Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-25wd4 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T15:07:07.365Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 September 2017

Thomas McNally
Affiliation:
Trinity College, Dublin
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Wittgenstein and the Philosophy of Language
The Legacy of the <I>Philosophical Investigations</I>
, pp. 201 - 206
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2017

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ahmed, A. ed. 2010. Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ahmed, A. 2010. Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. A Reader’s Guide. London & New York: Continuum.Google Scholar
Albritton, R. 1966. “Postscript to ‘On Wittgenstein’s Use of the Term “Criterion”’.” In Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations, edited by Pitcher, G., 247–50. New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G.E.M. 1971. An Introduction to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Augustine, . 1992. Confessions. Translated by H. Chadwick. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Austin, J.L. 1957. ‘A Plea for Excuses.’ Reprinted in Austin’s Collected Papers, edited by Urmson, J.O. & Warnock, G.J., 175204. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Baker, G.P. & Hacker, P.M.S. 1984. Scepticism, Rules and Language. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Baker, G.P. 1985. Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar and Necessity: Volume 2 of An Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Baker, G.P. 2005a. Wittgenstein: Understanding and Meaning. Volume 1 of An Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations. 2nd Edition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Baker, G.P. 2005b. Wittgenstein: Understanding and Meaning. Volume 1 of An Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations. Part II: Exegesis §§1–184. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Baker, G.P. 2009. Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar and Necessity. Volume 2 of An Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations. 2nd Edition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Baker, G.P. 2004. Wittgenstein’s Method: Neglected Aspects. Edited by Morris, K.J.. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bar-On, , D. 1992. ‘On the Possibility of a Solitary Language.’ Nous 26 (1): 2745.Google Scholar
Beaney, M. ed. 1997. The Frege Reader. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Beckerman, A. & Nimtz, C. eds. 2005. Philosophy – Science – Scientific Philosophy. Paderborn: Mentis.Google Scholar
Berger, A. ed. 2011. The Cambridge Companion to Kripke. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Blackburn, S. 1984. ‘The Individual Strikes Back.’ Reprinted in Rule-Following and Meaning, edited by Miller, A. & Wright, C., 2844. Chesham: Acumen.Google Scholar
Boghossian, P. 1989. ‘The Rule-Following Considerations.’ Mind 98: 507–49.Google Scholar
Boghossian, P. 2005. ‘Is Meaning Normative?’ In Philosophy – Science – Scientific Philosophy, edited by Beckerman, A. & Nimtz, C., 205–18. Paderborn: Mentis.Google Scholar
Brandom, , R. 1994. Making It Explicit. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Buckle, S. 2001. Hume’s Enlightenment Tract: The Unity and Purpose of An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Byrne, A. 1996. ‘On Misinterpreting Kripke’s Wittgenstein.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (2): 339–43.Google Scholar
Candlish, S. 1980. ‘The Real Private Language Argument.’ Philosophy 55 (211): 8594.Google Scholar
Canfield, J.V. 1974. ‘Criteria and Rules of Language.’ The Philosophical Review 83 (1): 7087.Google Scholar
Canfield, J. V. 1986. The Philosophy of Wittgenstein: The Private Language Argument. New York & London: Garland Publishing.Google Scholar
Canfield, J. V. 1996. ‘The Community View.’ The Philosophical Review 105 (4): 469–88.Google Scholar
Cavell, S. 1979. The Claim of Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Charles, D. & Child, W. eds. 2001. Wittgensteinian Themes: Essays in Honour of David Pears. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Child, W. 2001. ‘Pears’ Wittgenstein: Rule-Following, Platonism, and Naturalism.’ In Wittgensteinian Themes: Essays in Honour of David Pears, edited by Charles, D. & Child, W., 81114. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Conant, J. & Diamond, C. 2004. ‘On Reading the Tractatus Resolutely: Reply to Meredith Williams & Peter Sullivan.’ In Wittgenstein’s Lasting Significance, edited by Kölbel, M. & Weiss, B., 4699. London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Conant, J. 2006. ‘Wittgenstein’s Later Criticism of the Tractatus.’ In Wittgenstein: The Philosopher and his Works, edited by Pichler, A. & Säätelä, S., 172204. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Conant, J. 2011. ‘Wittgenstein’s Methods.’ In The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein, edited by Kuusela, O. & McGinn, M., 620–45. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J.M. ed. 1997. Plato, Complete Works. Indianapolis & Cambridge: Hackett.Google Scholar
