life and training in language-games,” Educational Philosophy and Theory 40:621–37.Google Scholar
Stickney, J. 2008b. “Training and mastery of techniques in Wittgenstein’s later philosophy: a response to Michael Luntley,” Educational Philosophy and Theory 40:678–94.Google Scholar
Stickney, J. 2009a. “Wittgenstein’s contextualist approach to judging ‘sound’ teaching: escaping enthrallment in criteria-based assessments,” Educational Theory 59(2):197295.Google Scholar
Stickney, J. 2009b. “Casting teachers into education reforms and regimes of inspection: resistance to normalization through self-governance,” in Peters, M. A. et al. (eds.), Governmentality Studies in Education. Sense, 235–56.Google Scholar
Stickney, J. 2012. “Judging teachers: Foucault, governance and agency during education reforms,” Educational Philosophy and Theory 44:649–62.Google Scholar
Stine, G. 1976. “Skepticism, relevant alternatives, and deductive closure,” Philosophical Studies 29:249–61.Google Scholar
Stocker, M. 1976. “The schizophrenia of modern ethical theories,” Journal of Philosophy 73(14):453–66.Google Scholar
Stoecker, R. 1993. Reflecting Davidson: Donald Davidson Responding to an International Forum of Philosophers. Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Stone, A. 2007. An Introduction to Feminist Philosophy. Polity Press.Google Scholar
Stone, L. 1999. “Reconstructing Dewey’s critical philosophy: toward a literary pragmatist criticism,” in Popkewitz, T. S. and Fendler, L. (eds.), Critical Theories in Education: Changing Terrains of Knowledge and Politics. Routledge, 209–28.Google Scholar
Stone, L. 2008. “Speculation on a missing link: Dewey’s democracy and schools,” Journal of Educational Controversy 3(1):article 3. http://cedar.wwu.edu/jec/vol3/iss1/3.Google Scholar
Stout, R. 1996. Things that Happen because They Should. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stout, R. 1997. “Processes,” Philosophy 72:1927.Google Scholar
Stoutland, F. 1998. “Intentionalists and Davidson on rational explanation,” in Meggle, 1998: 191–208.Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo. 1953. Natural Right and History. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo. 1964. The City and Man. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo. 1983. “Philosophy as rigorous science and political philosophy,” in Pangle, Thomas L. (ed.), Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy. University of Chicago Press, 2937.Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo. 1988a [1959]. “On classical political philosophy,” in What Is Political Philosophy? and Other Studies. University of Chicago Press, 7894.Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo. 1988b [1959]. “Political philosophy and history,” in What Is Political Philosophy? and Other Studies. University of Chicago Press, 5677.Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo. 1989a. “An epilogue,” in An Introduction to Political Philosophy: Ten Essays by Leo Strauss. Ed. Gildin, Hilail. Wayne State University Press, 125–55.Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo. 1989b. “Introduction to History of Political Philosophy,” in An Introduction to Political Philosophy. Ed. Gildin, Hilail. Wayne State University Press, 159–66.Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo. 1989c. “Progress or return? The contemporary crisis of civilization,” in An Introduction to Political Philosophy. Ed. Gildin, Hilail. Wayne State University Press, 249310.Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo. 1989d. “The three waves of modernity,” in An Introduction to Political Philosophy. Ed. Gildin, Hilail. Wayne State University Press, 8198.Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo. 1989e. “Relativism,” in Pangle, Thomas L. (ed.), The Rebirth of Classical Political Rationalism: An Introduction to the Thought of Leo Strauss. University of Chicago Press, 1326.Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo. 1989f. “What is liberal education?” in An Introduction to Political Philosophy. Ed. Gildin, Hilail. Wayne State University Press, 311–19.Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo. 1989g. “What is political philosophy?” in An Introduction to Political Philosophy. Ed. Gildin, Hilail. Wayne State University Press, 357.Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo. 2000 [1961]. On Tyranny, revised and expanded edition. Ed. Gourevitch, Victor and Roth, Michael S.. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. 1994. Mental Reality. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. 2008. Real Materialism and Other Essays. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. 1949. “Truth,” Analysis 9:8397.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. 1950. “On referring,” Mind 59(235):320–44.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. 1962. “Freedom and resentment,” Proceedings of the British Academy 48:125.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. 1966. The Bounds of Sense. Methuen.Google Scholar
Strevens, M. 2003. “Against Lewis’ new theory of causation: a story with three morals,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 84:398412.Google Scholar
Stroll, A. 2001. Twentieth Century Analytic Philosophy. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Stromberg, R. N. 1990. European Intellectual History since 1789. Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Strong, E. W. 1987. “The founding of the Journal of the History of Philosophy,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 25(1):179–83.Google Scholar
Stroud, B. 1984. The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Stroud, B. 2004. “The charm of naturalism,” in De Caro, and Macarthur, 2004: 21–35.Google Scholar
