Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-skm99 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T14:30:18.448Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 May 2016

C. Mantzavinos
Affiliation:
University of Athens, Greece
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Explanatory Pluralism , pp. 189 - 213
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2016

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abney, Drew H., Dale, Rick, Yoshimi, Jeff, Kello, Chris T., Tylén, Kristian, and Fusaroli, Ricardo (2014): “Joint Perceptual Decision-Making: A Case Study in Explanatory Pluralism”, Frontiers in Psychology, vol. 5, pp. 112.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Achinstein, Peter (1983): The Nature of Explanation, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Acierno, Louis (1994): The History of Cardiology, London and New York: The Parthenon Publishing Group.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, Marcus (2009): “Empirical Evidence and the Knowledge-that/Knowledge-how Distinction”, Synthese, vol. 170, pp. 97114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aird, W.C. (2011): “Discovery of the Cardiovascular System: From Galen to William Harvey”, Journal of Thrombosis and Haemostasis, vol. 9 (Suppl. 1), pp. 118129.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Albert, Hans (1968/1985): Treatise on Critical Reason, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Albert, Hans (1978): Traktat über Rationale Praxis, Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).Google Scholar
Albert, Hans (1982): Die Wissenschaft und die Fehlbarkeit der Vernunft, Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).Google Scholar
Albert, Hans (1987): Kritik der Reinen Erkenntnislehre, Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).Google Scholar
Alt, James (2009): “Comment: Conditional Knowledge: An Oxymoron?” in Mantzavinos, C. (ed.): Philosophy of the Social Sciences. Philosophical Theory and Scientific Practice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 146153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, John R. (2010): Cognitive Psychology and Its Implications, 7th edition, New York: Worth Publishers.Google Scholar
Arabatzis, Theodore (2006): “On the Inextricability of the Context of Discovery and the Context of Justification”, in Schickore, Jutta and Steinle, Friedrich (eds.): Revisiting Discovery and Justification, Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 215230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Axelrod, Robert (1986): “An Evolutionary Approach to Norms”, American Political Science Review, vol. 80, pp. 10951111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Celsius, Aulus Cornelius (1935): De Medicina (On Medicine), vol. 1, Loeb Classical Library edition, translated by Spencer, W.G., Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Baker, Alan (2012): “Science-Driven Mathematical Explanations”, Mind, vol. 121, pp. 243267.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bandura, Albert (1986): Social Foundations of Thought and Action: A Social Cognitive Theory, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Bargh, John A. and Chartrand, Tanya L. (1999): “The Unbearable Automaticity of Being”, American Psychologist, vol. 54, pp. 462479.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, Barry, Bloor, David, and Henry, John (1996): Scientific Knowledge. A Sociological Analysis, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Bartelborth, Thomas (2002): “Explanatory Unification”, Synthese, vol. 130, pp. 91107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartelborth, Thomas (2007): Erklären, Berlin and New York: de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartlett, Frederic (1932): Remembering, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Batterman, Robert W. (2010): “On the Explanatory Role of Mathematics in Empirical Science”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, vol. 61, pp. 125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bechtel, William (2006): Discovering Cell Mechanisms, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bechtel, William (2008): Mental Mechanisms: Philosophical Perspectives on Cognitive Neuroscience, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bechtel, William (2011): “Mechanism and Biological Explanation”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 78, pp. 533557.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bechtel, William and Abrahamsen, Adele (2005): “Explanation: A Mechanist Alternative”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, vol. 36, pp. 421441.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Becker, Gary (1976): The Economic Approach to Human Behavior, Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Becker, Gary and Posner, Richard (2009): Uncommon Sense: Economic Insights from Marriage to Terrorism, Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernholz, Peter, Streit, Manfred E. and Vaubel, Roland (1998): Political Competition, Innovation and Growth, Berlin: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bible, Old Testament.Google Scholar
Binmore, Ken and Samuelson, Larry (1994): “An Economist’s Perspective on the Evolution of Norms”, Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, vol. 150, pp. 4563.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander (2005): “Explanation and Metaphysics”, Synthese, vol. 143, pp. 89107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blaug, Marc (1997): Economic Theory in Retrospect, 5th edition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bogen, Jim and Machamer, Peter (2011): “Mechanistic Information and Causal Continuity”, in Illari, Phyllis McKay, Russo, Federica, and Williamson, Jon (eds.): Causality in the Sciences, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 845864.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boudon, Raymond (1974): Education, Opportunity and Social Inequlity, New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Boyer, Pascal (2000): “Evolution of the Modern Mind and the Origins of Culture: Religious Concepts as a Limiting-Case”, in Carruthers, Peter and Chamberlain, Andrew (eds.): Evolution and the Human Mind. Modularity, Language and Meta-Cognition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 93112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyle, Robert (1688): A Disquisition About the Final Causes of Natural Things: Wherein It is Inquired, Whether, and, (if at all) with What Cautions a Naturalist Should Admit Them? London: John Caplot.Google Scholar
Brain, Peter (1986): Galen on Bloodletting, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Braine, David (1972): “Varieties of Necessity”, Supplementary Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. 46, pp. 139170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Braithwaite, Richard B. (1953): Scientific Explanation. A Study of the Function of Theory, Probability and Law in Science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brandt, Karl (1993): Geschichte der Deutschen Volkswirtschaftslehre, vol. 2, Freiburg i. Br.: Rudolf Haufe Verlag.Google Scholar
Brennan, Geoffrey and Buchanan, James (1985): The Reason of Rules – Constitutional Political Economy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brewer, William F., Chinn, Clark A., and Samarapungavan, Ala (2000): “Explanation in Scientists and Children”, in Keil, Frank C. and Wilson, Robert A. (eds.): Explanation and Cognition, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, pp. 279298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bromberger, Sylvain (1966): “Why-Questions”, in Colodny, Robert (ed.): Mind and Cosmos, Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, pp. 86111.Google Scholar
Brown, Matthew J. (2013): “Values in Science beyond Underdetermination and Inductive Risk”, Philosophy of Science, Vol. 80, pp. 829839.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, James (1975): The Limits of Liberty. Between Anarchy and Leviathan, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, James and Tullock, Gordon (1962): The Calculus of Consent – Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy, Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Bueno, Otávio and French, Steven (2012): “Can Mathematics Explain Physical Phenomena?British Journal for Philosophy of Science, vol. 63, pp. 85113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bueter, Anke (2015): “The Irreducibility of Value-Freedom to Theory Assessment”, Studies in History and philosophy of Science, Vol. 49, pp. 1826.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Burkert, Walter (1999): “The Logic of Cosmogony”, in Buxton, Richard (ed.): From Myth to Reason? Studies in the Development of Greek Thought, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 87106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Butterfield, Herbert (1957): The Origins of Modern Science 1300–1800, rev. edition, New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Campbell, Donald T. (1965): “Variation and Selective Retention in Socio-Cultural Evolution”, in Barringer, Herbert R., Blanksten, George I., and Mack, Raymond W. (eds.): Social Change in Developing Areas, Cambridge, MA: Schenkman, pp. 1949.Google Scholar
