Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-swr86 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-24T04:56:24.228Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 March 2019

Jason W. Carter
Affiliation:
University of Edinburgh
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Aristotle on Earlier Greek Psychology
The Science of Soul
, pp. 228 - 242
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2019

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Primary Sources

Barnes, J. (1984). The Complete Works of Aristotle. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (1994). Posterior Analytics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hamlyn, D. (2002). Aristotle De Anima: Books II and II (With Passages from Book I). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hett, W. (1986). Aristotle: On the Soul, Parva Naturalia, On Breath (Loeb Classical Library). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hicks, R. (1907). Aristotle De Anima. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Jannone, A., and Barbotin, E. (2002). Aristote: De l’ame. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Joachim, H. (1922). Aristotle on Coming-To-Be and Passing-Away. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. (2017). Aristotle: De Anima. Translated with Introduction and Notes. Indianapolis, IN/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Rodier, G. (1900). Aristote, Traité de l’ame, 2 vols. Paris: Ernest Leroux.Google Scholar
Ross, W. (1936). Aristotle’s Physics: A Revised Text with Introduction and Commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. (1949). Aristotle’s Prior and Posterior Analytics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. (1956). Aristotelis De Anima. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [=OCT]Google Scholar
Ross, W. (1961). Aristotle De Anima: Edited, with Introduction and Commentary. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shields, C. (2016). Aristotle: De Anima, Translated with an Introduction and Commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Smith, J. (1931). De Anima, trans. Smith, J., in The Works of Aristotle, vol. 3, ed. Ross, W.D.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Torstrik, A. (1863). Aristotelis De Anima Libri III. Berolini: apud Weidmannos.Google Scholar
Tricot, J. (2010). Aristote: De l’âme. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar

Secondary Sources

Curd, P. (2010). Anaxagoras of Clazomenae: Fragments and Testimonia. A Text and Translation with Notes and Essays. Toronto, Ontario: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Diels, H. (1951). Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, 6th edn, revised by Kranz, Walter, 3 vols. Berlin: Weidmann.Google Scholar
Graham, D. (2010). The Texts of Early Greek Philosophy: The Complete Fragments and Selected Testimonies of the Major Presocratics, 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kahn, C. (1994). Anaximander and the Origins of Greek Cosmology. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Kirk, G., Raven, J., and Schofield, M. (1983). The Presocratic Philosophers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKirahan, R. (2010). Philosophy before Socrates: An Introduction with Texts and Commentary, 2nd edn. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Sider, D. (2005). The Fragments of Anaxagoras: Edited with an Introduction and Commentary. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. (1999). The Atomists Leucippus and Democritus: Fragments: A Text and Translation. Toronto, Ontario: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Wright, M. (2001). Empedocles: The Extant Fragments. London: Bristol Classical Press.Google Scholar
Aeschylus, . (1955). Septem Quae Supersunt Tragoedias, ed. Page, D.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Aquinas, T. (1959). In Aristotelis librum de Anima commentarium, ed. Pirotta, M.. Taurini: Marietti. [= In De an.]Google Scholar
Aquinas, T. (19641981). Summa Theologiae. London: Blackfriars. [=Summa]Google Scholar
Augustine, . (1933). De Quantitate Animae: The Measure of the Soul. Latin text, trans. Tourscher, F.. London: B. Herder.Google Scholar
Cicero, M. (1927). Tusculan Disputations (Loeb Classical Library). London: W. Heineman. [=Tusc. Disp.]Google Scholar
Diels, H. (1879). Doxographi Graeci. Berlin: Reimer.Google Scholar
Epicurus, . (1926): Epicurus: The Extant Remains, with Short Critical Apparatus, ed. and trans. Bailey, C.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Euripides, . (1984). Euripides Fabulae, Vol. 1, ed. Diggle, J.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fortenbaugh, W., and Schütrumpf, E. (2001). Dicaearchus of Messana: Text, Translation, and Discussion (Rutgers University Studies in Classical Humanities). London: Transaction Books.Google Scholar
Galen, . (1979). Galen on the Doctrines of Hippocrates and Plato (Corpus Medicorum Graecorum; V.4, 1,2), ed. and trans. De Lacy, P.. Berlin: Academie–Verlag. [=PHP]Google Scholar
Heinze, R. (1892). Xenocrates: Darstellung der Lehre und Sammlung der Fragmente. Leipzig: B.G. Teubner.Google Scholar
Herodotus, . (1958). Historiae, ed. Hude, C.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Homer, . (1920). Homeri Opera, 5 vols. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Philoponus, . (1991). Philoponus: On Aristotle on the Intellect (De Anima 3.4–8), trans. Charlton, W.. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Plutarch, . (1976). De animae Procreation in Timaeo, trans. by Cherniss, Harold, in: Plutarch’s Moralia, Vol. XIII, Part 1. London: Loeb.Google Scholar
Simplicius, . (1995). On Aristotle’s on the Soul 1.1–2.4, trans. Urmson, J.. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Waszink, J. (2010). Quinti Septimi Florentis Tertulliani De Anima. Leiden, the Netherlands: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ackrill, J. (1972/1973). ‘Aristotle’s Definitions of Psuche’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 73:119–33.Google Scholar
Ackrill, J. (1981). ‘Aristotle’s Theory of Definition: Some Questions on Posterior Analytics II 8–10’, in Berti, (1981):359–84.Google Scholar
