Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-sjtt6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-25T21:41:39.206Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 February 2024

Claudine Verheggen
Affiliation:
York University, Toronto
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2024

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ahmed, Arif. 2007. Saul Kripke. Bloomsbury/Continuum.Google Scholar
Ahmed, Arif. 2018. “Review of T. Crane, The Meaning of Belief,” Mind 127 (508): 12611270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alston, William. 2000. Illocutionary Acts and Sentence Meaning. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. 1972. Intention. 2nd ed. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. 1985. “Critical Notice: Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15 (4): 103109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arpaly, Nomy. 2002. “Moral Worth,” Journal of Philosophy 99 (5): 223245.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ayer, A. J. 1936. Language, Truth, and Logic. Victor Gollancz.Google Scholar
Bader, Ralf. In press. “Grounding, Reduction, and Analysis.”Google Scholar
Baker, Gordon P. and Hacker, P. M. S.. 1984. “On Misunderstanding Wittgenstein: Kripke’s Private Language Argument,” Synthese 58 (3): 407450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackburn, Simon. 1984. “The Individual Strikes Back,” Synthese 58 (3): 281301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Block, Irving (ed.). 1981. Perspectives on the Philosophy of Wittgenstein. Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bloor, David. 1997. Wittgenstein, Rules and Institutions. Routledge.Google Scholar
Boghossian, Paul. 1989. “The Rule-Following Considerations,” Mind 98 (392): 507549. Reprinted in Alexander Miller and Crispin Wright, eds., Rule-Following and Meaning (2002). Acumen Publishing: 141–187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boghossian, Paul. 1990. “The Status of Content,” Philosophical Review 99 (2): 157184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boghossian, Paul. 2001. “How Are Objective Epistemic Reasons Possible?,” in Boghossian, Paul, ed., Content and Justification: Philosophical Papers (2008). Oxford University Press: 235266.Google Scholar
Boghossian, Paul. 2008a. Content and Justification: Philosophical Papers. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boghossian, Paul. 2008b. “Is Meaning Normative?,” in Boghossian, Paul, ed., Content and Justification: Philosophical Papers. Oxford University Press: 95108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boghossian, Paul. 2012. “Blind Rule-Following,” in Coliva, Annalisa, ed., Mind, Meaning, and Knowledge: Themes from the Philosophy of Crispin Wright. Oxford University Press: 2748.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boghossian, Paul. 2015. “Is (Determinate) Meaning a Naturalistic Phenomenon?,” in Gross, Steven, Tebben, Nicholas, and Williams, Michael, eds., Meaning without Representation: Essays on Truth, Expression, Normativity and Naturalism. Oxford University Press: 331358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bolker, Ethan. 1966. “Functions Resembling Quotients of Measures,” Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 124 (2): 292312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, Daniel. 2017. “Semantic Non-factualism in Kripke’s Wittgenstein,” Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 5 (9): 113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brandom, Robert. 1994. Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Bridges, Jason. 2014. “Rule-Following Skepticism, Properly So Called,” in Conant, James and Kern, Andrea, eds., Varieties of Skepticism: Essays after Kant, Wittgenstein, and Cavell. De Gruyter: 249288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buleandra, Andrei. 2008. “Normativity and Correctness: A Reply to Hattiangadi,” Acta Analytica 23 (2): 177186.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, Tyler. 1979. “Individualism and the Mental,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4 (1): 73121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, Tyler. 1986. “Intellectual Norms and the Foundations of Mind,” The Journal of Philosophy 83 (12): 697720.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, Tyler. 1996. “Our Entitlement to Self-Knowledge,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 96 (1): 91116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, Tyler. 2013. Cognition through Understanding: Philosophical Essays, Volume 3. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burgess, Alexis and Sherman, Brett. 2014. “Introduction: A Plea for the Metaphysics of Meaning,” in Burgess, Alexis and Sherman, Brett, eds., Metasemantics: New Essays on the Foundations of Meaning. Oxford University Press: 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bykvist, Krister and Hattiangadi, Anandi. 2013. “Belief, Truth and Blindspots,” in Chan, Timothy, ed., The Aim of Belief. Oxford University Press: 100122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, Alexander. 1996. “On Misinterpreting Kripke’s Wittgenstein,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (2): 339343.