Campbell, Donald T. (1974/1987): “Evolutionary Epistemology”, originally published in Schlipp, Paul A. (ed.): The Philosophy of Karl Popper, La Salle, IL: Open Court, pp. 413463, and reprinted in Radnitzky, Gerard and Bartley, W.W. III (eds.) (1987): Evolutionary Epistemology, Rationality and the Sociology of Knowledge, La Salle, IL: Open Court, pp. 48114.Google Scholar
Carey, Susan (1985): Conceptual Change in Childhood, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf (1932): “Überwindung der Metaphysik durch logische Analyse der Sprache”, Erkenntnis, vol. 2, pp. 219241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carrier, Martin (2013): “Values and Objectivity in Science: Value-Ladeness, Pluralism and the Epistemic Attitude”, Science & Education, vol. 22, pp. 25472568.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, Peter (2002): “The Roots of Scientific Reasoning: Infancy, Modularity and the Art of Trucking”, in Carruthers, Peter, Stich, Stephen, and Siegal, Michael (eds.): The Cognitive Basis of Science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 7395.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy (1999): The Dappled World. A Study of the Boundaries of Science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy (2007): Hunting Causes and Using Them, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Celsus, , On Medicine, Prooemium, Loeb Classical Library edition, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Cesalpino, Andrea (1571): Peripateticarum Questionum, Libri Quinque, Venice: Apud Iuntas.Google Scholar
Cesalpino, Andrea (1593): Quaestionum Medicarum, Libri II, Venice: Apud Iuntas.Google Scholar
Cesalpino, Andrea (1606): Praxis Universae Artis Medicae, Treviso: Sumptibus Robert Meietti.Google Scholar
Chang, Hasok (2012): Is Water H2O? Evidence, Realism and Pluralism, Berlin and New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, Matthew (2012): Exploring Greek Myth, Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Cohen, Neal J. and Squire, Larry R. (1980): “Preserved Learning and Retention of Pattern-Analyzing Skill in Amnesia: Dissociation of Knowing How and Knowing That”, Science, vol. 210, pp. 207210.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Coleman, James S. (1990a): Foundations of Social Theory, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Coleman, James S. (1990b): “The Emergence of Norms”, in Hechter, Michael, Opp, Karl-Dieter, and Wippler, Reinhard (eds.): Social Institutions, Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter, pp. 3559.Google Scholar
Colombo, Matteo and Hartmann, Stephan (2015): “Bayesian Cognitive Science, Unification, and Explanation”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science (Advanced Access) published September 30, 2015.Google Scholar
Colombo, Matteo, Hartmann, Stephan, and van Iersel, Robert (2015): “Models, Mechanisms, and Coherence”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, vol. 66, pp. 181212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Colombo, Realdo (1559): De Re Anatomica, Libri XV, Venice: Nicolai Beuilacquae.Google Scholar
Coppola, Edward D. (1957): “The Discovery of the Pulmonary Circulation: A New Approach”, Bulletin of the History of Medicine, vol. 21, pp. 4477.Google Scholar
Cosmides, Leda and John, Tooby (eds.) (1992): The Adapted Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cournot, Augustin (1838): Recherches sur les Principes Mathématiques de la Théorie des Richesses, Paris: Chez L. Hachette.Google Scholar
Craver, Carl (2007): Explaining the Brain. Mechanisms and the Mosaic Unity of Neuroscience, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crupi, Vincenzo and Tentori, Katya (2012): “A Second Look at the Logic of Explanatory Power (with Two Novel Representation Theorems)”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 79, pp. 365385.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Currie, Adrian Mitchell (2014): “Narratives, Mechanisms and Progress in Historical Science”, Synthese, vol. 191, pp. 11631183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
D’Andrade, Roy (1995): The Development of Cognitive Anthropology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darden, Lindley (2006): Reasoning in Biological Discoveries. Essays in Mechanisms, Interfield Relations and Anomaly Resolution, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Daston, Lorraine and Galison, Peter (2010): Objectivity, New York: Zone Books.Google Scholar
Davidson, Janet E. and Sternberg, Robert J. (eds.) (2003): The Psychology of Problem Solving, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, Martin (2015): “Knowledge (Explicit, Implicit and Tacit): Philosophical Aspects”, International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, 2nd edition, vol. 13, London: Elsevier, pp. 7490.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Regt, Henk W. (2006): “Wesley Salmon’ s Complementarity Thesis: Causalism and Unificationism Reconciled?International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 20, pp. 129147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Debru, Armelle (2008): “Anatomy”, in Hankinson, Robert J. (ed.): The Cambridge Companion to Galen, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 263282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Demeulenaere, Pierre (ed.) (2011): Analytical Sociology and Social Mechanisms, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Denzau, Arthur and North, Douglass C. (1994): “Shared Mental Models: Ideologies and Institutions”, Kyklos, vol. 47, pp. 331.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Devitt, Michael (2011): “Methodology and the Nature of Knowing How”, Journal of Philosophy, vol. 108, pp. 205218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Díez, José, Kareem, Khalifa, and Bert, Leuridan (2013): “General Theories of Explanation: Buyer Beware”, Synthese, vol. 190, pp. 379396.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donald, Merlin (1991): The Origins of the Modern Mind. Three Stages in the Evolution of Culture and Cognition, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Douglas, Heather (2013): “The Value of Cognitive Values”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 80, pp. 796806.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dowe, Philip (2000): Physical Causation, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Downes, Anthony (1957): An Economic Theory of Democracy, New York: Harper.Google Scholar
Dupré, John (1993): The Disorder of Things, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Eknoyan, Garabed and De Santo, Natale G. (1997): “Realdo Colombo (1516–1559). A Reappraisal”, American Journal of Nephrology, vol. 17, pp. 261268.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Elster, Jon (1989a): The Cement of Society. A Study of Social Order, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elster, Jon (1989b): “Social Norms and Economic Theory”, Journal of Economic Perspectives, vol. 3, pp. 99107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elster, Jon (2007): Explaining Social Behavior, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epictetus, (1916): Epicteti Dissertationes ab Arriano digestae, ed. Schenkl, Heinrich, Leipzig: B.G.Teubner.Google Scholar
Fogan, Melinda Bonnie (2015): “Collaborative Explanation and Biological Mechanism”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol. 52, pp. 6778.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fancy, Nahyan (2013): Science and Religion in Mamluk Egypt: Ibn al-Nafis, Pulmonary Transit and Bodily Resurrection, London and New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Faucher, Luc, Mallon, Ron, Nazer, Daniel, Nichols, Shaun, Ruby, Aaron, Stich, Stephen, and Weinberg, Jonathan (2002): “The Baby in the Lab-Coat: Why Child Development Is Not an Adequate Model for Understanding the Development of Science”, in Carruthers, Peter, Stich, Stephen, and Siegal, Michael (eds.): The Cognitive Basis of Science, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, pp. 335362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Faye, Jan (2012): After Postmodernism. A Naturalistic Reconstruction of the Humanities, Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Faye, Jan (2014): The Nature of Scientific Thinking. On Interpretation, Explanation and Understanding, Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ferguson, Adam (1792): Principles of Moral and Political Science, Edinburgh: W. Creech.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul (1975/2010): Against Method, 4th edition, London and New York: Verso.Google Scholar