Algra, K., van der Horst, P., and Runia, D. (1996). Polyhistor: Studies in the History and Historiography of Ancient Philosophy. Leiden, the Netherlands: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, J. (1974). ‘Forms and First Principles’. Phronesis 19:257–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, J. (1976). Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Books M and N. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bailey, C. (1928). The Greek Atomists and Epicurus: A Study. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Balme, D. (1941). ‘Greek Science and Mechanism II: The Atomists’. Classical Quarterly 35:23–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baltussen, H. (1996). ‘A “Dialectical” Argument in De Anima A 4: On Aristotle’s Use of Topoi in Systematic Contexts’, in Algra, van der Horst, and Runia (1996):333–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baltussen, H. (2000). Theophrastus against the Preoscratics and Plato: Peripatetic Dialectic in the De Sensibus. Leiden, the Netherlands: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barker, A. (1984). ‘Aristoxenus’ Theorems and the Foundations of Harmonic Science’. Ancient Philosophy 4:23–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barker, A. (1988). ‘Aristotle on Perception and Ratios’. Phronesis 26:248–66.Google Scholar
Barker, A. (2007). The Science of Harmonics in Classical Greece. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, J. (1971/1972). ‘Aristotle’s Concept of Mind’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 72:101–14.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (1980). ‘Aristotle and the Methods of Ethics’. Revue internationale de philosophie 133/134: 490–511.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (1982). The Presocratic Philosophers. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Barney, R. (2012). ‘History and Dialectic (Metaphysics A 3, 983a24–4b8)’, in Steel, and Primavesi, (2012):66–104.Google Scholar
Bartoš, H. (2006). ‘Varieties of the Ancient Greek Body Soul Distinction’. Rhizai 1: 59–78.Google Scholar
Bastit, M. (1996). ‘Qu’est-ce qu’une Partie de l’Âme pour Aristote?’, in Viano, (1996):13–36.Google Scholar
Beare, J. (1906). Greek Theories of Elementary Cognition: From Alcmaeon to Aristotle. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Benson, H. (2003). ‘The Method of Hypothesis in the Meno’. Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 18:95–143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berryman, S. (2002). ‘Aristotle on Pneuma and Animal Self-Motion’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 23:85–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berryman, S. (2003). ‘Ancient Automata and Mechanical Explanation’. Phronesis 48:344–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berti, E. (1981). Aristotle on Science: Proceedings of the Eighth Symposium Aristotelicum. Padua, Italy: Editrice Antenore.Google Scholar
Betegh, G. (2004). The Derveni Papyrus: Cosmology, Theology and Interpretation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Betegh, G. (2009). ‘The Limits of the Soul: Heraclitus B45 DK. Its Text and Interpretation’, in Hülsz, (2009):391–414.Google Scholar
Blair, G. (1967). ‘The Meaning of “Energeia” and “Entelecheia” in Aristotle’. International Philosophical Quarterly 7:101–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bobzien, S. (1998). ‘The Inadvertent Conception and Late Birth of the Free-Will Problem’. Phronesis 43:133–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bobzien, S. (2000). ‘Did Epicurus Discover the Free Will Problem?Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 19: 287–337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bogen, J. (1996). ‘Fire in the Belly: Aristotelian Elements, Organisms, and Chemical Compounds’, in Lewis, and Bolton, (1996):183–216.Google Scholar
Bolton, R. (1987). ‘Definition and Scientific Method in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics and Generation of Animals’, in Gotthelf, and Lennox, (1987):120–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bolton, R. (1991). ‘Aristotle’s Method in Natural Science: Physics I’, in Judson, (1991):1–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bolton, R. (1994). ‘The Problem of Dialectical Reasoning (Συλλογισμός)’. Ancient Philosophy 14:99–132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bonitz, H. (1955). Index Aristotelicus, ed. Meyer, Jürgen Bona. Graz, Austria: Akademische Druck-U. Verlagsanstalt.Google Scholar
Bordt, M. (2011). ‘Why Aristotle’s God Is Not the Unmoved Mover’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 40:91–109.Google Scholar
Bos, A. (2007). ‘Aristotle on Dissection of Plants and Animals and His Concept of the Instrumental Soul–body’. Ancient Philosophy 27:95–106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowen, A., and Wildberg, C. (2009). New Perspectives on Aristotle’s De Caelo. Leiden, the Netherlands: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowin, J. (2011). ‘Aristotle on Various Types of Alteration in De Anima II 5’. Phronesis 56:138–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bradshaw, D. (1997). ‘Aristotle on Perception: The Dual-Logos Theory’. Apeiron 30:143–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brancacci, A., and Morel, P.-M. (2007). Democritus: Science, the Arts, and the Care of the Soul – Proceedings of the International Colloquium on Democritus. Leiden, the Netherlands: Brill.Google Scholar
Brentano, F. (1977). The Psychology of Aristotle, ed. and trans. George, R.. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Brody, B. (1972). ‘Towards an Aristotelian Theory of Scientific Explanation’. Philosophy of Science 39:20–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bronstein, D. (2016). Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burkert, W. (1972). Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. (1981). ‘Aristotle on Understanding Knowledge’, in Berti, (1981):97–139.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. (1992a). ‘Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind Still Credible? A Draft’, in Nussbaum, and Rorty, (1992):15–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnyeat, M. (1992b). ‘How Much Happens When Aristotle Sees Red and Hears Middle C? Remarks on De Anima 2.7–8’, in Nussbaum, and Rorty, (1992):421–34.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. (2002). ‘De Anima ii.5’. Phronesis 47:28–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnyeat, M. (2004). ‘Aristotle on the Foundations of Sublunary Physics’, in de Haas and Mansfeld (2004):7–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnyeat, M. (2008). Aristotle’s Divine Intellect. Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