Crary, A. & Read, R. eds. 2000. The New Wittgenstein. London & New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Crary, A. ed. 2007. Wittgenstein and the Moral Life: Essays in Honor of Cora Diamond. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Davies, D. 1998. ‘How Sceptical is Kripke’s “Sceptical Solution”?’ Philosophia 26 (1): 119–40.Google Scholar
Devitt, M. & Sterelny, K. 1999. Language and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language. 2nd Edition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Devitt, M. & Hanley, R. eds. 2006. The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Language. Oxford: BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Dummett, M. 1959. ‘Wittgenstein’s Philosophy of Mathematics.’ The Philosophical Review 68 (3): 324–48.Google Scholar
Ellis, J. & Guevara, D. eds. 2012. Wittgenstein and the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fogelin, , R.J. 1976. Wittgenstein. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Frege, G. 1918. ‘Thought.’ Reprinted in The Frege Reader, edited by Beaney, M., 325–45. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Glock, H.-J. 1996. A Wittgenstein Dictionary. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Glock, H.-J. 2008. ‘Meaning, Rules, and Conventions.’ In Wittgenstein’s Enduring Arguments, edited by Levy, D.K. & Zamuner, E., 156–78. London & New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Glüer, K. & Pagin, P. 1999. ‘Rules of Meaning and Practical Reasoning.’ Synthese 117: 207–27.Google Scholar
Glüer, K. & Wikforss, Å. 2009. ‘Against Content Normativity.’ Mind 118: 3170.Google Scholar
Glüer, K. & Wikforss, Å. 2010. ‘Es braucht die Regel nicht: Wittgenstein on Rules and Meaning.’ In The Later Wittgenstein on Language, edited by Whiting, D., 148–66. New York: Palgrave MacMillan.Google Scholar
Goldfarb, W. 1983. ‘I Want You to Bring Me a Slab: Remarks on the Opening Sections of the Philosophical Investigations.’ Synthese 56 (3): 265–82.Google Scholar
Goldfarb, W. 1985. ‘Kripke on Wittgenstein and Rules.’ Reprinted in Rule-Following and Meaning, edited by Miller, A. & Wright, C., 92108. Chesham: Acumen.Google Scholar
Goldfarb, W. 2012. ‘Rule-Following Revisited.’ In Wittgenstein and the Philosophy of Mind, edited by Ellis, J. & Guevara, D., 7390. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goodman, R.B. 2002. Wittgenstein and William James. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hacker, P.M.S. 1972. Insight and Illusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hacker, P.M.S. 1990. Wittgenstein: Meaning and Mind. Volume 3 of An Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hanna, R. 2010. ‘From Referentialism to Human Action: the Augustinian Theory of Language.’ In Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations: A Critical Guide, edited by Ahmed, A., 1129. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hattiangadi, A. 2006. ‘Is Meaning Normative?’ Mind and Language 21 (2): 220–40.Google Scholar
Hattiangadi, A. 2007. Oughts and Thoughts: Rule Following and the Normativity of Meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hattiangadi, A. 2009. ‘Some More Thoughts on Semantic Oughts: A Reply to Daniel Whiting.’ Analysis 69 (1): 5463.Google Scholar
Haukioja, J. 2004. ‘Is Solitary Rule-Following Possible?Philosophia 32: 125.Google Scholar
Horwich, P. 2005. Reflections on Meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Horwich, P. 2012. Wittgenstein’s Metaphilosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1975a. Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals. 3rd Edition. Edited by Selby-Bigge, L.A.. Revised by Nidditch, P.H.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1975b. A Treatise of Human Nature. 2nd Edition. Edited by Selby-Bigge, L.A.. Revised by Nidditch, P.H.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
James, W. 2007. The Principles of Psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kahane, G., Kanterian, E., & Kuusela, O. eds. 2007. Wittgenstein and His Interpreters. Malden, MA, Oxford & Victoria: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Kenny, A. 1971. ‘The Verificationist Principle and the Private Language Argument.’ Reprinted in The Philosophy of Wittgenstein: The Private Language Argument, edited by Canfield, J.V., 208–33. New York & London: Garland Publishing.Google Scholar
Kenny, A. 2006. Wittgenstein. 2nd Edition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Kölbel, M. & Weiss, B. eds. 2004. Wittgenstein’s Lasting Significance. London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. 1982. Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kusch, M. 2006. A Sceptical Guide to Meaning and Rules. Defending Kripke’s Wittgenstein. Chesham: Acumen.Google Scholar
Kuusela, O. 2008. The Struggle Against Dogmatism: Wittgenstein and the Concept of Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kuusela, O. & McGinn, M. ed. 2011. The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lear, J. 1984. ‘The Disappearing “We”.’ Aristotelian Society 58: 219–42.Google Scholar
Lepore, E. & Smith, B. eds. 2006. The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Levy, D.K. & Zamuner, E. eds. 2008. Wittgenstein’s Enduring Arguments. London & New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Locke, J. 1975. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Edited by Nidditch, P.H.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, W.G. 1971. ‘Noninductive Evidence: Recent Work on Wittgenstein’s “Criteria”.’ American Philosophical Quarterly 8: 109–25.Google Scholar