Files, Craig (1996): “Goodman’s Rejection of Resemblance”, British Journal of Aesthetics, vol. 36, pp. 398412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fisher, George Jackson (1880): “Hieronymus Fabricius ab Acquapendente”, Annals of Anatomy and Surgery, pp. 373379.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry (1983): The Modularity of Mind, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Franklin-Hall, Laura R. (2014): “High-Level Explanation and the Interventionist’s ‘Variables Problem’”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science (Advance Access), published December 18, 2014.Google Scholar
Frede, Michael (ed.) (1985): Galen: Three Treatises on the Nature of Science, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Frede, Michael (1987): “On the Method of the So-Called Methodical School of Medicine”, in Frede, Michael (ed.): Essays in Ancient Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 261278 [originally published in Barnes, Jonathan, Brunschwig, Jacques, Burnyeat, Myles, and Schofield, Malcolm (eds.) (1982): Science and Speculation, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 123].Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob (1893/1998): Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, Hildesheim, Zürich and New York: Georg Olms Verlag.Google Scholar
Friedman, Michael (1974): “Explanation and Scientific Understanding”, Journal of Philosophy, vol. 71, pp. 519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Michael (2001): Dynamics of Reason, Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Friedman, Michael (2002): “Kant, Kuhn and the Rationality of Science”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 69, pp. 171190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Michael (2011): “Extending the Dynamics of Reason”, Erkenntnis, vol. 75, pp. 431444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Michael (2012): “Reconsidering the Dynamics of Reason: Response to Ferrari Mormann, Nordmann, and Uebel”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol. 43, pp. 4753.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fries, Jakob Friedrich (1828–1831): Neue oder anthropologische Kritik der Vernunft, vols. 1–3, 2nd edition, Heidelberg: Christian Friedrich Winter.Google Scholar
Frigg, Roman and Hunter, Matthew (eds.) (2010): Beyond Mimesis and Convention. Representation in Art and Science, Dordrecht, Heidelberg, London and New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fullbrook, Edward (ed.) (2008): Ontology and Economics: Tony Lawson and His Critiques, London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Furley, David. J. and Wilkie, J.S. (1984): Galen on Respiration and the Arteries, Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gentner, Dedre and Gentner, Donald R. (1983): “Flowing Waters or Teeming Crowds: Mental Models of Electricity”, in Gentner, Dedre and Stevens, Albert (eds.): Mental Models, Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, pp. 99129.Google Scholar
Gervais, Raoul (2014): “A Framework for Inter-Level Explanations: Outlines for a New Explanatory Pluralism”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol. 48, pp. 19.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Giere, Ronald (1996): “The Scientist as Adult”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 63, pp. 538541.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giere, Ronald (2004): “How Models are Used to Represent Reality”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 71, pp. 742752.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giere, Ronald (2006): Scientific Perspectivism, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gigerenzer, Gerd (2008): “Why Heuristics Work”, Perspectives on Psychological Science, vol. 3, pp. 2029.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gigerenzer, Gerd, Todd, Peter, and the ABC Research Group (1999): Simple Heuristics that Make Us Smart, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, Gerd, Hertwig, Ralph, and Pachur, Thorsten (eds.) (2011): Heuristics: The Foundations of Adaptive Behavior, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gijsbers, Victor (2007): “Why Unification is Neither Necessary Nor Sufficient for Explanation”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 74: pp. 481500.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glennan, Stuart (2002): “Rethinking Mechanistic Explanation”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 69, pp. 342353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glennan, Stuart (2010): “Ephemeral Mechanisms and Historical Explanation”, Erkenntnis, vol. 72, pp. 251266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glymour, Clark (2015): “Probability and the Explanatory Virtues”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, vol. 66, pp. 591604.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, Peter (2003): Theory and Reality, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, Nelson (1976): Languages of Art. An Approach to a Theory of Symbols, Indiana: Hackett Publishing Company.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gopnik, Alison (1996a): “The Scientist as Child”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 63, pp. 485514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gopnik, Alison (1996b): “Reply to Commentators”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 63, pp. 552561.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gopnik, Alison (2000): “Explanation as Orgasm and the Drive for Causal Knowledge: The Function, Evolution, and Phenomenology of the Theory Formation System”, in Keil, Frank C. and Wilson, Robert A. (eds.): Explanation and Cognition, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, pp. 299323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gopnik, Alison (2012): “Scientific Thinking in Young Children: Theoretical Advances, Empirical Research, and Policy Implications”, Science, vol. 337 (no. 6102), pp. 16231627.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gopnik, Alison and Meltzhoff, Andrew (1998): Words, Thoughts, and Theories, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gossen, Hermann Heinrich (1854): Entwicklung der Gesetze des menschlichen Verkehrs, und der daraus fließenden Regeln für menschliches Handeln, Braunschweig: Friedrich Vieweg & Sohn.Google Scholar
Grantham, Todd A. (1999): “Explanatory Pluralism in Paleobiology”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 66, pp. S223S236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grantham, Todd A. (2004): “Conceptualizing the (Dis)unity of Sciences”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 71, pp. 133155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greenberg, Gabriel (2013): “Beyond Resemblance”, Philosophical Review, vol. 122, pp. 215287.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grimm, Stephen R. (2008): “Explanatory Inquiry and the Need for Explanation”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, vol. 59, pp. 481497.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hacking, Ian (2002): Historical Ontology, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Halonen, Ilpo and Hintikka, Jaako (2005): “Toward a Theory of the Process of Explanation”, Synthese, vol. 143, pp. 561.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hankinson, Robert J. (2008): “The Man and His Work”, in Hankinson, Robert J. (ed.): The Cambridge Companion to Galen, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harbecke, Jens (2010): “Mechanistic Constitution in Neurobiological Explanations”, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 24 (3), pp. 267285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, Gilbert (1965): “The Inference to the Best Explanation”, Philosophical Review, pp. 8895.Google Scholar
Harvey, William (1628/1989): Exercitatio Anatomica de Motu Cordis et Sanguinis in Animalibus, English translation by Willis, Robert in The Works of Harvey, William, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. (1955): “Degrees of Explanation”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, vol. 6, pp. 209225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. (1967): “The Theory of Complex Phenomena”, in von Hayek, Friedrich A.: Studies in Philosophy, Politics, and Economics, London: Routledge, pp. 2242.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. (1982): Law, Legislation and Liberty, 3 volumes, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Hedström, Peter and Swedberg, Richard (eds.) (1996): Social Mechanisms. An Analytical Approach to Social Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Helmreich, G. (1907–1909): Galeni. De Usu Partium Libri XVII, Leipzig: Teubner.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. (1965): Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science, New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. and Oppenheim, Paul (1948): “Studies in the Logic of Explanation”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 15, 135175 [Reprinted in Hempel (1965)].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herfeld, Catherine (2012): The Many Faces of Rational Choice Theory, Ph.D. Dissertation, Witten/Herdecke University.Google Scholar