Bywater, I. (1888). ‘Aristotelia III’. The Journal of Philology 17:53–74.Google Scholar
Carter, J. (2017). ‘Aristotle’s Critique of Timaean Psychology’. Rhizomata 5:51–78.Google Scholar
Carter, J. (2018). ‘Does the Soul Weave? Reconsidering De Anima 1.4, 408a29–b18’. Phronesis 63:25–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caston, V. (1993). ‘Aristotle and Supervenience’. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 31 (Supplement):107–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caston, V. (1997). ‘Epiphenomenalisms, Ancient and Modern’. The Philosophical Review 106:309–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caston, V. (1999). ‘Aristotle’s Two Intellects: A Modest Proposal’. Phronesis 44:199–227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caston, V. (2000). ‘Aristotle’s Argument for Why the Understanding Is Not Compounded with the Body’. Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 16:135–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caston, V. (2005). ‘The Spirit and the Letter: Aristotle on Perception’, in Salles, (2005):245–320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, A. (1997). ‘Did Democritus Ascribe Weight to Atoms?Australasian Journal of Philosophy 75:279–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D., Manley, D., and Wasserman, R. (2009). Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charles, D. (2005). Aristotle on Meaning and Essence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Charlton, W. (1985). ‘Aristotle and the Harmonia Theory’, in Gotthelf, (1985):131–50.Google Scholar
Charles, D. (1991). ‘Aristotle’s Definition of Soul’. Phronesis 25: 170–86.Google Scholar
Cherniss, H. (1935). Aristotle’s Criticism of Presocratic Philosophy. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Press.Google Scholar
Cherniss, H. (1944). Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato and the Academy. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Press.Google Scholar
Chiba, K. (2012). ‘Aristotle on Heuristic Inquiry and Demonstration of What it Is’, in Shields, (2012):171–201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cleary, J. (1994). ‘Phainomena in Aristotle’s Methodology’. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 2: 61–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Code, A. (1987). ‘Soul as Efficient Cause in Aristotle’s Embryology’. Philosophical Topics 15:51–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Code, A. (1991). ‘Aristotle, Searle, and the Mind–Body Problem’, in Lepore, and Van Gulick, (1991):105–13.Google Scholar
Cohen, S. (1992). ‘Hylomorphism and Functionalism’, in Nussbaum, and Rorty, (1992):57–73.Google Scholar
Cohoe, C. (2013). ‘Why the Intellect Cannot Have a Bodily Organ: De Anima 3.4’. Phronesis 58:344–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohoe, C. (2016). ‘When and Why Understanding Needs Phantasmata: A Moderate Interpretation of Aristotle’s De Memoria and De Anima on the Role of Images in Intellectual Activities’. Phronesis 61:337–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collobert, C. (2002). ‘Aristotle’s Review of the Presocratics: Is Aristotle Finally a Historian of Philosophy?’. Journal of the History of Philosophy 40:281–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coope, U. (2005). Time for Aristotle: Physics IV. 10–14. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooper, J. (2012). ‘Conclusion – and Retrospect: Metaphysics A.10’, in Steel, and Primavesi, (2012):333–64.Google Scholar
Corcilius, K., and Gregoric, P. (2010). ‘Separability vs. Difference: Parts and Capacities of the Soul in Aristotle’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 39:81–120.Google Scholar
Crane, T., and Patterson, S. (2000). The History of the Mind Body Problem. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Crowley, T. (2008). ‘Aristotle’s “So-Called” Elements’. Phronesis 53:223–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Curd, P. (2010). Anaxagoras of Clazomenae: Fragments and Testimonia. A Text and Translation with Notes and Essays by Patricia Curd. Toronto, Ontario: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Curd, P., and Graham, D. (2008). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dancy, R. (1996). ‘Keeping Body and Soul Together: On Aristotle’s Theory of Forms’, in Wians, (1996):249–87.Google Scholar
Danieli, M. (1984). Zum Problem der Traditionsaneignung bei Aristoteles: Untersucht am Beispiel von De Anima I. Königstein/Ts: Anton Hain.Google Scholar
Darcus, S. (1977). ‘Daimon Parallels the Holy Phren in Empedocles’. Phronesis 22:175–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. (2001). Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Haas, F., and Mansfeld, J. (2004). Aristotle: On Generation and Corruption, Book 1: Symposium Aristotelicum. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Descartes, R. (1984). The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, eds. Cottingham, J., Stoothoff, R., and Murdoch, D.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [=CSM]Google Scholar
Deslauriers, M. (2007). Aristotle on Definition. Leiden: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Destrée, P., Salles, R., and Zingano, M. (2014). What Is Up to Us?: Studies on Agency and Responsibility in Ancient Philosophy: Sankt Augustin: Academia Richarz.Google Scholar