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Canfield, John. 1996. “The Community View,” The Philosophical Review 105 (4): 469488.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf. 1956. Meaning and Necessity. 2nd ed. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, David. 1996. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, David. 2002. “Does Conceivability Entail Possibility,” in Szabo Gendler, Tamar and Hawthorne, John, eds., Conceivability and Possibility. Oxford University Press: 145200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, David. 2006. “Perception and the Fall from Eden,” in Gendler, Tamar S. and Hawthorne, John, eds., Perceptual Experience. Oxford University Press: 49125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, David. 2009. “The Two-Dimensional Argument against Materialism,” in McLaughlin, Brian P., Beckermann, Ansgar, and Walter, Sven, eds., Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford University Press: 313336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, David. In Press. “Inferentialism, Australian Style,” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association.Google Scholar
Child, William. 2010. “Wittgenstein’s Externalism,” in Whiting, Daniel, ed., The Later Wittgenstein on Language. Palgrave Macmillan: 6380.Google Scholar
Child, William. 2019. “Meaning, Use, and Supervenience,” in Conant, James and Sunday, Sebastian, eds., Wittgenstein on Philosophy, Objectivity, and Meaning. Cambridge University Press: 211230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, Noam. 1965. Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Churchland, Paul. 1981. “Eliminative Materialism and Propositional Attitudes,” Journal of Philosophy 78 (2): 6790.Google Scholar
Coates, Paul. 1997. “Meaning, Mistake and Miscalculation,” Minds and Machines 7: 171197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1973. “Radical Interpretation,” Dialectica 27 (3–4): 313328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1984. Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1985. “A New Basis for Decision Theory,” Theory and Decision 18 (1): 8798.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1986. “A Nice Derangement of Epitaphs,” in LePore, Ernest, ed., Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Blackwell: 433446.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1987. “Knowing One’s Own Mind,” in Davidson, Donald, ed., Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective (2001). Oxford University Press: 1538.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1990. “The Structure and Content of Truth,” The Journal of Philosophy 87 (6): 238279.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1994. “The Social Aspect of Language,” in Davidson, Donald, ed., Truth, Language, and History (2005). Clarendon Press: 109125.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1999. “The Emergence of Thought,” Erkenntnis 51 (1): 717.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 2001a. “Comments on Karlovy Vary Papers,” in Kotatko, Petr, Pagin, Peter, and Segal, Gabriel, eds., Interpreting Davidson. Center for the Study of Language and Information: 285307.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 2001b. “Externalisms,” in Kotatko, Petr, Pagin, Peter, and Segal, Gabriel, eds., Interpreting Davidson. Center for the Study of Language and Information: 116.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 2001c. Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 2001d. “The Second Person,” in Davidson, Donald, ed., Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective. Oxford University Press: 107121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, David. 1998. “How Sceptical Is Kripke’s ‘Sceptical Solution’?,” Philosophia 26 (1): 119140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, Daniel. 1981. The Intentional Stance. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Diamond, Cora. 1989. “Rules: Looking in the Right Place,” in Zephaniah Phillips, Dewi and Winch, Peter, eds., Wittgenstein: Attention to Particulars. St. Martin’s Press: 1234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorr, Cian and Hawthorne, John. 2013. “Naturalness,” in Bennett, Karen and Zimmerman, Dean, eds., Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Volume 8. Oxford University Press: 377.Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred. 1981. Knowledge and the Flow of Information. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dummett, Michael. 1974. “What Is a Theory of Meaning?,” in Guttenplan, Samuel, ed., Mind and Language. Clarendon Press: 97122.Google Scholar
Dummett, Michael. 1976. “What Is a Theory of Meaning? (II),” in Evans, Gareth and McDowell, John, eds., Truth and Meaning: Essays in Semantics. Oxford University Press: 67137.Google Scholar
Dummett, Michael. 1978. Truth and Other Enigmas. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ebbs, Gary. 1997. Rule-Following and Realism. Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ebbs, Gary. 2000. “The Very Idea of Sameness of Extension across Time,” American Philosophical Quarterly 37 (3): 245268.Google Scholar
Ebbs, Gary. 2017. “Rules and Rule-Following,” in Glock, Hans-Johann and Hyman, John, eds., A Companion to Wittgenstein. Wiley-Blackwell: 390406.Google Scholar