Herrick, James Bryan (1942): A Short History of Cardiology, Springfield, IL: Charles C. Thomas.Google Scholar
Hesiod, : Theogony, Penguin Classics, London.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hey, Spencer Phillips (2014): “Heuristics and Meta-Heuristics in Scientific Judgment”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science (Advance Access), published December 24, 2014.Google Scholar
Hieronymus Fabricius ab Acquapendendte (1603): De Venarum Ostiolis, facsimile edition, English translation by Franklin, K.J., , D.M., 1933, Springfeld, IL, and Baltimore, MD: Charles C. Thomas.Google Scholar
Holland, John H., Holyoak, Keith J., Nisbett, Richard, and Thagard, Paul (1986): Induction: Processes of Inference, Learning and Discovery, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hull, David (1988): Science as a Process, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Humphreys, Paul. (1981): “Aleatory Explanation”, Synthese, 48, pp. 225232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Humphreys, Paul (1989): The Chances of Explanation, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hutchins, Edwin and Brian, Hazlehurst (1992): “Learning in the Culture Process”, in Langdon, Christopher G., Taylor, Charles, Doyne Farmer, J., and Steen, Rasmussen (eds.): Artificial Life II, Redwood City, CA: Addison-Wesley, pp. 689706.Google Scholar
Iskandar, A.Z. (ed.) (1988): Galeni De Optimo Medico Cognoscendo, Corpus Medicorum Graecorum, Suppl. Or. IV [Arabic], Berlin: Berlin-Bradenburgische Akademie der Wissenschaften.Google Scholar
Jackson, Frank and Pettit, Philip (1992): “In Defense of Explanatory Ecumenism”, Economics and Philosophy, vol. 8, pp. 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jaffé, William (ed.) (1965): Correspondence of Léon Walras and Related Papers, vol. II, Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Jansson, Lina (2014): “Causal Theories of Explanation and the Challenge of Explanatory Disagreement”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 81, pp. 332348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jevons, William Stanley (1871): The Theory of Political Economy, London and New York: MacMillan & Co.Google Scholar
Johnson-Laird, Philip N. (1983): Mental Models, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Johnson-Laird, Philip N. (2006): How We Reason, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jones, Eric L. (2003): The European Miracle, 3rd edition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keil, Frank C. and Wilson, Robert A. (2000): “Explaining Explanation”, in Keil, Frank C. and Wilson, Robert A. (eds.): Explanation and Cognition, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, pp. 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kellert, Stephen H., Longino, Helen E., and Kenneth Waters, C. (2006): “Introduction: The Pluralist Stance”, in Kellert, Stephen H., Longino, Helen E., and Kenneth Waters, C. (eds.): Scientific Pluralism, Minneapolis and London: University of Minnesota Press, pp. viixxix.Google Scholar
Keuth, Herbert (1993): Erkenntnis oder Entscheidung. Zur Kritik der kritischen Theorie, J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).Google Scholar
Key, Jack D., Keys, Thomas E., and Callahan, John A. (1979): “Historical Development of Concept of Blood Circulation”, The American Journal of Cardiology, vol. 43, pp. 10261032.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Khalifa, Kareem (2012): “Inaugurating Understanding or Repackaging Explanation?Philosophy of Science, vol. 79, pp. 1537.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Khan, Ijaz A., Daya, Samantapudi K., and Gowda, Ramesh M. (2005): “Evolution of the Theory of Circulation”, International Journal of Cardiology, vol. 98, pp. 519521.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kitcher, Philip (1981): “Explanatory Unification”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 48, pp. 251281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (1985): “Two Approaches to Explanation”, Journal of Philosophy, vol. 82, pp. 632639.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (1989): “Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the World”, in Kitcher, Philip and Salmon, Wesley (eds.): Scientific Explanation, volume 13 of Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 410505.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (1993): The Advancement of Science, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (2001): Science, Truth, and Democracy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (2011a): The Ethical Project, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (2011b): Science in a Democratic Society, New York: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip and Varzi, Achille (2000): “Some Pictures Are Worth 2N0 Sentences”, Philosophy, vol. 75, pp. 377381.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knight, Jack (2009): “Causal Mechanisms and Generalizations”, in Mantzavinos, C. (ed.): Philosophy of the Social Sciences. Philosophical Theory and Scientific Practice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 179184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koertge, Noretta (1992): “Explanation and Its Problems”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, vol. 43, pp. 8598.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koethe, John (2002): “Stanley and Williamson on Knowing How”, The Journal of Philosophy, vol. 99, pp. 325328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kühn, Carl Gottlob (ed.) (1821–1833): Claudii Galeni Opera Omnia, Leipzig: C. Cnobloch, rpt. Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 19641965.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas (1962/1970): The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, second enlarged edition, Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas (1977): “Objectivity, Value Judgment, and Theory Choice”, in Kuhn, Thomas: The Essential Tension, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, pp. 320339.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kybourg, Henry E. (1965): “Comment”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 32, 147151.Google Scholar
Lange, Marc (2013): “What Makes a Scientific Explanation Distinctively Mathematical?”, British Journal for Philosophy of Science, vol. 64, pp. 485511.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lange, Marc (2014): “Aspects of Mathematical Explanation: Symmetry, Unity, and Salience”, Philosophical Review, vol. 123, pp. 485531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Larkin, Jill H. and Simon, Herbert (1987): “Why a Diagram is (Sometimes) Worth Ten Thousand Words”, Cognitive Science, vol. 11, pp. 6599.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, Larry (1977): Progress and Its Problems. Towards a Theory of Scientific Growth, Berkeley, Los Angeles and London: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, Larry (1984): Science and Values, Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, Larry (2004): “The Epistemic, the Cognitive, and the Social”, in: Peter, Machamer and Gereon, Wolters (eds.): Science, Values, and Objectivity, Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, pp. 1423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lawson, Tony (1997): Economics and Reality, London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lawson, Tony (2003): Reorienting Economics, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lewis, David (1986): “Causal Explanation”, Philosophical Papers, vol. 2, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 214240.Google Scholar
Lipton, Peter (2004): Inference to the Best Explanation, 2nd edition, London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Little, Daniel (2009): “The Heterogeneous Social: New Thinking About the Foundations of the Social Sciences”, in Mantzavinos, C. (ed.): Philosophy of the Social Sciences. Philosophical Theory and Scientific Practice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 154178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, G.E.R. (2008): “Galen and His Contemporaries”, in Hankinson, Robert J. (ed.): The Cambridge Companion to Galen, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 3448.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen (1990): Science as Social Knowledge, Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen (2002): The Fate of Knowledge, Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen (2013): Studying Human Behavior: How Scientists Investigate Aggression and Sexuality, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lorenz, Konrad (1941): “Kants Lehre vom Apriorischen im Lichte gegenwärtiger Biologie”, Blätter für deutsche Philosophie, vol. 15 (1), pp. 95124.Google Scholar