Dillon, J. (1985). ‘Xenocrates’ Metaphysics: Fr. 15 (Heinze) Re-Examined’. Ancient Philosophy 5:47–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dillon, J. (1996). The Middle Platonists: 80 B.C.–A.D. 2020. New York: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Dillon, J. (2003). The Heirs of Plato: A Study of the Old Academy (347–274 B.C.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Distelzweig, P. (2013). ‘The Intersection of the Mathematical and Natural Sciences: The Subordinate Sciences in Aristotle’. Apeiron 46:85–105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Driscoll, J. (1992). ‘The Anaxagorean Assumption in Aristotle’s Account of Mind’, in Preus, and Anton, (1992):273–92.Google Scholar
Edmunds, L. (1972). ‘Necessity, Chance, and Freedom in the Early Atomists’. Phoenix 26:342–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engberg-Peterson, T. (1979). ‘More on Aristotelian Epagoge’. Phronesis 24:301–19.Google Scholar
Englert, W. (1987). Epicurus on the Swerve and Voluntary Action. Atlanta, GA: Scholars Press.Google Scholar
Evans, J. (1977). Aristotle’s Concept of Dialectic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Everson, S. (1991). Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Everson, S. (1997). Aristotle on Perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Falcon, A. (2009). ‘The Scope and Unity of Aristotle’s Investigation of the Soul’, in Van Riel, and Destrée, (2009):167–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ferejohn, M. (1988). ‘Meno’s Paradox and De Re Knowledge in Aristotle’s Theory of Demonstration’. History of Philosophy Quarterly 5:99–117.Google Scholar
Ferejohn, M. (1991). The Origins of Aristotelian Science. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feser, E. (2013). Aristotle on Method and Metaphysics. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frede, D. (1992). ‘The Cognitive Role of Phantasia in Aristotle’, in Nussbaum, and Rorty, (1992):279–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frede, D. (1996). ‘The Philosophical Economy of Plato’s Psychology: Rationality and Common Concepts in the Timaeus’, in Frede, and Stryker, (1996):29–58.Google Scholar
Frede, D. (2012). ‘The Endoxon Mystique: What Endoxa Are and What They Are Not’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 43:184–215.Google Scholar
Frede, D., and Reis, B. (2009). Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frede, D., and Stryker, G. (1996). Rationality in Greek Thought. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frede, M. (1992). ‘On Aristotle’s Conception of the Soul’, in Nussbaum, and Rorty, (1992):93–107.Google Scholar
Frede, M. (2008). ‘Aristotle on Thinking’. Rhizai 5:287–301.Google Scholar
Frede, M., and Charles, D. (2000). Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda: Symposium Aristotelicum. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frede, M., and Long, A. (2011). A Free Will: Origins of the Notion in Ancient Thought. London: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Freeland, C. (1990). ‘Scientific Explanation and Empirical Data in Aristotle’s Meteorology’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 8:67–102.Google Scholar
Furley, D. (1967). Two Studies in the Greek Atomists. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Furley, D. (1994). ‘Self Movers’, in Gill, (1994):3–14.Google Scholar
Gelber, J. (2010). ‘Form and Inheritance in Aristotle’s Embryology’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 39:183–212.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. (2004). ‘The Unity of Intellect in Aristotle’s De Anima. Phronesis 49:348–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gill, M. (1994). Self-Motion: From Aristotle to Newton. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gill, M., and Pellegrin, P. (2006). A Companion to Ancient Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldin, O. (1996). Explaining an Eclipse: Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics 2.1–10. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gomperz, H. (1932). ‘ΑΣΩΜΑΤΟΣ’. Hermes 67:155–67.Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. (1985). Aristotle on Nature and Living Things: Philosophical and Historical Studies. Pittsburgh, PA: Mathesis Publications Inc.Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. (1989). ‘Teleology and Spontaneous Generation in Aristotle: A Discussion’. Apeiron 22:181–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gotthelf, A., and Lennox, J. (1987). Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gottschalk, H. (1971). ‘Soul as Attunement’. Phronesis 16:179–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Graham, D. (2004). ‘Was Anaxagoras a Reductionist?’. Ancient Philosophy 24:1–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Granger, H. (1995a). ‘Aristotle on the Subjecthood of Form.’ Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 13:135–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Granger, H. (1995b) ‘The Subjecthood of Form: A Reply to Shields.’ Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 13:177–85.Google Scholar
Gregoric, P. (2007). Aristotle on the Common Sense. Oxford Aristotle Studies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guthrie, W. (1957). ‘Aristotle as Historian’. Journal of Hellenic Studies 77:35–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guthrie, W. (19621981). A History of Greek Philosophy, 6 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hamlyn, D. (1976). ‘Aristotelian Epagoge’. Phronesis 21:167–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hankinson, R. (1998). Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Heinaman, R. (1990). ‘Aristotle and the Mind–Body Problem’. Phronesis 35:83–102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heinaman, R. (2007). ‘Actuality, Potentiality and De Anima II.5’. Phronesis 52:139–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardie, W. (1968). ‘Aristotle and the Freewill Problem’. Philosophy 43:274–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haslanger, S. (1994). ‘Parts, Compounds, and Substantial Unity’, in Scaltsas, Charles, and Gill (1994):129–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heidel, W. (1906). ‘Qualitative Change in Pre-Socratic Philosophy’. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 19:333–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heidel, W. (1913). ‘On Certain Fragments of the Pre-Socratics: Critical Notes and Elucidations’. Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences 48:681–734.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horky, P. (2013). ‘Theophrastus on Platonic and “Pythagorean” Imitation’. Classical Quarterly 63:686–712.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huby, P. (1967). ‘The First Discovery of the Freewill Problem’. Philosophy 42:353–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hülsz, E. (2009). Nuevos ensayos sobre Heráclito. Actas del Segundo Symposium Heracliteum. Ciudad de México: Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México.Google Scholar