Lycan, W.G. 2000. Philosophy of Language: A Contemporary Introduction. London & New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Malcolm, N. 1954. ‘Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations.’ The Philosophical Review 63 (4): 530–59.Google Scholar
Malcolm, N. 1986. Nothing is Hidden: Wittgenstein’s Criticism of his Early Thought. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 1984. ‘Wittgenstein on Following a Rule.’ Synthese 58 (3): 325–63.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 1998. Mind, Value, and Reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 2009a. ‘How Not to Read Philosophical Investigations: Brandom’s Wittgenstein.’ In The Engaged Intellect: Philosophical Essays, McDowell, J., 96111. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 2009b. ‘Are Meaning, Understanding, etc., Definite States?’ In The Engaged Intellect: Philosophical Essays, edited by McDowell, J., 7995. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 2009c. The Engaged Intellect: Philosophical Essays. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McGinn, C. 1984. Wittgenstein on Meaning: An Interpretation and Evaluation. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
McNally, T. 2013. ‘Dummett’s Radical Conventionalist Reading of Wittgenstein.’ Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 32 (1): 111–24.Google Scholar
McNally, T. 2016a. ‘Wittgenstein’s Anti-Platonist Argument.’ Philosophical Investigations 39 (3): 281301.Google Scholar
McNally, T. 2016b. ‘More Than a Feeling: Wittgenstein and William James on Love and Other Emotions.’ British Journal of the History of Philosophy 24 (4): 720–41.Google Scholar
Mill, J.S. 1961. A System of Logic. 8th Edition. London: Longmans.Google Scholar
Miller, A. & Wright, C. eds. 2002. Rule-Following and Meaning. Chesham: Acumen.Google Scholar
Miller, A. 2006. ‘Meaning Scepticism.’ In The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Language, edited by Devitt, M. & Hanley, R., 91113. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Miller, A. 2007. Philosophy of Language. 2nd Edition. London & New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Miller, A. 2010. ‘Kripke’s Wittgenstein, Factualism, and Meaning.’ In The Later Wittgenstein on Language, edited by Whiting, D., 167–90. Hampshire & New York: Palgrave MacMillan.Google Scholar
Moore, A.W. 1985. ‘Transcendental Idealism in Wittgenstein, and Theories of Meaning.’ The Philosophical Quarterly 35 (139): 134155.Google Scholar
Moore, A.W. 2007. ‘Wittgenstein and Transcendental Idealism.’ In Wittgenstein and His Interpreters, edited by Kahane, G., Kanterian, E., & Kuusela, O., 174–99. Malden, MA, Oxford & Victoria: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Morris, M. 2007. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mulhall, S. 2009. ‘Hopelessly Strange: Bernard Williams’ Portrait of Wittgenstein as a Transcendental Idealist.’ European Journal of Philosophy 17 (3): 386404.Google Scholar
Pears, D. 1988. The False Prison. Volume 2. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Pitcher, G. ed. 1966. Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations. New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Pichler, A. & Säätelä, S., eds. 2006. Wittgenstein: The Philosopher and his Works. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Reeve, C.D.C. 1997. Plato, Cratylus: Translated with Introduction and Notes. In Plato, Complete Works, edited by Cooper, J.M.. Indianapolis & Cambridge: Hackett.Google Scholar
Rhees, R. 1954. ‘Can there be a Private Language?’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supp. Vol. 28: 6394.Google Scholar
Rundle, B. 1990. Wittgenstein and Contemporary Philosophy of Language. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Russell, B. 1905. ‘On Denoting.’ Mind 14: 479–93.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 1963. Self-Knowledge and Self-Identity. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Schroeder, S. 2006. Wittgenstein: The Way Out of the Fly Bottle. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Searle, J. 1958. ‘Proper Names.’ Mind 67: 166–73.Google Scholar
Soames, S. 1998. ‘Facts, Truth-Conditions, and the Skeptical Solution to the Rule-Following Paradox.’ Philosophical Perspectives 12: 313–48.Google Scholar
Stern, D. 2004. Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stern, D. 2010. ‘Another Strand in the Private Language Argument.’ In Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations: A Critical Guide, edited by Ahmed, A., 178–96. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stern, D. 2011. ‘Private Language.’ In The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein, edited by Kuusela, O. & McGinn, M., 333–50. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stroud, B. 1965. ‘Wittgenstein and Logical Necessity.’ Philosophical Review 74: 504–18.Google Scholar
Thomson, J.J. 1964. ‘Private Languages.’ American Philosophical Quarterly 1: 2031.Google Scholar