Lorenz, Konrad (1943): “Die angeborenen Formen möglicher Erfahrung”, Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie, vol. 5, pp. 235409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lorenz, Konrad (1965): Evolution and Modification of Behavior, Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Lorenz, Konrad (1973): Die Rückseite des Spiegels. Versuch einer Naturgeschichte menschlicher Erkennens, München and Zürich: Pieper.Google Scholar
Love, Alan C. (2015): “Collaborative Explanation, Explanatory Roles, and Scientific Explaining in Practice”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol. 52, pp. 8894.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lütge, Christoph (2001): Ökonomische Wissenschaftstheorie, Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.Google Scholar
Lütge, Christoph (2004): “Economics in Philosophy of Science: A Dismal Contribution?Synthese, vol. 140 (3), pp. 279305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machamer, Peter (2009): “Explaining Mechanisms”, unpublished paper.Google Scholar
Machamer, Peter, Darden, Lindley, and Craver, Carl (2000): “Thinking about Mechanisms”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 67, pp. 125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mäki, Uskali (2001): “Explanatory Unification: Double and Doubtful”, Philosophy of the Social Sciences, vol. 31, pp. 488506.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mäki, Uskali (2002): “Symposium on Explanations and Social Ontology 2: Explanatory Ecumenism and Economics Imperialism”, Economics and Philosophy, vol. 18, pp. 235257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mäki, Uskali and Marchionni, Caterina (2009): “On the Structure of Explanatory Unification: The Case of Geographical Economics”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol. 40, pp. 185195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malpighi, Marcello (1661/1929): De Pulmonibus epistolae II ad Borellium, translated into English by Young, James: Malpighi’s “De Pulmonibus”, in Proceedings of the Royal Society of Medicine, vol. 23, pp. 111.Google Scholar
Malthus, Thomas Robert (1814): Observations on the Effects of Corn Laws on the Agriculture and General Wealth of the Country, London: J. Johnson & Co.Google Scholar
Mantzavinos, C. (1994): Wettbewerbstheorie. Eine kritische Auseinandersetzung, Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.Google Scholar
Mantzavinos, C. (1999): “Carl Menger und die Wettbewerbstheorie”, Jahrbücher für Nationalökonomie und Statistik, vol. 219, pp. 685691.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mantzavinos, C. (2001): Individuals, Institutions and Markets, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mantzavinos, C. (2005): Naturalistic Hermeneutics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mantzavinos, C. (2007): “Interpreting the Rules of the Game”, in Engel, Christoph and Strack, Fritz (eds.): The Impact of Court Procedure on the Psychology of Judicial Decision Making, Baden-Baden: Nomos, pp. 1330.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mantzavinos, C. (ed.) (2009): Philosophy of the Social Sciences. Philosophical Theory and Scientific Practice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mantzavinos, C., Douglass, North, and Shariq, Syed (2004): “Learning, Institutions and Economic Performance”, Perspectives on Politics, vol. 2, pp. 7584.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marchionni, Caterina (2008): “Explanatory Pluralism and Complementarity. From Autonomy to Integration”, Philosophy of the Social Sciences, vol. 38, pp. 314333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marshall, Alfred (1890/1920): Principles of Economics, 8th edition, London: MacMillan.Google Scholar
Mattern, Susan P. (2008): Galen and the Rhetoric of Healing, Baltimore: The John Hopkins University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayer, Richard E. (1992): Thinking, Problem Solving, Cognition, 2nd edition, New York: W.H. Freeman.Google Scholar
McAdams, Richard (1997): “The Origin, Development, and Regulation of Norms”, Michigan Law Review, vol. 96, pp. 338433.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCauley, Robert (2000): “The Naturalness of Religion and the Unnaturalness of Science”, in Keil, Frank C. and Wilson, Robert A. (eds.): Explanation and Cognition, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, pp. 6185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCauley, Robert (2009): “Time is of the Essence: Explanatory Pluralism and Accommodating Theories About Long Term Processes”, Philosophical Psychology, vol. 22, pp. 611635.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCauley, Robert (2013): “Explanatory Pluralism and the Cognitive Science of Religion: Or Why Scholars in Religious Studies Should Stop Worrying About Reductive Elimination of the Religious and Why Cognitive Science Poses No Threat to Religious Studies”, Working Paper.Google Scholar
McCauley, Robert and Bechtel, William (2001): “Explanatory Pluralism and Heuristic Identity Theory”, Theory and Psychology, vol. 11, pp. 736760.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMullen, Emerson Thomas (1995): “Anatomy of a Physiological Discovery: William Harvey and the Circulation of the Blood”, Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine, vol. 88, pp. 491498.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan (1983/2012): “Values in Science”, in PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, vol. 182, vol. Two: Symposia and Invited Papers, and reprinted in Zygon, vol. 47, pp. 686709.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan (2008): “The Virtues of a Good Theory”, in Psillos, Stathis and Curd, Martin (eds.): The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science, London and New York: Routledge, pp. 498508.Google Scholar
Menger, Carl (1871/1968): Grundsätze der Volkswirtschaftslehre, Wien: Wilhelm Braumüller, and 2nd edition 1968 by von Hayek, Friedrich A.: Carl Menger: Gesammelte Werke, Band I, Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).Google Scholar
Menger, Carl (1976): Principles of Economics, translated by Dingwall, James and Hoselitz, Bert F., Arlington, VA: The Institue for Humane Studies.Google Scholar
Meyerhof, Max (1935): “Ibn An-Nafis (XIIIth cent.) and His Theory of the Lesser Circulation”, Isis, vol. 23, pp. 100120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John Stuart (1843/1974): A System of Logic. Ratiocinative and Inductive, vol. VII of the Collected Works of Mill, John Stuart, ed., Robson, J.M. and McRae, R.F., Toronto: University of Toronto Press and Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart (1848/1909): Principles of Political Economy with Some of Their Applications to Social Philosophy, 7th edition, London: Longmans Green and Co.Google Scholar
Mitchell, Sandra (2003): Biological Complexity and Integrative Pluralism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitchell, Sandra (2009a): Unsimple Truths. Science, Complexity and Policy, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitchell, Sandra (2009b): “Complexity and Explanation in the Social Sciences”, in: Mantzavinos, C. (ed.): Philosophy of the Social Sciences. Philosophical Theory and Scientific Practice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 130145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mithen, Steven (1996): The Prehistory of the Mind: The Cognitive Origins of Art, Religion and Science, New York: Thames and Hudson.Google Scholar
Mithen, Steven (2002): “Human Evolution and the Cognitive Basis of Sciences”, in Carruthers, Peter, Stephen, Stich, and Siegal, Michael (eds.): The Cognitive Basis of Science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 2340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morrison, Margaret (2000): Unifying Scientific Theories, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mueller, Dennis (2003): Public Choice III, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Ernst (1961): The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nathan, Marco J. (2015): “Unificatory Explanation”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science (Advance Access), published July 8, 2015.Google Scholar
Nee, Victor (1998): “Norms and Networks in Economic and Organizational Performance”, American Economic Review (Papers and Proceedings), vol. 88, pp. 8589.Google Scholar