Stump, E. 1993. Reasoned Faith. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Stump, E. 2010. Wandering in Darkness: Narrative and the Problem of Suffering. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stump, E. and Flint, T. P.. 1993. Hermes and Athena: Biblical Exegesis and Philosophical Theology. University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Styron, W. 1979. Sophie’s Choice. Random House.Google Scholar
Sullivan, R. J. 1989. Immanuel Kant’s Moral Theory. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Suppe, F. 1977. The Structure of Scientific Theories. University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Suppe, F. 1989. The Semantic Conception of Theories and Scientific Realism. University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Surprenant, C. 2014. Kant and the Cultivation of Virtue. Routledge.Google Scholar
Swanton, C. 2003. Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic View. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Swanton, C. 2015. The Virtue Ethics of Hume and Nietzsche. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1968. Space and Time. St. Martin’s Press.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1970. The Concept of Miracle. Macmillan.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1971. “The paradoxes of confirmation – a survey,” American Philosophical Quarterly 8(4):318–30.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1973. An Introduction to Confirmation Theory. Methuen.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1974. The Justification of Induction. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1977. The Coherence of Theism. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1979. The Existence of God. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1981. Faith and Reason. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1989. Responsibility and Atonement. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1991. Revelation. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1994. The Christian God. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1998. Providence and the Problem of Evil. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 2013. Mind, Brain, and Free Will. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tahko, T. E. 2013. “Truth-grounding and transitivity,” Thought 2(4):332–40.Google Scholar
Tahko, T. E. 2014. “Boring infinite descent,” Metaphilosophy 45(2):257–69.Google Scholar
Talisse, R. 2007. A Pragmatist Philosophy of Democracy. Routledge.Google Scholar
Tanizaki, Junichirō. 1977. In Praise of Shadows. Trans. Harper, T. J. and Seidensticker, E. G.. Leete’s Island Books.Google Scholar
Tannenbaum, J. 2002. “Acting with feeling from duty,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 5:321–37.Google Scholar
Tanney, J. 2009. “Reasons as non-causal, context-placing explanations,” in Sandis, C. (ed.), New Essays on the Explanation of Action. Palgrave Macmillan, 94111.Google Scholar
Tarski, A. 1935. “Der Wahrheitsbegriff in den formalisierton Sprachen,” Studia Philosophica 1:261405. Trans. as “The concept of truth in formalized languages,” in Woodger 1956: 152–278.Google Scholar
Tarski, A. 1936. “Uber den Begriff der logischen Folgerung,” Actes du Congrès International de Philosophie Scientifique 7 (Actualités scientifiques et industrielles 394), Paris, 111. Trans. as “On the concept of logical consequence,” in Woodger 1956: 409–20.Google Scholar
Tarski, A. 1958. “Remarks on predicate logic with infinitely long expressions,” Colloquium Mathematicum 16:171–6.Google Scholar
Tatzel, A. 2002. “Bolzano’s theory of ground and consequence,” Notre Dame Journal of Symbolic Logic 43(1):125.Google Scholar
Tavinor, G. 2009. The Art of Videogames. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. 1980. “Understanding in human science,” Review of Metaphysics 34(1):2538.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. 1984. “Philosophy and its history,” in Rorty, , Schneewind, , and Skinner, 1984: 17–30.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. 1985a. Philosophical Papers, vol. 2. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. 1985b. “What is human agency?” in Human Agency and Language: Philosophical Papers, vol. 1. Cambridge University Press, 1544.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. 1986. “Foucault on freedom and truth,” in Hoy, D. C. (ed.), Foucault: A Critical Reader. Blackwell, 69103.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. 1991. The Ethics of Authenticity. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. 1995. Philosophical Arguments. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. 2004. Modern Social Imaginaries. Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, P. 1986. Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, P. C. 2016. Black Is Beautiful: A Philosophy of Black Aesthetics. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Taylor, Richard. 1966. Action and Purpose. Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Taylor, Robert S. 2011. Reconstructing Rawls: The Kantian Foundations of Justice as Fairness. Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
Teichmann, R. 2008. The Philosophy of Elizabeth Anscombe. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tenenbaum, S. (ed.). 2010. Desire, Practical Reason, and the Good. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Thayer-Bacon, B. J. 2006. “Shared authority in democratic classrooms,” in Cooper, K. and White, R. (eds.), The Practical Critical Educator: Critical Inquiry and Educational Practice. Springer, 95109.Google Scholar
Thom, P. 1993. For an Audience: A Philosophy of the Performing Arts. Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Thomasson, A. L. 2000. “After Brentano: a one-level theory of consciousness,” European Journal of Philosophy 8:190209.Google Scholar
Thomasson, A. L. 2005. “First-person knowledge in phenomenology,” in Smith, and Thomasson, 2005: 115–39.Google Scholar