Hussey, E. (1972). The Pre-Socratics. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Hussey, E. (1991). ‘Aristotle’s Mathematical Physics: A Reconstruction’, in Judson, (1991):213–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hussey, E. (2006). ‘Parmenides on Thinking’, in King, (2006):13–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hussey, E. (2012). ‘Aristotle on Earlier Natural Science’, in Shields, (2012):17–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ierodiakonou, K. (2005). ‘Empedocles on Colour and Colour Vision’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 29:1–37.Google Scholar
Ilievski, P. (1993). ‘The Origin and Semantic Development of the Term Harmony’. Illinois Classical Studies 18:19–29.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. (1987). ‘Ways to First Principles: Aristotle’s Methods of Discovery’. Philosophical Topics 15:109–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Irwin, T. (1988). Aristotle’s First Principles. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Jaeger, W. (1934). Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of His Development, trans. Robinson, R.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Johansen, T. (1997). Aristotle on the Sense-Organs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johansen, T. (2008). ‘Soul as an Inner Principle of Change: The Basis of Aristotle’s Psychological Naturalism’, in Scott, (2008):276–300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johansen, T. (2012). The Powers of Aristotle’s Soul. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, M. (2009). ‘Spontaneity, Democritean Causality, and Freedom’. Elenchos 30:5–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, M. (2014). ‘Changing Our Minds: Democritus on What Is Up to Us’, in Destrée, Salles and Zingano, (2014):1–17.Google Scholar
Judson, L. (1991). Aristotle’s Physics: A Collection of Essays. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Judson, L. (2005). ‘Aristotelian Teleology’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 29:341–66.Google Scholar
Judson, L. (2018). ‘Physics I.5’, in Quarantotto, (2018):130–53.Google Scholar
Kahn, C. (1960). ‘Religion and Natural Philosophy in Empedocles’ Doctrine of the Soul’. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 42:3–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahn, C. (1992). ‘Aristotle on Thinking’, in Nussbaum, and Rorty, (1992):359–80.Google Scholar
Kakkuri-Knuuttila, M. (2005). ‘The Relevance of Dialectic Skills to Philosophical Inquiry in Aristotle’. Rhizai 2:31–74.Google Scholar
Kamtekar, R. (2009). ‘Knowing by Likeness in Empedocles’. Phronesis 54:215–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, I. (1996). Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Pluhar, W.. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing. [=CPR]Google Scholar
Kelsey, S. (2003). ‘Aristotle’s Definition of Nature’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 25:59–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelsey, S. (2010). ‘Hylomorphism in Aristotle’s Physics’. Ancient Philosophy 30:107–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
King, R. (2006). Common to Body and Soul: Philosophical Approaches to Explaining Living Behavior in Greco-Roman Antiquity. Berlin: Walter de Gryter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kosman, A. (1973). ‘Understanding, Explanation, and Insight in the Posterior Analytics’, in Lee, Mourelatos and Rorty, (1973):374–92.Google Scholar
Kupreeva, I. (2004). ‘Alexander of Aphrodisias on Mixture and Growth’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 27:297–334.Google Scholar
Laks, A. (1993). ‘Mind’s Crisis. On Anaxagoras’ ΝΟΥΣ’. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 31:19–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laks, A. (1999). ‘Soul, Sensation, and Thought’, in Long, (1999):252–3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laks, A., and Rashed, M. (2004). Aristote et le mouvement des animaux. Lille, France: Presses Universitaires Du Septentrion.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Landor, B. (1981). ‘Aristotle on Demonstrating Essence’. Apeiron 19:116–32.Google Scholar
Langton, R. (2000). ‘The Musical, the Magical and the Mathematical Soul’, in Crane, and Patterson, (2000):13–33.Google Scholar
Lee, E., Mourelatos, A., and Rorty, R. (1973). Exegesis and Argument. Assen, the Netherlands: van Gorcum.Google Scholar
Lee, M. (2005). Epistemology after Protagoras: Responses to Relativism in Plato, Aristotle, and Democritus. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leibniz, G. (1989). Philosophical Essays, trans. Ariew, R. and Garber, D.. Indianapolis, IN: Hacket Publishing. [=PE]Google Scholar
Lennox, J. (1982). ‘Teleology, Chance, and Aristotle’s Theory of Spontaneous Generation’. Journal of the History of Philosophy 20:219–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. (2014). ‘Aristotle on the Emergence of Material Complexity: Meteorology IV and Aristotle’s Biology. HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 4:272–305.Google Scholar
Lepore, E., and Van Gulick, R. (1991). John Searle and His Critics. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