Nee, Victor and Ingram, Paul (1998): “Embeddedness and Beyond: Institutions, Exchange and Social Structure”, in Nee, Victor and Brinton, Mary C. (eds.): The New Institutionalism in Sociology, New York: Russell Sage Foundation, pp. 1945.Google Scholar
Nee, Victor and Strang, David (1998): “The Emergence and Diffusion of Institutional Forms”, Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, vol. 154, pp. 706715.Google Scholar
Nelson, Richard and Winter, Sidney (1982): An Evolutionary Theory of Economic Change, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Nersessian, Nancy (1992): “How Do Scientists Think? Capturing the Dynamics of Conceptual Change in Science”, in Giere, Ronald (ed.): Cognitive Models of Science, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. XV, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 344.Google Scholar
Nersessian, Nancy (2008a): Creating Scientific Concepts, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nersessian, Nancy (2008b): “Mental Modeling in Conceptual Change”, in Vosniadou, Stella (ed.): International Handbook of Research on Conceptual Change, London and New York: Routledge, pp. 391416.Google Scholar
Neumann, John and Morgenstern, Oskar (1944): Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Newell, Allen and Simon, Herbert (1972): Human Problem Solving, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Nickel, Bernhard (2010): “How General Do Theories of Explanation Need to Be?Noûs, vol. 42, pp. 305328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickles, Thomas (2006): “Heuristic Appraisal: Context of Discovery or Justification?”, in Schickore, Jutta and Steinle, Friedrich (eds.): Revisiting Discovery and Justification, Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 159182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nietzsche, Friedrich (1887): Zur Genealogie der Moral. Eine Streitschrift, Leigzig: Verlag C.G. Naumann.Google Scholar
Nisbett, Richard and Ross, Lee (1980): Human Inference: Strategies and Shortcomings of Social Judgment, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
North, Douglass C. (1990): Institutions, Institutional Change, and Economic Performance, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozick, Robert (1994): “Invisible-Hand Explanations”, American Economic Review (Papers and Proceedings), vol. 84, pp. 314318.Google Scholar
Nutton, Vivian (2004): Ancient Medicine, London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nutton, Vivian (2008): “The Fortunes of Galen”, in Hankinson, Robert J. (ed.): The Cambridge Companion to Galen, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 355390.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Olson, Mancur (1965): The Logic of Collective Action, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
O’Malley, Charles Donald (1970): “The Lure of Padua”, Medical History, vol. 14, pp.19.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Opp, Karl-Dieter (1979): “The Emergence and Effects of Social Norms. A Confrontation of Some Hypotheses of Sociology and Economics”, Kyklos, vol. 32, pp. 775801.Google Scholar
Opp, Karl-Dieter (1982): “The Evolutionary Emergence of Norms”, British Journal of Social Psychology, vol. 21, pp. 139149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ott, Alfred E. and Winkel, Harald (1985): Geschichte der theoretischen Volkswirtschaftslehre, Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.Google Scholar
Overton, James A. (2013): “‘Explain’ in Scientific Discourse”, Synthese, vol. 190, pp. 13831405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Palmieri, Paolo (2012): “Signals, Cochlear Mechanics and Pragmatism: A New Vista on Human Hearing?”, Journal of Experimental & Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, vol. 24, pp. 527548.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Papineau, David (2009): “Physicalism and the Human Sciences”, in Mantzavinos, C. (ed.): Philosophy of the Social Sciences. Philosophical Theory and Scientific Practice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 103123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perini, Laura (2005a): “The Truth in Pictures”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 72, pp. 262285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perini, Laura (2005b): “Visual Representations and Confirmation”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 72, pp. 913926.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perini, Laura (2005c): “Explanation in Two Dimensions: Diagrams and Biological Explanation”, Biology and Philosophy, vol. 20, pp. 257269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perini, Laura (2013): “Diagrams in Biology”, The Knowledge Engineering Review, vol. 28, pp. 273286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Petkov, Stefan (2015): “Explanatory Unification and Conceptualization”, Synthese, vol. 192, pp. 36953717.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Piaget, Jean (1936): La Naissance de l’ Intelligence chez l’Enfant, Neuchatel and Paris: Delachau et Niestle.Google Scholar
Pincock, Christopher (2012): Mathematics and Scientific Representation, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pincock, Christopher (2015): “Abstract Explanations in Science”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, vol. 66, pp. 857882.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plutynski, Anya (2004): “Explanation in Classical Population Genetics”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 71, pp. 12011214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polanyi, Michael (1958): Personal Knowledge, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1934): Logik der Forschung, Vienna: Springer, Imprint 1935, actually published 1934.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1949): “Naturgesetze und theoretische Systeme,” in Moser, Simon (ed.): Gesetze und Wirklichkeit, Innsbruck: Tyrolia-Verlag, pp. 4360.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1957): “The Aim of Science”, Ratio, I, pp. 2435 [and reprinted in Objective Knowledge. An Evolutionary Approach, rev. edition, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979, pp. 191205].Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1958/1989): “Back to the Presocratics”, in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, N.S. vol. 59, and reprinted in: Conjectures and Refutations. The Growth of Scientific Knowledge, 5th revised edition, London: Routledge, pp. 136165.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1959/2002): The Logic of Scientific Discovery, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1963/1989): Conjectures and Refutations. The Growth of Scientific Knowledge, 5th revised edition, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1970): “Normal Science and Its Dangers”, in Lakatos, Imre and Musgrave, Alan (eds.): Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 5158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1972/1992): Objective Knowledge. An Evolutionary Approach, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1987): “Die erkenntnistheoretische Position der evolutionären Erkenntnistheorie”, in Riedl, Rupert and Wuketits, Franz (eds.): Die Evolutionäre Erkenntnistheorie. Bedingungen. Lösungen. Kontroversen, Berlin: Parcy.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. and Eccles, John C. (1977/1983): The Self and Its Brain. An Argument for Interactionism, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Posner, Richard (2010): Economic Analysis of Law, 8th edition, New York: Aspen Publishers.Google Scholar
Potochnik, Angela (2010): “Levels of Explanation Reconceived”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 77, pp. 5972.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prioreschi, Plinio (2004): “Andrea Cesalpino and Systemic Circulation”, Annales Pharmaceutiques Francaises, vol. 62, pp. 382400.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Psillos, Stathis (2002): Causation and Explanation, Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Psillos, Stathis (2007): “Past and Contemporary Perspectives on Explanation”, in Kuipers, Theo (ed.): Handbook of the Philosophy of Science. Focal Issues, Amsterdam and Oxford: Elsevier, pp. 97174.Google Scholar
Railton, Peter (1978): “A Deductive-Nomological Model of Probabilistic Explanation”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 45, pp. 206226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Railton, Peter (1981): “Probability, Explanation and Information”, Synthese, vol. 48, pp. 233256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reutlinger, Alexander (2014): “Why Is There Universal Macrobehavior? Renormalization Group Explanation as Noncausal Explanation”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 81, pp. 11571170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ricardo, David (1817/1951): On the Principles of Political Economy and Taxation, ed. Sraffa, Pierro, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rice, Collin (2015): “Moving Beyond Causes: Optimality Models and Scientific Explanation”, Noûs, vol. 49, pp. 589615.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richardson, Alan W. (2006): “The Many Unities of Science: Politics, Semantics, and Ontology”, in Kellert, Stephen H., Longino, Helen E., and Kenneth Waters, C. (eds.): Scientific Pluralism, Minneapolis and London: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 125.Google Scholar