Thomasson, A. L. 2007. Ordinary Objects. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Thomasson, A. L. 2008. “Phenomenal consciousness and the phenomenal world,” The Monist 91(2):191214.Google Scholar
Thompson, B. 2009. “Senses for senses,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 87:99117.Google Scholar
Thompson, E. 2015. Waking, Dreaming, Being: Self and Consciousness in Neuroscience, Meditation, and Philosophy. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Thompson, M. 2008. Life and Action: Elementary Structures of Practice and Practical Thought. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Thomson, I. 2000. “From the question concerning technology to the quest for a democratic technology: Heidegger, Marcuse, Feenberg,” Inquiry 43(2):203–16.Google Scholar
Thomson, I. 2002. “Heidegger on ontological education, or how we become what we are,” in Peters, M. A. (ed.), Heidegger, Education, and Modernity. Rowman & Littlefield, 123–50.Google Scholar
Thomson, I. 2003. “Interpretation as self-creation: Nietzsche on the pre-Platonics,” Ancient Philosophy 23(1):195213.Google Scholar
Thomson, I. 2004a. “Heidegger’s perfectionist philosophy of education in Being and Time,” Continental Philosophy Review 37(4):439–67.Google Scholar
Thomson, I. 2004b. “Ontology and ethics at the intersection of phenomenology and environmental philosophy,” Inquiry 47(4):380412.Google Scholar
Thomson, I. 2005. Heidegger on Ontotheology: Technology and the Politics of Education. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Thomson, I. 2009a. “Rethinking Levinas on Heidegger on death,” Harvard Review of Philosophy 16:2343.Google Scholar
Thomson, I. 2009b. “Phenomenology and technology,” in Pedersen, S. A., Berg Olsen, J.-K., and Hendricks, V. F. (eds.), A Companion to Philosophy of Technology. Blackwell, 195201.Google Scholar
Thomson, I. 2011. Heidegger, Art, and Postmodernity. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Thomson, I. 2012. “In the future philosophy will be neither continental nor analytic but synthetic: toward a promiscuous miscegenation of (all) philosophical traditions and styles,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 50(2):191205.Google Scholar
Thomson, I. 2013. “Death and demise in Being and Time,” in Wrathall, M. A. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger’s Being and Time. Cambridge University Press, 260–90.Google Scholar
Thomson, I. 2015. “The failure of philosophy: why didn’t Being and Time answer the question of being?” in Braver, L. (ed.), Division III of Heidegger’s Being and Time: The Unanswered Question of Being. The MIT Press, 285310.Google Scholar
Thomson, I. 2017. “Heidegger’s Nazism in the light of his early Black Notebooks: a view from America,” in Denker, A. and Zaborowski, H. (eds.), Zur Hermeneutik der “Schwarzen Hefte”: Heidegger Jahrbuch 11. Karl Alber, 184209.Google Scholar
Thomson, I. forthcoming. “The nothing [das Nichts],” in Wrathall, M. (ed.), The Heidegger Lexicon. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Thomson, J. J. 1990. The Realm of Rights. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Thomson, J. J. 2003. “Causation: omissions,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66(1):81103.Google Scholar
Thrasher, J. and Vallier, K.. 2015. “The fragility of consensus: public reason, diversity and stability,” European Journal of Philosophy 23(4):933–54.Google Scholar
Tilghman, B. R. 1984. But Is It Art? Blackwell.Google Scholar
Tilghman, B. R. 1991. Wittgenstein, Ethics and Aesthetics: The View from Eternity. Macmillan.Google Scholar
Tillemans, T. J. F. 2013. “How do Mādhyamikas think?Philosophy East and West 63(3):417–25.Google Scholar
Timmermann, J. 2007. Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: A Commentary. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Timmons, M. (ed.). 2002. Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretative Essays. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Todd, C. 2011. The Philosophy of Wine: A Case of Truth, Beauty, and Intoxication. Routledge.Google Scholar
Todd, S. 2009. Toward an Imperfect Education: Facing Humanity, Rethinking Cosmopolitanism. Paradigm.Google Scholar
Tola, F. and Dragonetti, C.. 2004. Being as Consciousness: Yogācāra Philosophy of Buddhism. Motilal Banarsidass.Google Scholar
Tomasi, J. 2012. Free Market Fairness. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Tooby, J. and Cosmides, L.. 1990. “The past explains the present: emotional adaptations and the structure of ancestral environments,” Ethology and Sociobiology 11(4–5):375424.Google Scholar
Tooley, D. M. 1977. “The nature of laws,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7:667–98.Google Scholar
Tormey, A. 1971. The Concept of Expression. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Trakakis, N. 2007. William Rowe on Philosophy of Religion: Selected Works. Ashgate.Google Scholar
Trampota, A., Sensen, O., and Timmermann, J. (eds.). 2013. Kant’s “Tugendlehre”: A Commentary. Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Trianosky, G. 1990. “What is virtue ethics all about?American Philosophical Quarterly 27:335–44.Google Scholar
Trifonas, P. 2000. The Ethics of Writing: Derrida, Deconstruction and Pedagogy. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Trifonas, P. and Peters, M. (eds.). 2004. Derrida, Deconstruction and Education: Ethics of Pedagogy and Research. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Trogdon, K. 2013a. “Grounding: necessary or contingent?Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 94:465–85.Google Scholar
Trogdon, K. 2013b. “An introduction to grounding,” in Hoeltje, M., Schnieder, B., and Steinberg, A. (eds.), Varieties of Dependence: Ontological Dependence, Grounding, Supervenience, Response-Dependence. Philosophia Verlag, 97122.Google Scholar