Lesher, J. (1995). ‘Mind’s Knowledge and Powers of Control in Anaxagoras DK B12’. Phronesis 40:125–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leunissen, M. (2010a). ‘Aristotle’s Syllogistic Model of Knowledge and the Biological Sciences: Demonstrating Natural Processes’. Apeiron 43:31–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leunissen, M. (2010b). Explanation and Teleology in Aristotle’s Science of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levine, J. (1983). ‘Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Divide’. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64:357–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, F. (1996). ‘Self-knowledge in Aristotle’. Topoi 15:39–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, F. (2003). ‘Is There Room for Anaxagoras in an Aristotelian Theory of Mind?Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 25:89–129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, F., and Bolton, R. (1996). Form, Matter, and Mixture in Aristotle. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
Lloyd, G. (1966). Polarity and Analogy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lloyd, G., and Owen, G. (1978). Aristotle on Mind and the Senses: Proceedings of the Seventh Symposium Aristotelicum. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Long, A. (1966). ‘Thinking and Sense-perception in Empedocles: Mysticism or Materialism?Classical Quarterly 16: 256–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Long, A. (1999). The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lorenz, H. (2007). ‘The Assimilation of Sense to Sense-Object in Aristotle’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 33:179–220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manning, G. (2013). ‘The History of Hylomorphism’. Journal of the History of Ideas 74:173–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (1990). ‘Doxography and Dialectic: The Sitz in Leben of the Placita’, in Haase, W., and Temporini, H. (eds.), 1990, Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt, Teil II: Principat, Band 36.4. Berlin-New York: De Gruyter:3056–229.Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (2007). ‘Out of Touch: Philoponus as a Source for Democritus’, in Brancacci, and Morel, (2007):277–92.Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (2010). ‘Physikai doxai and problêmeta physica in Philosophy and Rhetoric: From Aristotle to Aëtius (and Beyond)’, in Mansfeld, and Runia, (2010):33–97.Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J., and Runia, D. (2010). Aëtiana: The Method and Intellectual Context of a Doxographer. Volume Three. Studies in the Doxographical Traditions of Ancient Philosophy. Leiden, the Netherlands: Brill.Google Scholar
Mansion, S. (1961a). Aristote et les problèmes de méthode. Paris, France: Louvain.Google Scholar
Mansion, S. (1961b). ‘Le role de l’exposé et de la criticism des philosophies antérieures chez Aristote’, in Mansion, (1961):35–56.Google Scholar
Marmodoro, A. (2014). Aristotle on Perceiving Objects. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marmodoro, A. (2017). Everything in Everything: Anaxagoras’s Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, A., and Primavesi, O. (1998). L’Empédocle de Strasbourg: (P. Strasb. gr. Inv. 1665–1666). Berlin: Bibliothèque nationale et universitaire de Strasbourg; Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
McDaniel, K. (2009). ‘Ways of Being’, in Chalmers, , Manley, , and Wasserman, (2009):290–319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKirahan, R. (1983). ‘Aristotelian Epagoge in Prior Analytics 2.21 and Posterior Analytics 1.1’. Journal of the History of Philosophy 21:1–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKirahan, R. (1992). Principles and Proofs: Aristotle’s Theory of Demonstrative Science. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
McPherran, M. (2010). Plato’s Republic: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Menn, S. (1992). ‘Aristotle and Plato on God as Nous and as the Good’. The Review of Metaphysics 45:543–73.Google Scholar
Menn, S. (1995). Plato on God as Nous. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press.Google Scholar
Menn, S. (2002). ‘Aristotle’s Definition of the Soul and the Programme of the De Anima’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 12:83–139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyer, S. (1994). ‘Self-Movement and External Causation’, in Gill, (1994):65–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Jr., F. (1999). ‘Aristotle’s Philosophy of Soul’. The Review of Metaphysics 53:309–37.Google Scholar
Miller, Jr., F. (2012). ‘Aristotle on the Separability of Mind’, in Shields, (2012):306–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Modrak, D. (1991). ‘The Nous-Body Problem in Aristotle’. The Review of Metaphysics 44:755–74.Google Scholar
Morel, P.-M. (1996). Démocrite et la recherché des causes. Paris, France: Klincksieck.Google Scholar
Morison, B. (2002). On Location: Aristotle’s Concept of Place. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morison, B. (2004). ‘Self-motion in Physics VIII’, in Laks, and Rashed, (2004):67–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, S. (1993). Daidalos and the Origins of Greek Art. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Mourelatos, A. (1984). ‘Aristotle’s Rationalist Account of Qualitative Interaction’. Phronesis 29:1–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mourelatos, A. (2005). ‘Intrinsic and Relational Properties of Atoms in the Democritean Ontology’, in Salles, (2005):39–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mourelatos, A. (2006). ‘The Concept of the Universal in Some Later Pre-Platonic Cosmologists’, in Gill, and Pellegrin, (2006):56–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, M. (1982). ‘Saving Aristotle’s Appearances’, in Nussbaum, and Schofield, (1982):267–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, M. (1984). ‘Aristotelian Dualism: Reply to Howard Robinson’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 2:197–207.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M., and Putnam, H. (1992). ‘Changing Aristotle’s Mind’, in Nussbaum, and Rorty, (1992):27–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, M., and Rorty, A. (1992). Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M., and Schofield, M. (1982). Language and Logos: Studies in Ancient Greek Philosophy Presented to G.E.L. Owen. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nuyens, F. (1973). L’évolution de la psychologie d’Aristote. Louvain, Belgium: Éditions de l’Institut supérieure de philosophie.Google Scholar