Rocca, Julius (2008): “Anatomy”, in Hankinson, Robert J. (ed.): The Cambridge Companion to Galen, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 242262.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rogers, Brian and Cassandra, Rogers (2009): “Visual Globes, Celestial Spheres, and the Perception of Straight and Parallel Lines”, Perception, vol. 38, pp. 12951312.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rosefeld, Tobias (2004): “Is Knowing-how Simply a Case of Knowing-that?Philosophical Investigations, vol. 27, pp. 370379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roth, Moritz (1892): Andreas Vesalius Bruxellensis, Berlin: George Reimer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruben, David-Hillel (2012): Explaining Explanation, 2nd edition, Boulder and London: Paradigm Publishers.Google Scholar
Ruphy, Stéphanie (2011): “From Hacking’s Plurality of Styles of Scientific Reasoning to ‘Foliated Pluralism’: A Philosophically Robust Form of Ontologico-Methodological Pluralism”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 78, pp. 12121222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, Bertrand (1912): “On the Notion of Cause”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society New Series, vol. 13, pp. 126.Google Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert (1949): The Concept of Mind, London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Saatsi, Juha and Pexton, Mark (2013): “Reassessing Woodward’s Account of Explanation: Regularities, Counterfactuals, and Noncausal Explanations”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 80, pp. 613624.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, Wesley (1970): “Statistical Explanation”, in Colodny, Robert G. (ed.): The Nature and Function of Scientific Theories, Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, pp. 173231. [Reprinted in Salmon, Wesley (1971): Statistical Explanation and Statistical Relevance, Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, pp. 2987.]Google Scholar
Salmon, Wesley (1984): Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, Wesley (1990): Four Decades of Scientific Explanation, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, Wesley (1998): Causality and Explanation, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Samarapungavan, Ala (1992): “Children’s Judgments in Theory Choice Tasks: Scientific Rationality in Childhood”, Cognition, vol. 45, pp. 132.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schank, Roger and Abelson, Robert (1977): Scripts, Plans, Goals and Understanding, Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Schiffer, Stephen (2002): “Amazing Knowledge”, Journal of Philosophy, vol. 99, pp. 200202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmid, Michael (2006): Die Logik mechanismischer Erklärungen, Wiesbaden: VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften.Google Scholar
Schrödinger, Erwin (1958): Mind and Matter, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schupbach, Jonah N. and Sprenger, Jan (2011): “The Logic of Explanatory Power”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 78, pp. 105127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schurz, Gerhard (1999): “Explanation as Unification”, Synthese, vol. 120, pp. 95114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schurz, Gerhard and Lambert, Karel (1994): “Outline of a Theory of Scientific Understanding”, Synthese, vol. 101, pp. 65120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Servetus, Miguel (1553): Christianismi Restitutio, Vienne, English translation: The Restoration of Christianity, by Hoffmann, Christopher A. and Hiller, Marian, Lewiston, NY: The Edwin Mellen Press, 2008.Google Scholar
Sextus, Empiricus (1933): Outlines of Pyrrhonism, translated by Bury, R.G., Loeb Classical Library, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sheredos, Benjamin, Daniel, Burnston, Adele, Abrahamsen and William, Bechtel (2013): “Why Do Biologists Use So Many Diagrams?”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 80, pp. 931944.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shulman, Robert G. and Shapiro, Ian (2009): “Reductionism in the Human Sciences: A Philosopher’s Game”, in Mantzavinos, C. (ed.): Philosophy of the Social Sciences. Philosophical Theory and Scientific Practice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 124129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simon, Herbert (1992): “Scientific Discovery as Problem Solving”, in Egidi, Massimo and Marris, Robin (eds.): Economics, Bounded Rationality and the Cognitive Revolution, Hants: Edward Elgar, pp. 102119.Google Scholar
Simon, Herbert (2000): “Discovering Explanations”, in Keil, Frank C. and Wilson, Robert A. (eds.): Explanation and Cognition, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, pp. 2159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siraisi, Nancy (1981): Tadeo Alderotti and His Pupils: Two Generations of Italian Medical Learning, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Skow, Bradford (2014): “Are There Non-Causal Explanations (of Particular Events?)British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, vol. 65, pp. 445467.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skow, Bradford (2015): “Are There Genuine Physical Explanations of Mathematical Phenomena?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, vol. 66, pp. 6993.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Adam (1759/1976): The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Adam (1776/1976): An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, ed. Cannan, Edwin, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Smith, Ryan (2014): “Explanation, Understanding, and Control”, Synthese, vol. 191, pp. 41694200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snellen, H.A. (1984): History of Cardiology, Rotterdam: Donker Academic Publications.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (1983): “Equilibrium Explanation”, Philosophical Studies, vol. 43, pp. 201210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, Elliott (2002): “What is the Problem of Simplicity?” in Zellner, Arnold, Keuzenbach, Hugo and McAleer, Michael (eds.): Simplicity, Inference and Econometric Modelling, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1331.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sokal, Alan and Bricmont, Jean (1997): Les Impostures Intellectuelles, Paris: Editions Odile Jacob.Google Scholar
Staden, Heinrich von (1995): “Anatomy as Rhetoric: Galen on Dissection and Persuasion”, Journal of the History of Medicine and Allied Sciences, vol. 50, pp. 4766.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanley, Jason (2011): Know How, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanley, Jason and Williamson, Timothy (2001): “Knowing How”, The Journal of Philosophy, vol. 98, pp. 411444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steel, Daniel (2004): “Can a Reductionist Be a Pluralist?”, Biology and Philosophy, vol. 19, pp. 5573.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steiner, Mark (1978a): “Mathematical Explanation”, Philosophical Studies, vol. 34, pp. 135151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steiner, Mark (1978b): “Mathematics, Explanation, and Scientific Knowledge”, Noûs, vol. 12, pp. 1728.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, Kim (1996): “Explanatory Pluralism in Evolutionary Biology”, Biology and Philosophy, vol. 11, pp. 193214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, Kim (2014): The Evolved Apprentice. How Evolution Made Humans Unique, Cambridge, MA, and London: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Streissler, Erich (1989): “Carl Menger”, in Starbatty, Joachim (ed.): Klassiker des ökonomischen Denkens, vol. II, München: Beck, pp. 118127.Google Scholar