Tuana, N. 2011. “Approaches to feminism,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Zalta, E. N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/feminism-approaches/.Google Scholar
Tucker, A. (ed.). 2009. A Companion to the Philosophy of History and Historiography. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Tuomela, R. 2007. The Philosophy of Sociality: The Shared Point of View. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Turing, A. M. 1950. “Computing machinery and intelligence,” Mind 59:433–60.Google Scholar
Turri, J. 2011. “Manifest failure: the Gettier problem solved,” Philosophers’ Imprint 11(8):111.Google Scholar
Tye, M. 1992. “Visual qualia and visual content,” in Crane, T. (ed.), The Contents of Experience. Cambridge University Press, 158–76.Google Scholar
Tye, M. 1995. Ten Problems of Consciousness. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Tye, M. 2002. “Representationalism and the transparency of experience,” Noûs 36:137–51.Google Scholar
Shizuteru, Ueda. 1965. Die Gottesgeburt in der Seele und der Durchbruch zu Gott. Die mystische Anthropologie Meister Eckharts und ihre Konfrontation mit der Mystik des Zen Buddhismus. Gütersloher Verlagshaus Gerd Mohn.Google Scholar
Shizuteru, Ueda. 1983a. “Ascent and descent: Zen Buddhism in comparison with Meister Eckhart (Part 1).” Trans. James W. Heisig. Eastern Buddhist 16(1):5273.Google Scholar
Shizuteru, Ueda. 1983b. “Ascent and descent: Zen Buddhism in comparison with Meister Eckhart (Part 2).” Trans. I. Astly and J. W. Heisig. Eastern Buddhist 16(2):7291.Google Scholar
Shizuteru, Ueda. 1990. “Freedom and language in Meister Eckhart and Zen Buddhism (Part One).” Trans. R. F. Szippl. Eastern Buddhist 23(2):1859.Google Scholar
Shizuteru, Ueda. 1991. “Freedom and language in Meister Eckhart and Zen Buddhism (Part Two).” Trans. R. F. Szippl. Eastern Buddhist 24(1):5280.Google Scholar
Vaidya, A. J. 2013. “Nyāya perceptual theory: disjunctivism or anti-individualism?Philosophy East and West 63(4):562–85.Google Scholar
Vallier, K. 2011. “Against public reason liberalism’s accessibility requirement,” Journal of Moral Philosophy 8:366–89.Google Scholar
Vallor, S. 2016. Technology and the Virtues: A Philosophical Guide to a Future Worth Wanting. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Valore, P. 2016. “Naturalism as a background metaphysics,” in Calemi, F. (ed.), Metaphysics and Scientific Realism: Essays in Honour of David Armstrong. Walter de Gruyter, 253–60.Google Scholar
Van Brakel, J. 2000. Philosophy of Chemistry: Between the Manifest and the Scientific Image. Leuven University Press.Google Scholar
Van Buren, J. 1995. “The ethics of Formale Anzeige in Heidegger,” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 62(2):157–70.Google Scholar
Vandenberg, D. 1971. Being and Education. Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C. 1970. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Time and Space. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C. 1980. The Scientific Image. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C. 1989. Laws and Symmetry. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C. 2008. Scientific Represenetation: Paradoxes of Perspective. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
van Gelder, T. J. 1995. “What might cognition be, if not computation?Journal of Philosophy 92:345–81.Google Scholar
van Gelder, T. J. 1998. “The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21:615–28, 654–66.Google Scholar
Van Heijenoort, J. (ed.). 1967. From Frege to Gödel. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Van Norden, B. 2003. “Mengzi and virtue ethics,” Journal of Ecumenical Studies 40(1–2):120–36.Google Scholar
Van Norden, B. 2007. Virtue Ethics and Consequentialism in Early Chinese Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Van Norden, B. 2017. Taking Back Philosophy: A Multicultural Manifesto. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
van Plato, J. 2014. “The development of proof theory,” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Zalta, E. N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/proof-theory-development/.Google Scholar
Van Schoelandt, C. and Gaus, G.. 2018. “Constructing distributive justice,” in Knoll, M., Snyder, S., and Simsek, N. (eds.), New Perspectives on Distributive Justice: Deep Disagreements, Pluralism, and the Problem of Consensus. Walter de Gruyter, 403–21.Google Scholar
Vann, R. T. 1995. “Turning linguistic: history and theory and History and Theory, 1960–1975,” in Ankersmit, and Kellner, 1995: 40–69.Google Scholar
Varga, S. 2011. Authenticity as an Ethical Ideal. Routledge.Google Scholar
Vattimo, G. 1988. The End of Modernity: Nihilism and Hermeneutics in Postmodern Culture. Trans. Snyder, J. R.. Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Vattimo, G. 1997. Beyond Interpretation: The Meaning of Hermeneutics for Philosophy. Trans. Webb, D.. Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Vattimo, G. 2002. After Christianity. Trans. D’Isanto, L.. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Vattimo, G. 2014. “What need, what metaphysics?Parrhesia 21:53–7.Google Scholar
Vaught, R. 1974. “Model theory before 1945,” in Henkin, L., Addison, J., Change, C. C., Craig, W., Scott, D., and Vaught, R. (eds.), Proceedings of the Tarski Symposium. American Mathematical Society, 153–72.Google Scholar
Velleman, J. D. 1989. Practical Reflection. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Velleman, J. D. 1992. “The guise of the good,” Noûs 26(1):326.Google Scholar
Velleman, J. D. 2004. “Replies to discussion of The Possibility of Practical Reason,” Philosophical Studies 121:225–38.Google Scholar
Velleman, J. D. 2009. How We Get Along. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Verbeek, P. P. 2005. What Things Do: Philosophical Reflections on Technology, Agency, and Design. Trans. Crease, R. P.. Penn State University Press.Google Scholar