Urmson, J.O & Warnock, G.J. eds. 1979. Austin’s Collected Papers, 3rd Edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Whiting, D. 2007. ‘The Normativity of Meaning Defended.’ Analysis 67 (2): 133–40.Google Scholar
Whiting, D. 2010. The Later Wittgenstein on Language. Hampshire & New York: Palgrave MacMillan.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1974. ‘Wittgenstein and Idealism.’ Reprinted in Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973–1980, edited by Williams, B., 144–63. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1981. Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973–1980. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, M. 1999. Wittgenstein, Mind and Meaning: Toward a Social Conception of Mind. London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Williams, M. 2007. ‘Blind Obedience: Rules, Community, and the Individual.’ In Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations: Critical Essays, edited by Williams, M., 6192. Plymouth: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Williams, M. 2007. Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations: Critical Essays. Plymouth: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. 1996. Vagueness. London & New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Wilson, G. 1994. ‘Kripke on Wittgenstein on Normativity.’ Reprinted in Rule-Following and Meaning, edited by Miller, A. & Wright, C., 234–59. Chesham: Acumen.Google Scholar
Wilson, G. 1998. ‘Semantic Realism and Kripke’s Wittgenstein.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (1): 99122.Google Scholar
Wilson, G. 2006. ‘Rule-Following, Meaning and Normativity.’ In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language, edited by Lepore, E. & Smith, B., 151–74. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, G. 2011. ‘On the Skepticism about Rule-Following in Kripke’s Version of Wittgenstein.’ In The Cambridge Companion to Kripke, edited by Berger, A., 253–89. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Witherspoon, E. 2011. ‘Wittgenstein on Criteria and the Problem of Other Minds.’In The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein, edited by Kuusela, O. & McGinn, M., 472–98. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1956. Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics. Edited by von Wright, G.H., Rhees, R., & Anscombe, G.E.M.. Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1958. The Blue and Brown Books. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1974a. Philosophical Grammar, edited by Rhees, R.. Translated by A. Kenny. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1974b. On Certainty. Revised Edition. Edited by Anscombe, G.E.M. & von Wright, G.H.. Translated by D. Paul & G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1975. Philosophical Remarks, edited by Rhees, R.. Translated by R. Hargreaves & R. White. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1979a. Lectures: Cambridge 1932–35. From the Notes of Alice Ambrose and Margaret MacDonald, edited by Ambrose, A.. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1979b. Notebooks 1914–1916. 2nd Edition, edited by von Wright, G.H. & Anscombe, G.E.M.. Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1980a. Lectures: Cambridge 1930–1932. From the Notes of J. King and D. Lee, edited by Lee, D.. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1980b. Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology, Volume I, edited by Anscombe, G.E.M. & von Wright, G.H.. Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1980c. Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology, Volume II, edited by von Wright, G.H. & Nyman, Heikki. Translated by C.G. Luckhardt & M.A.E. Aue. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1981. Zettel. 2nd Edition, edited by Anscombe, G.E.M. & von Wright, G.H.. Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 2001. Philosophical Investigations. 3rd Edition. Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 2005a. Big Typescript, edited and translated by Luckhardt, C.G. & Aue, M.A.E.. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 2005b. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Translated by C.K. Ogden. London & New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Wright, C. 1980. Wittgenstein on the Foundations of Mathematics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, C. 2001. Rails to Infinity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, C. 2007. ‘Rule-Following without Reasons: Wittgenstein’s Quietism and the Constitutive Question.’ Ratio 20 (4): 481502.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Thomas McNally, Trinity College, Dublin
  • Book: Wittgenstein and the Philosophy of Language
  • Online publication: 01 September 2017
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108181976.009
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Thomas McNally, Trinity College, Dublin
  • Book: Wittgenstein and the Philosophy of Language
  • Online publication: 01 September 2017
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108181976.009
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Thomas McNally, Trinity College, Dublin
  • Book: Wittgenstein and the Philosophy of Language
  • Online publication: 01 September 2017
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108181976.009
Available formats
×