O’Brien, D. (1969). Empedocles’ Cosmic Cycle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
O’Keefe, T. (2005). Epicurus on Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Osborne, C. (1987a). ‘Empedocles Recycled’. The Classical Quarterly 37:24–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Osborne, C. (1987b). Rethinking Early Greek Philosophy: Hippolytus of Rome and the Presocratics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Osborne, C. (2000). ‘Rummaging in the Recycling Bins of Upper Egypt: A Discussion of Martin and O. Primavesi, L’Empédocle de Strasbourg’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 18:329–56.Google Scholar
Owen, G. (1961). ‘Tithenai ta Phainomena’, in Mansion, (1961):83–103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owen, G. (1968a). Aristotle on Dialectic: The Topics (Proceedings of the Third Symposium Aristotelicum). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Owen, G. (1968b). ‘Dialectic and Eristic in the Treatment of the Forms’, in Owen, (1968):103–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peramatzis, M. (2011). Priority in Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Oxford: University of Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perälä, M. (2018). ‘Aristotle on Perceptual Discrimination’. Phronesis 63:257–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Philip, J. (1966). ‘The “Pythagorean” Theory of the Derivation of Magnitudes’. Phoenix 20:32–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pines, S. (1961). ‘A New Fragment of Xenocrates and Its Implications’. Transactions of the American Philosophical Society 51:3–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polansky, R. (2007). Aristotle’s De Anima. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Politis, V. (2001). ‘Aristotle’s Account of the Intellect as Pure Capacity’. Ancient Philosophy 21:375–402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Preus, A., and Anton, J. (1992). Essays in Greek Philosophy V: Aristotle’s Ontology. New York: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Primavesi, O. (2008). ‘Empedocles: Physical and Mythical Divinity’, in Curd, and Graham, (2008):250–83.Google Scholar
Pritzl, K. (1994). ‘Opinions as Appearances: Endoxa in Aristotle’. Ancient Philosophy 14:41–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Purinton, J. S. (1999). ‘Epicurus on “Free Volition” and the Atomic Swerve’. Phronesis 44:253–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quarantotto, D. (2018a). Aristotle’s Physics Book I: A Systematic Exploration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quarantotto, D. (2018b). ‘The Role, Structure, and Status of Aristotle’s Physics I’, in Quarantto, (2018):1–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rechenauer, G. (2009). ‘Demokrits Seelenmodell und die Prinzipien der atomistischen Physik’, in Frede, and Reis, (2009):111–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reeve, C. (2012). ‘Aristotle’s Philosophical Method’, in Shields, (2012):150–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Renehan, R. (1980). ‘On the Greek Origins of the Concepts Incorporeality and Immateriality’. Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies 21:105–38.Google Scholar
Ryle, G. (2002). The Concept of Mind. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Salles, R. (2005). Metaphysics, Soul, and Ethics in Ancient Thought: Themes from the Work of Richard Sorabji. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scaltsas, T., Charles, D., and Gill, M. (1994). Unity, Identity, and Explanation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schibli, H. (1993). ‘Xenocrates’ Daemons and the Irrational Soul’. Classical Quarterly 43:143–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schofield, M. (1980). An Essay on Anaxagoras. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. (1991a). ‘Explanatory Projects in Physics 2.3 and 7’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy (Supplementary Volume) 9:29–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schofield, M. (1991b). ‘Heraclitus’ Theory of Soul and its Antecedents’, in Everson, (1991):13–34.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. (1992). ‘Aristotle on the Imagination’, in Nussbaum, and Rorty, (1992):249–77.Google Scholar
Scott, D. (2008). Maieusis. Essays in Ancient Philosophy in Honour of Myles Burnyeat. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Searle, J. (1997). The Mystery of Consciousness. New York: The New York Review of Books.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. (1983). ‘Epicurus’ Refutation of Determinism’, in Συζήτησις: studi sull’ epicureismo greco e romano offerti a Marcello Gigante. Napoli, Italy: G. Macchiaroli:11–51.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. (2007). Creationism and its Critics in Antiquity. Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shields, C. (1988a). ‘Soul as Subject in Aristotle’s De Anima’. The Classical Quarterly 38:140–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shields, C. (1988b). ‘Soul and Body in Aristotle’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 6:103–37.Google Scholar
Shields, C. (1995a). ‘Intentionality and Isomorphism in Aristotle’. Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 11:307–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shields, C. (1995b). ‘The Subjecthood of Souls and Other Forms: A Response to Granger’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 13:161–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shields, C. (2002). Order in Multiplicity: Homonymy in the Philosophy of Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shields, C. (2007). ‘The Peculiar Motion of Aristotelian Souls’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 81:139–61.Google Scholar