Vermazen, B. 1985. “Negative acts,” in Vermazen, and Hintikka, 1985: 93–104.Google Scholar
Vermazen, B. and Hintikka, M. B. (eds.). 1985. Essays on Davidson: Actions and Events. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Vidal, J. 2011. “Bolivia enshrines natural world’s rights with equal status for Mother Earth,” The Guardian, 10.Google Scholar
Vinueza, A. 2000. “Sensations and the language of thought,” Philosophical Psychology 13:373–92.Google Scholar
Vogel, J. 1990. “Cartesian skepticism and inference to the best explanation,” Journal of Philosophy 87:658–66.Google Scholar
Vogel, J. 2004. “Skeptical arguments,” Philosophical Issues 14:426–55.Google Scholar
Vogel, S. 2002. “Environmental philosophy after the end of nature,” Environmental Ethics 24(1):2339.Google Scholar
Vogel, S. 2015. Thinking Like a Mall: Environmental Philosophy after the End of Nature. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
von Wright, G. H. 1963 Norm and Action. Routledge.Google Scholar
von Wright, G. H. 1971. Understanding and Explanation. Routledge.Google Scholar
Wagner, P. (ed.). 2012. Carnap’s Ideal of Explication and Naturalism. Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Wain, K. 2007. “Foucault: the ethics of self-creation and the future of education,” in Peters, M. A. and Besley, T. (eds.), Why Foucault? Peter Lang, 205–26.Google Scholar
Wainwright, W. J. 1995. Reason and the Heart: A Prolegomenon to a Critique of Passional Reason. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Waithe, M. E. (ed.). 1995. A History of Women Philosophers, 4 vols. Kluwer.Google Scholar
Waks, L. 2008. Leaders in Philosophy of Education: Intellectual Self-Portraits. Sense.Google Scholar
Wall, J. 2005. Moral Creativity: Paul Ricoeur and the Poetics of Possibility. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wall, S. 2002. “Is public justification self-defeating?American Philosophical Quarterly 39:385–93.Google Scholar
Wallace, J. 1978. Virtues and Vices. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Walsh, P. 2016. “Husserl’s concept of motivation: the Logical Investigations and beyond,” in Meixner, U. and Newen, A. (eds.), Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy/Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse. Mentis, 7083.Google Scholar
Walsh, W. H. 1951. An Introduction to the Philosophy of History. HutchinsonGoogle Scholar
Walton, K. L. 1970. “Categories of art,” Philosophical Review 79:334–67.Google Scholar
Walton, K. L. 1978. “Fearing fictions,” Journal of Philosophy 75:527.Google Scholar
Walton, K. L. 1990. Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wanderer, J. and Levine, S.. 2013. “Review of The Pittsburgh School of Philosophy by Chauncey Maher,” Notre Dame Philosophical Review. https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/the-pittsburgh-school-of-philosophy-sellars-mcdowell-brandom/.Google Scholar
Warfield, T. 1999. “Against representational theories of consciousness,” Journal of Consciousness Studies 6:66–9.Google Scholar
Warnke, G. 1987. Gadamer: Hermeneutics, Tradition and Reason. Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Warnke, G. 2015. “Hermeneutics and feminism,” in Malpas, J. and Gander, H.-H. (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Hermeneutics. Routledge, 644–59.Google Scholar
Warren, K. J. 2000. Ecofeminist Philosophy: A Western Perspective on What It Is and Why It Matters. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Wartenberg, T. 2006. Thinking through Cinema: Film as Philosophy. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wartenberg, T. 2007. “Can philosophy be screened?” in Thinking on Screen: Film as Philosophy. Routledge, 114.Google Scholar
Wartenberg, T. 2015. “Philosophy of film,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Zalta, E. N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries.Google Scholar
Watson, A. 2010. “Bhaṭṭa Rāmakantha’s elaboration of self-awareness (svasāṃvedana) and how it differs from Dharmakīrti’s exposition of the concept,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 38(3):297321.Google Scholar
Watson, G. (ed.). 1982. Free Will. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Watson, G. 1997. “On the primacy of character,” in Statman, D. (ed.), Virtue Ethics. Edinburgh University Press, 5681. Reprinted in O. Flanagan and A. Rorty (eds.), Identity, Character, and Morality. The MIT Press, 1990, 449–69.Google Scholar
Watson, R. A. 2002. “What is the history of philosophy and why is it important?Journal of the History of Philosophy 40(4):525–8.Google Scholar
Watson, R. A. 2012. “The Journal of the History of Philosophy: what it all means,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 25(1):15.Google Scholar
Tetsurō, Watsuji. 1988. Climate and Culture: A Philosophical Study. Trans. Bownas, G.. Greenwood Press.Google Scholar
Tetsurō, Watsuji. 1996. Watsuji Tetsurō’s Rinrigaku: Ethics in Japan. Trans. Seisaku, Yamamoto and Carter, Robert. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Webber, J. 2018. Rethinking Existentialism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weber, M. 1958. From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology. Ed and trans. Gerth, H. and Wright Mills, C.. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weber, M. 2001 [1905]. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. Trans. Parsons, T.. Routledge.Google Scholar
Weeks, K. 2011. The Problem with Work: Feminism, Marxism, Antiwork Politics, and Postwork Imaginaries. Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Weigelin-Schwiedrzik, S. 2011. “Chinese historical writing since 1949,” in Schneider, and Woolf, 2011: 615–36.Google Scholar
Weinberg, J. M., Nichols, S., and Stich, S.. 2001. “Normativity and epistemic intuitions,” Philosophical Topics 29:429–60.Google Scholar