Strevens, Michael (2008): Depth. An Account of Scientific Explanation, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Stump, David (1992): “Naturalized Philosophy of Science with a Plurality of Methods”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 59, pp. 456460.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suárez, Mauricio (2004): “An Inferential Conception of Scientific Representation”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 71, pp. 767779.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suárez, Mauricio (2015): “Deflationary Representation, Inference, and Practice”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol. 49, pp. 3647.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, Robert (1998): “Normative Expectations: The Simultaneous Evolution of Institutions and Norms”, in Ben-Ner, Avner and Putterman, Louis (eds.): Economics, Values, and Organization, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 73100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sun, Ron, Merrill, Edward, and Peterson, Todd (2001): “From Implicit Skills to Explicit Knowledge: A Bottom-Up Model of Skill Learning”, Cognitive Science, vol. 25, pp. 203244.Google Scholar
Suppes, Patrick (1978): “The Plurality of Science”, Philosophy of Science, Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 2: Symposia and Invited Papers, pp. 316.Google Scholar
Teller, Paul (2008): “Representation in Science”, in Psillos, Stathis and Curd, Martin (eds.): The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science, London and New York, pp. 435441.Google Scholar
Thagard, Paul (1988): Computational Philosophy of Science, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thagard, Paul (1996): Mind. An Introduction into Cognitive Science, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Thagard, Paul (2012): The Cognitive Science of Science. Explanation, Discovery and Conceptual Change, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thalos, Mariam (2002): “Explanation is a Genus: An Essay on the Varieties of Scientific Explanation”, Synthese, vol. 130, pp. 317354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thiene, Gaetano (1997): “The Discovery of Circulation and the Origin of Modern Medicine during the Italian Renaissance”, Cardiovascular Pathology, vol. 6 (2), March/April, pp. 7988.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Thünen, Johann Heinrich (1842): Der isolierte Staat in Beziehung auf Landwirtschaft und Nationalökonomie, zweite erweiterte Ausgabe, Rostock: Leopold.Google Scholar
Topitsch, Ernst (1958): Vom Ursprung und Ende der Metaphysik. Eine Studie zur Weltanschauungskritik, Wien: Springer Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trivers, Robert (1971): “The Evolution of Reciprocal Altruism”, Quarterly Review of Biology, vol. 46, pp. 4557.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ullmann-Margalit, Edna (1978): “Invisible-Hand Explanations”, Synthese, vol. 39, pp. 263291.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Bouwel, Jeroen (2004): “Explanatory Pluralism in Economics: Against the Mainstream?Philosophical Explorations, vol. 7, pp. 299315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Bouwel, Jeroen and Weber, Erik (2008): “A Pragmatist Defense of Non-Relativistic Explanatory Pluralism in History and Social Science”, History and Theory, vol. 47, pp. 168182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas C. (1980): The Scientific Image, Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas C. (2008): Scientific Representation, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vesalius, Andreas (1538): Tabulae Anatomicae Sex, Venice.Google Scholar
Vesalius, Andreas (1543): De Humani Corporis Fabrica Libri Septem, Basel: Johannes Oporinus, English Translation: On the Fabric of the Human Body, by William Frank Richardson and John Burd Carman, volume 5 containing Books VI: The Heart and Associated Organs and Book VI: The Brain, Novato CA: Norman Anatomy Series, No 5.Google Scholar
Vollmer, Gerhard (1975/2002): Evolutionäre Erkenntnistheorie, 8th edition, Stuttgart: Hirzel.Google Scholar
Vosniadou, Stella and Brewer, William F. (1992): “Mental Models of the Earth: A Study of Conceptual Change in Childhood”, Cognitive Psychology, vol. 24, pp. 535585.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vosniadou, Stella and Brewer, William F. (1994): “Mental Models of the Day/Night Cycle”, Cognitive Science, vol. 18, pp. 123183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vosniadou, Stella, Vamvakoussi, Xenia, and Skopeliti, Irini (2008): “The Framework Theory Approach to the Problem of Conceptual Change”, in Vosniadou, Stella (ed.): International Handbook of Research on Conceptual Change, New York and London: Routledge, pp. 334.Google Scholar
Wallis, Charles (2008): “Consciousness, Context, and Know-How”, Synthese, vol. 160, pp. 123153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walras, Leon (1874): Éléments d’Économie Politique Pure, ou Théorie de la Richesse Sociale, Lausanne: L. Corbaz & Cie.Google Scholar
Weatherall, James Owen (2011): “On (Some) Explanations in Physics”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 78, pp. 421447.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weber, Erik and van Bouwel, Jeroen (2002): “Symposium on Explanations and Social Ontology 3: Can We Dispense with Structural Explanations of Social Facts?”, Economics and Philosophy, vol. 18, pp. 259275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weber, Erik, van Bouwel, Jeroen, and de Vreese, Leen (2013): Scientific Explanation, Heidelberg, New York and London: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weber, Max (1985): Gesammelte Aufsätze für Wissenschaftslehre, 6th revised edition, Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).Google Scholar
Weslake, Brad (2010): “Explanatory Depth”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 77, pp. 273294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whitehead, Alfred N. (1911): An Introduction to Mathematics, London: Williams and Norgate.Google Scholar
Wiberg, Julius (1937): “The Medical Science of Ancient Greece: The Doctrine of the Heart”, Janus, vol. 41, pp. 225254.Google Scholar
Wilkenfeld, Daniel A. (2014): “Functional Explaining. A New Approach to the Philosophy of Explanation”, Synthese, vol. 191, pp. 33673391.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Willius, Fredrick A. and Dry, Thomas J. (1948): A History of the Heart and the Circulation, Philadelphia: WB Saunders Co.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, William C. (1976): “Reductionism, Levels of Organization, and the Mind-Body Problem”, in Globus, G., Maxwell, G. and Savodnik, I. (eds.), Consciousness and the Brain: A Scientific and Philosophical Inquiry, New York: Plenum, pp. 202267.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, William C. (2007): Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings. Piecewise Approximations to Reality, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Winter, Susan (2013): The Prince of Medicine: Galen in the Roman Empire, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1953): Philosophische Untersuchungen/Philosophical Investigations, translated by Anscombe, G.E.M., Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wong, Wai-hung and Zanja, Yudell (2015): “A Normative Account of the Need for Explanation”, Synthese, vol. 192, pp. 28632885.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodward, James (2000): “Explanation and Invariance in the Special Sciences,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, vol. 51, pp. 197254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodward, James (2003): Making Things Happen, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Woodward, James (2014): “Interventionism and Causal Exclusion”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, DOI:10.1111/phpr.12095.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woody, Andrea I. (2004): “More Telltale Signs: What Attention to Representation Reveals About Scientific Explanation”, Philosophy of Science, vol. 71, pp. 780793.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woody, Andrea I. (2015): “Re-orienting Discussions of Scentific Explanation: A Functional Perspective”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol. 52, pp. 7987.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, Cory (2015): “The Ontic Conception of Scientific Explanation”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol. 54, pp. 2030.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ylikoski, Petri and Kuorikoski, Jaako (2010): “Dissecting Explanatory Power”, Philosophical Studies, vol. 148, pp. 201219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • C. Mantzavinos, University of Athens, Greece
  • Book: Explanatory Pluralism
  • Online publication: 05 May 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316440599.014
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • C. Mantzavinos, University of Athens, Greece
  • Book: Explanatory Pluralism
  • Online publication: 05 May 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316440599.014
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • C. Mantzavinos, University of Athens, Greece
  • Book: Explanatory Pluralism
  • Online publication: 05 May 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316440599.014
Available formats
×