Shields, C. (2010). ‘Plato’s Divided Soul’, in McPherran, (2010):147–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shields, C. (2012). The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shields, C. (2013). ‘The Phainomenological Method in Aristotle’s Metaphysics’, in Feser, (2013):7–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shorey, P. (1901). ‘Aristotle’s De Anima’. The American Journal of Philology 22:149–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shorey, P. (1960). The Unity of Plato’s Thought. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Sider, D. (2005). The Fragments of Anaxagoras: Edited with an Introduction and Commentary. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag.Google Scholar
Silverman, A. (1989). ‘Color and Color-Perception in Aristotle’s De Anima’. Ancient Philosophy 9:271–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sisko, J. (1999). ‘On Separating the Intellect from the Body: Aristotle’s De anima III.4, 429a10–b5. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 81:249–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sisko, J. (2000). ‘Aristotle’s Nous and the Modern Mind’. Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 16:177–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, R. (1993). ‘Aristotle on the Uses of Dialectic’. Synthese 96:335–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solmsen, F. (1960). Aristotle’s System of the Physical World: A Comparison with His Predecessors. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. (1974). ‘Body and Soul in Aristotle’. Philosophy 49:63–89.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sorabji, R. (1980). Necessity, Cause and Blame: Perspectives on Aristotle’s Theory. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. (1988). Matter, Space, and Motion: Theories in Antiquity and Their Sequel. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. (1992). ‘Intentionality and Physiological Processes: Aristotle’s Theory of Sense Perception’, in Nussbaum, and Rorty, (1992):195–225.Google Scholar
Steel, C., and Primavesi, O. (2012). Aristotle’s Metaphysics Alpha: Symposium Aristotelicum. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tarán, L. (1981). Speusippus of Athens: A Critical Study with a Collection of the Related Texts and Commentaries. Leiden, the Netherlands: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tracy, T. (1982). ‘The Soul/Boatman Analogy in Aristotle’s De anima. Classical Philology 77:97–112.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Trépanier, S. (2014). ‘From Wandering Limbs to Limbless Gods: δαίμων as Substance in Empedocles’. Apeiron 47:172–210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Upton, T. (1985). ‘The Role of Dialectic and Objections in Aristotelian Science’. Southern Journal of Philosophy 22:241–56.Google Scholar
Van Riel, G., and Destrée, P. (2009). Ancient Perspectives on Aristotle’s De anima. Leuven: Leuven University Press.Google Scholar
Viano, C. (1996a). Corps et âme. Sur le De Anima d’Aristote. Paris, France: J. Vrin.Google Scholar
Viano, C. (1996b). ‘La Doxographie du De Anima (I, 2–5) ou le Contre-modèle de l’Âme’, in Viano, (1996).Google Scholar
Vlastos, G. (1945). ‘Ethics and Physics in Democritus’. The Philosophical Review 54:578–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
von Fritz, K. (1943). ‘Νοῦς and Νοεῖν in the Homeric Poems’. Classical Philology 38:79–93.Google Scholar
von Fritz, K. (1945). ‘Νοῦς, Νοεῖν and their Derivatives in Pre-Socratic Philosophy (Excluding Anaxagoras): Part I’. Classical Philology 40:223–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
von Fritz, K. (1946). ‘Νοῦς, Νοεῖν and their Derivatives in Pre-Socratic Philosophy (Excluding Anaxagoras): Part II’. Classical Philology 41:12–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ward, J. (1988). ‘Perception and Λόγος in De Anima II.12’. Ancient Philosophy 8:217–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ward, J. (2008). Aristotle on Homonymy: Dialectic and Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wardy, R. (1990). The Chain of Change: A Study of Aristotle’s Physics VII. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Warren, J. (2007). Presocratics. Stocksfield: Acumen.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waterlow, S. (1998). Nature, Change, and Agency in Aristotle’s Physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weiss, H. (1938). ‘Democritus’ Theory of Cognition: (A Discussion of Two Aristotelian Passages concerning Democritus)’. The Classical Quarterly 32:47–56.Google Scholar
Whiting, J. (1992). ‘Living Bodies’, in Nussbaum, and Rorty, (1992):75–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, J. (2002). ‘Locomotive Soul: The Parts of Soul in Aristotle’s Scientific Works’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 22:141–200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wians, W. (1996). Aristotle’s Philosophical Development: Problems and Prospects. Landham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Wilkes, K. (1979). ‘Conclusions in the Meno’. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 61:143–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilkes, K. (1992). ‘Psuchē versus the Mind’, in Nussbaum, and Rorty, (1992):109–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. (1986). ‘Hylomorphism’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 4:189–99.Google Scholar
Witt, C. (1992). ‘Dialectic, Motion, and Perception: De Anima, Book I’, in Nussbaum, and Rorty, (1992):169–83.Google Scholar
Wlodarczyk, M. (2000). ‘Aristotelian Dialectic and the Discovery of Truth.’ Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 18:153–210.Google Scholar
Wolfsdorf, D. (2008). ‘The Method εξ ὑποθέσεως at Meno 86e1–87d8’. Phronesis 53:35–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Jason W. Carter, University of Edinburgh
  • Book: Aristotle on Earlier Greek Psychology
  • Online publication: 08 March 2019
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108646321.013
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Jason W. Carter, University of Edinburgh
  • Book: Aristotle on Earlier Greek Psychology
  • Online publication: 08 March 2019
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108646321.013
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Jason W. Carter, University of Edinburgh
  • Book: Aristotle on Earlier Greek Psychology
  • Online publication: 08 March 2019
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108646321.013
Available formats
×