Weithman, P. 2010. Why Political Liberalism? On John Rawls’s Political Turn. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weithman, P. 2016. “Stability and the original position,” in Hinton, T. (ed.), The Original Position. Cambridge University Press, 224–46.Google Scholar
Wells, H. G. 1946. Mind at the End of Its Tether. Millet Books.Google Scholar
Wenar, L. 1995. “Political liberalism: an internal critique,” Ethics 102:3262.Google Scholar
Wendt, F. 2016. “The moral standing of modus vivendi agreements,” Public Affairs Quarterly 30:351–70.Google Scholar
Weslake, B. forthcoming. “A partial theory of actual causation,” British Journal for Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
Westerhoff, J. C. 2006. “Nāgārjuna’s catuṣkoṭi,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 34:367–95.Google Scholar
Wheeler, Michael W. 2005. Reconstructing the Cognitive World: The Next Step. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
White, H. 1973. Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth Century Europe. Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
White, L. Jr. 1967. “The historical roots of our ecological crisis,” Science 155:1,203–7.Google Scholar
White, M. 1959. “A plea for an analytic philosophy of history,” in Religion, Politics and the Higher Learning. Harvard University Press, 6174.Google Scholar
White, M. 1963. “The logic of historical narration,” in Hook, 1963: 3–31.Google Scholar
White, M. 1965. Foundations of Historical Knowledge. Harper & Row.Google Scholar
White, M. 2002. A Philosophy of Culture: The Scope of Holistic Pragmatism. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Whitehead, H. and Rendell, L.. 2014. The Cultural Lives of Whales and Dolphins. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Whitt, L., Roberts, M., Norman, W., and Grieves, V.. 2003. “Indigenous perspectives,” in Jamieson (ed.), D., A Companion to Environmental Philosophy. Blackwell, 320.Google Scholar
Whyte, K. 2017. “Indigenous climate change studies: indigenizing futures, decolonizing the Anthropocene,” English Language Notes 55:12.Google Scholar
Whyte, W. 1956. The Organizational Man. Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
Widerker, D. and McKenna, M.. 2003. Moral Responsibility and Alternative Possibilities. Ashgate.Google Scholar
Wierenga, E. 1989. The Nature of God: An Inquiry into Divine Attributes. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Wiesel, E. 1982. Night. Bantam Books.Google Scholar
Wild, J. 1955. The Challenge of Existentialism. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Wilks, Y. A. 1976. “Dreyfus’s disproofs,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 27:177–85.Google Scholar
Willett, C. 2014. Interspecies Ethics. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Willett, C. and Suchak, M.. 2018. “Sociality,” in Gruen, L. (ed.), Critical Terms in Animal Studies. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Williams, B. A. O. 1972. Morality: An Introduction to Ethics. Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Williams, B. A. O. 1973a. Problems of the Self: Philosophical Papers, 1956–1972. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, B. A. O. 1973b. “A critique of utilitarianism,” in Williams, B. and Smart, J., Utilitarianism: For and Against. Cambridge University Press, 75150.Google Scholar
Williams, B. A. O. 1978. Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry. Penguin.Google Scholar
Williams, B. A. O. 1981a. “Internal and external reasons,” in Williams 1981b: 101–13.Google Scholar
Williams, B. A. O. 1981b. Moral Luck. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, B. A. O. 1985. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, B. A. O. 1993. Shame and Necessity. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Williams, B. A. O. 1995. “Acts and omissions, doing and not doing,” in Williams, B. A. O., Making Sense of Humanity and Other Philosophical Papers 1982–1993. Cambridge University Press, 5664.Google Scholar
Williams, B. A. O. 2002. Truth and Truthfulness: An Essay in Genealogy. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, B. A. O. 2005. In the Beginning Was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, B. A. O. 2006. Philosophy as a Humanistic Discipline. Ed. Moore, A. W.. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, M. 1988. “Epistemological realism and the basis of scepticism,” Mind 97(387):415–39.Google Scholar
Williams, M. 1991. Unnatural Doubts: Epistemological Realism and the Basis of Scepticism. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Williams, M. 1999. Groundless Belief: An Essay on the Possibility of Epistemology, 2nd edition. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, P. 1992. The Alchemy of Race and Right. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, T. C. 1968. The Concept of the Categorical Imperative: A Study of the Place of the Categorical Imperative in Kant’s Ethical Theory. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2000. Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 2007. The Philosophy of Philosophy. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wilsch, T. 2015. “The nomological account of ground,” Philosophical Studies 172(12):3,293–312.Google Scholar
Wilson, A. 2018. “Metaphysical causation,” Noûs 52(4):723–51.Google Scholar
Wilson, E. E. 2015. “Self-legislation and self-command in Kant’s ethics,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 96:256–78.Google Scholar
Wilson, E. E. 2016. “Habitual desire: on Kant’s concept of inclination,” Kantian Review 21:211–35.Google Scholar
Wilson, E. O. 1978. On Human Nature. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, G. 1989. The Intentionality of Human Action. Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, G. 2011. Seeing Fictions in Film: The Epistemology of Movies. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, J. 1999. “How superduper does a physicalist supervenience need to be?Philosophical Quarterly 50(194):3352.Google Scholar