Ebbs, Gary. 2022. “Ginsborg’s Reading of Wittgenstein on Rules and Normativity,” Philosophical Investigations 45 (3): 374380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, Gareth. 1982. The Varieties of Reference. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Field, Hartry. 1994. “Deflationist Views of Meaning and Content,” Mind 103 (411): 249285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, Kit. 1994. “Essence and Modality,” Philosophical Perspectives 8 (Logic and Language): 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, Kit. 2002. The Limits of Abstraction. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, Kit. 2015. “Unified Foundations for Essence and Ground,” Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1 (2): 296311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry. 1975. The Language of Thought. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry. 1990a. A Theory of Content. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry. 1990b. “A Theory of Content II,” in Fodor, Jerry, ed., A Theory of Content. MIT Press: 89136.Google Scholar
Fogelin, Robert. 1987. Wittgenstein. Routledge.Google Scholar
Fogelin, Robert. 1996. “Wittgenstein’s Critique of Philosophy,” in Sluga, Hans D. and Stern, David, eds., The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein. Cambridge University Press: 3458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foot, Philippa. 1972. “Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives,” Philosophical Review 81 (3): 305316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frege, Gottlob. 1980. The Foundations of Arithmetic. Translated by J. L. Austin. Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Friedman, Milton. 1966. “The Methodology of Positive Economics,” in Friedman, Milton, ed., Essays in Positive Economics. University of Chicago Press: 347.Google Scholar
Gibbard, Allan. 2003. “Thoughts and Norms,” Philosophical Issues 13 (1): 8398.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, Allan. 2012. Meaning and Normativity. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah. 2010. “Review of A. Hattiangadi Oughts and Thoughts: Skepticism and the Normativity of Meaning,” Mind 119 (476): 11751186.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah. 2011a. “Inside and Outside Language: Stroud’s Nonreductionism about Meaning,” in Bridges, Jason, Kolodny, Niko, and Wong, Wai-Hung, eds., The Possibility of Philosophical Understanding: Reflections on the Thought of Barry Stroud. Oxford University Press: 147181.Google Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah. 2011b. “Primitive Normativity and Skepticism about Rules,” Journal of Philosophy 108 (5): 227254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah. 2012. “Meaning, Understanding and Normativity,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 86 (1): 127146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah. 2018. “Leaps in the Dark: Epistemological Skepticism in Kripke’s Wittgenstein,” in Anthony Bruno, G. and Rutherford, A. C., eds., Skepticism: Historical and Contemporary Inquiries. Routledge: 149166.Google Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah. 2020. “Wittgenstein on Going On,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 50 (1): 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah. 2022. “Going on as One Ought: Kripke and Wittgenstein on the Normativity of Meaning,” Mind and Language 37 (5): 872892.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah. In Press. “Skepticism and Quietism about Meaning and Normativity,” in Boyle, Matthew and Mylonaki, Evgenia, eds., Reason in Nature. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Glock, Hans-Johann. 2005. “The Normativity of Meaning Made Simple,” in Nimtz, Christian and Beckermann, Ansgar, eds., Philosophy – Science – Scientific Philosophy. Mentis: 199241.Google Scholar
Glock, Hans-Johann. 2019. “The Normativity of Meaning Revisited,” in Roughley, Neil and Bayertz, Kurt, eds., The Normative Animal?. Oxford University Press: 295318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glüer, Kathrin. 1999. “Sense and Prescriptivity,” Acta Analytica 14 (23): 111128.Google Scholar
Glüer, Kathrin. 2001. “Dreams and Nightmares: Conventions, Norms, and Meaning in Davidson’s Philosophy of Language,” in Kotatko, Petr, Pagin, Peter, and Segal, George, eds., Interpreting Davidson. Center for the Study of Language and Information: 5374.Google Scholar
Glüer, Kathrin. 2018. “Interpretation and the Interpreter,” in Ball, Derek and Rabern, Brian, eds., The Science of Meaning: Essays on the Metatheory of Natural Language Semantics. Oxford University Press: 226252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glüer, Kathrin and Wikforss, Åsa. 2009. “Against Content Normativity,” Mind 118 (469): 3170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glüer, Kathrin and Wikforss, Åsa. 2018. “The Normativity of Meaning and Content,” in Zalta, Edward N., ed., Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/meaning-normativity.Google Scholar