Wilson, J. 2010. “Much ado about ‘something’,” Analysis 71(1):172–88.Google Scholar
Wilson, J. 2014. “No work for a theory of grounding,” Inquiry 57(5–6):535–79.Google Scholar
Wilson, S. 1955. The Man in the Grey Flannel Suit. Da Capo Press.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, W. 1972. “Complexity and organization,” in Schaffner, K. F. and Cohen, R. S. (eds.), PSA 1972: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. Reidel, 6786.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, W. 1994. “The ontology of complex systems: levels of organization, perspectives and causal thickets,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, supplementary volume 20:207–74.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, W. K. Jr. and Beardsley, M. C.. 1946. “The intentional fallacy,” Sewanee Review 54:468–88.Google Scholar
Winch, P. 1958. The Idea of a Social Science and Its Relation to Philosophy. Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Windelband, W. 1883. “Kritische oder genetische Methode?” in Windelband, 1915: vol. 2, 99–135.Google Scholar
Windelband, W. 1915. Präludien: Aufsätze und Reden zur Philosophie und ihrer Geschichte, 5th edition. J. C. B. Mohr.Google Scholar
Winner, L. 1980. “Do artifacts have politics?Daedalus 109(1):121–36. Also adapted in Winner’s The Whale and the Reactor: A Search for Limits in an Age of High Technology. University of Chicago Press, 1986, 19–39.Google Scholar
Winsberg, E. 2009. “Computer simulation and the philosophy of science,” Philosophy Compass 4:835–45.Google Scholar
Withy, K. 2014. “Situation and limitation: making sense of Heidegger on thrownness,” European Journal of Philosophy 22(1):6181.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1961 [1922]. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Kegan Paul. Trans. Pears, D. and McGuinness, B.. Routledge.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1953. Philosophical Investigations. Trans. Anscombe, G. E. M., Hacker, P. M. S., and Schulte, J.. 2nd edition 1958; 3rd edition 2001. Revised 4th edition, ed. Hacker, and Schulte, , 2009. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1956. Remarks on the Foundation of Mathematics. Trans. Anscombe, G. E. M.. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1958. The Blue and Brown Books. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1963. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Trans. Pears, D. F. and McGuinness, B. F.. Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1965. The Blue and Brown Books (Preliminary Studies for the Philosophical Investigations). Harper Torchbooks.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1966. Lectures and Conversation on Aesthetics, Psychology, and Religious Belief. Ed. Barrett, C.. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1967. Zettel. Trans. Anscombe, G. E. M.. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1968. Philosophical Investigations, 3rd edition. Trans. Anscombe, G. E. M.. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1969. On Certainty. Ed. Anscombe, G. E. M. and von Wright, G. H., trans. Paul, D. and Anscombe, G. E. M.. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1979. Notebooks 1914–16. Trans. Anscombe, G. E. M.. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1980. Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology I. Trans. Anscombe, G. E. M.. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 2009. Philosophical Investigations, 4th edition. Trans. Anscombe, G. E. M., Hacker, P. M. S., and Schulte, J.. Oxford.Google Scholar
Wolfe, J. 2013. Heidegger’s Eschatology: Theological Horizons in Martin Heidegger’s Early Work. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wolff, R. P. 1973. The Autonomy of Reason: A Commentary on Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Wolin, R. 1993. The Heidegger Controversy: A Critical Reader. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Wolin, R. 2004. The Seduction of Unreason: The Intellectual Romance with Fascism from Nietzsche to Postmodernism. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Wollheim, R. 1968. Art and Its Objects: An Introduction to Aesthetics. Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Wollheim, R. 1987. Painting as an Art. Thames & Hudson.Google Scholar
Wolterstorff, N. 1980. Works and Worlds of Art. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Wolterstorff, N. 2015. Art Rethought: The Social Practices of Art. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wong, J. 2009. “Growing dendrites: brain-based learning, governmentality and ways of being a person,” in Peters, M. A. et al. (eds.), Governmentality Studies in Education. Sense, 36978.Google Scholar
Wood, A. 1999. Kant’s Ethical Thought. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wood, A. 2007. Kantian Ethics. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wood, T. E. 1994. Nāgārjunian Disputations: A Philosophical Journey through an Indian Looking-Glass. University of Hawai‘i Press.Google Scholar
Woodger, J. H. (trans.) 1956. Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics. Clarendon Press. 2nd edition Hackett, 1983.Google Scholar
Woodruff, P. 2008. The Necessity of Theater: The Art of Watching and Being Watched. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Woodward, J. 2003. Making Things Happen: A Theory of Causal Explanation. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Worrall, J. 1989. “Structural realism: the best of both worlds?Dialectica 43(1–2):99124.Google Scholar
Worrall, J. 2007. “Why there’s no cause to randomize,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58(3):451–88.Google Scholar
Wrathall, M. A. 2003. “Between earth and sky: Heidegger on life after the death of God,” in Wrathall, M. A. (ed.), Religion after Metaphysics. Cambridge University Press, 6987.Google Scholar
Wrathall, M. A. 2015. “Demanding authenticity of ourselves: Heidegger on authenticity as an extra-moral ideal,” in Altman, M. and Pedersen, H. (eds.), Horizons of Authenticity in Phenomenology, Existentialism, and Moral Psychology: Essay in Honor of Charles Guignon. Springer, 347–68.Google Scholar
Wrathall, M. A. 2017. “Making sense of human existence,” in Švec, O. and Čapek, J. (eds.), Pragmatic Perspectives in Phenomenology. Routledge, 227–41.Google Scholar
Wrathall, M. A. and Lambeth, M.. 2011. “Heidegger’s last God,” Inquiry 54:160–82.Google Scholar
Wright, C. 1985. “Facts and certainty,” Proceedings of the British Academy 71:429–72.Google Scholar
Wright, C. 1989. “Wittgenstein’s rule-following considerations and the central project of theoretical linguistics,” in George, 1989: 233–64.Google Scholar
Wright, C. 1992. “On Putnam’s proof that we are not brains-in-a-vat,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 92:6794.Google Scholar
Wright, C. 2000. “Cogency and question-begging: some reflections on McKinsey’s paradox and Putnam’s proof,” Philosophical Issues 10(1):140–63.Google Scholar
Wright, C. 2004. “Warrant for nothing (and foundations for free)?Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supplementary volume 78:167212.Google Scholar
Yablo, S. 2002. “De facto dependence,” Journal of Philosophy 99(3):130–48.Google Scholar
Yack, B. 2017. “Political liberalism, political not philosophical,” Perspectives on Political Science 15:146–51.Google Scholar
Yalçin, Ü. 1992. “Sceptical arguments from underdetermination,” Philosophical Studies 68:134.Google Scholar
Yoshimi, J. 2007. “Mathematizing phenomenology,” Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 6(3):271–91.Google Scholar
Yoshimi, J. 2010. “Husserl on psycho-physical laws,” New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 10:2542.Google Scholar
Young, J. O. 2001. Art and Knowledge. Routledge.Google Scholar
Young, J. O. 2007. Cultural Appropriation and the Arts. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Young, J. O. 2014. Critique of Pure Music. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Yu, K., Tao, J., and Ivanhoe, P. J. (eds.). 2010. Taking Confucian Ethics Seriously: Contemporary Theories and Applications. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Yasuo, Yuasa. 1987. The Body: Toward an Eastern Mind–Body Theory. Trans. Nagatomo, Shigenori and Kasulis, T. P.. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Yasuo, Yuasa. 1993. The Body, Self-Cultivation, and Ki-Energy. Trans. Nagatomo, Shigenori and Hull, Monte S.. SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Yusa, M. 2002. Zen and Philosophy: An Intellectual Biography of Nishida Kitarō. University of Hawai‘i Press.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, L. 1993. Rational Faith. University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, L. 1996. Virtues of the Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Zahavi, D. 2005a. “Intentionality and experience,” Synthesis Philosophia 20:299318.Google Scholar
Zahavi, D. 2005b. Subjectivity and Selfhood: Investigating the First-Person Perspective. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Zahavi, D. 2016. “Analytic and continental philosophy: from duality through plurality to (some kind of) unity,” in Rinofner-Kreidl, S. and Wiltsche, H. A. (eds.), Analytic and Continental Philosophy: Methods and Perspectives. Walter de Gruyter, 8093.Google Scholar
Zahavi, D. and Kriegel, U.. 2016. “For-me-ness: what it is and what it is not,” in Dahlstrom, D. O., Elpidorou, A., and Hopp, W. (eds.), Philosophy of Mind and Phenomenology: Conceptual and Empirical Approaches. Routledge, 3653.Google Scholar
Zangwill, N. 2001. The Metaphysics of Beauty. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Zangwill, N. 2007. Aesthetic Creation. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Zea, L. 1945. En torno a una filosofía Americana. El Colegio de México.Google Scholar
Zea, L. 1969. La filosofía Americana como filosofía sin más. Siglo XXI Editores.Google Scholar
Zhang, D. 2002 [1989]. Zhongguo gudian zhexue gainian fanzhou yaolun. Academy of Social Sciences. Trans. E. Ryden as Key Concepts in Chinese Philosophy. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Žižek, S. 1991. Looking Awry: An Introduction to Jacques Lacan through Popular Culture. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Zuckert, C. H. and Zuckert, M. P.. 2006. The Truth about Leo Strauss: Political Philosophy and American Democracy. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Zuckert, M. P. and Zuckert, C. H.. 2014. Leo Strauss and the Problem of Political Philosophy. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Edited by Kelly Becker, University of New Mexico, Iain D. Thomson, University of New Mexico
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Philosophy, 1945–2015
  • Online publication: 08 November 2019
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316779651.059
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Edited by Kelly Becker, University of New Mexico, Iain D. Thomson, University of New Mexico
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Philosophy, 1945–2015
  • Online publication: 08 November 2019
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316779651.059
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Edited by Kelly Becker, University of New Mexico, Iain D. Thomson, University of New Mexico
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Philosophy, 1945–2015
  • Online publication: 08 November 2019
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316779651.059
Available formats
×