Goldfarb, Warren. 1983. “I Want You to Bring Me a Slab: Remarks on the Opening Sections of Philosophical Investigations,” Synthese 56 (3): 265282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldfarb, Warren. 1985. “Kripke on Wittgenstein on Rules,” The Journal of Philosophy 82 (9): 471488. Reprinted in Alexander Miller and Cripsin Wright, eds., Rule-Following and Meaning (2002). Acumen Publishing: 92–107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldfarb, Warren. 1997. “Wittgenstein on Fixity of Meaning,” in Tait, William, ed., Early Analytic Philosophy: Frege, Russell, Wittgenstein. Open Court: 7590.Google Scholar
Graham, Peter. 2010. “In Defense of Objectivism about Moral Obligation,” Ethics 121 (1): 88115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, Derek. 2018. “Semantic Knowledge, Semantic Guidance, and Kripke’s Wittgenstein,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 99 (2): 186206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, Derek. 2021. “Rules of Belief and the Normativity of Intentional Content,” Acta Analytica 36 (2): 159169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greenspan, Patricia. 1970. “Conditional Oughts and Hypothetical Imperatives,” Journal of Philosophy 72 (10): 259276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guardo, Andrea. 2022. “Yet Another Victim of Kripkenstein’s Monster: Dispositions, Meaning, and Privilege,” Ergo 8 (55): 857882.Google Scholar
Haase, Matthias. 2009. “The Laws of Thought and the Power of Thinking,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 39 (Suppl 1): 249297.Google Scholar
Haddock, Adrian. 2012. “Meaning, Justification, and ‘Primitive Normativity’,” Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 86 (1): 147174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hale, Bob. 1987. Abstract Objects. Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hale, Bob. 2013. Necessary Beings: An Essay on Ontology, Modality, and the Relations between Them. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hale, Bob and Wright, Crispin. 2001. The Reason’s Proper Study: Essays Towards a Neo-Fregean Philosophy of Mathematics. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hattiangadi, Anandi. 2006. “Is Meaning Normative?,” Mind and Language 21 (2): 220240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hattiangadi, Anandi. 2007. Oughts and Thoughts: Rule-Following and the Normativity of Content. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hattiangadi, Anandi. 2009. “Some More Thoughts on Semantic Oughts: A Reply to Daniel Whiting,” Analysis 69 (1): 5463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hattiangadi, Anandi. 2015. “The Limits of Expressivism,” in Gross, Stephen, Tebben, Nicholas and Williams, Michael, eds., Meaning without Representation. Oxford University Press: 224244.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hattiangadi, Anandi. 2017. “The Normativity of Meaning,” in Hale, Bob, Miller, Alexander, and Wright, Crispin, eds., Companion to Philosophy of the Language, 2nd ed. Wiley: 649669.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hattiangadi, Anandi. 2018a. “Moral Supervenience,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 48 (3–4): 592615.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hattiangadi, Anandi. 2018b. “Normativity and Intentionality,” in Star, Daniel, ed., Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity. Oxford University Press: 10401064.Google Scholar
Hattiangadi, Anandi. 2018c. “The Normativity of meaning and the Hard Problem of Intentionality,” Symposium on Allan Gibbard’s Meaning and Normativity. Inquiry: 61 (7): 742754.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hattiangadi, Anandi. 2020. “Radical Interpretation and the Aggregation Problem,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 101 (2): 283303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hattiangadi, Anandi. 2023. “Logical Conventionalism and the Adoption Problem,” Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 97 (1): 4781.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hattiangadi, Anandi and Orri Stefánsson, H.. 2021. “Radical Interpretation and Decision Theory,” Synthese 199: 64736494. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03078-8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haugeland, John. 1998. “The Intentionality All-Stars,” in Haugeland, John, ed., Having Thought. Harvard University Press: 127170.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, John. 1990. “A Note on ‘Languages and Language’,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 68 (1): 116118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawthorne, John. 2007. “Craziness and Metasemantics,” The Philosophical Review 116 (3): 427440.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hlobil, Ulf. 2015. “Anti-normativism Evaluated,” International Journal of Philosophical Studies 23 (3): 376395.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, Terry and Timmons, Mark. 2006. “Cognitivist Expressivism,” in Horgan, Terry and Timmons, Mark, eds., Metaethics after Moore. Oxford University Press: 255298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hornsby, Jennifer. 2008. “A Disjunctivist Conception of Acting for Reasons,” in Haddock, Adrian and Macpherson, Fiona, eds., Disjunctivism. Oxford University Press: 244261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horwich, Paul. 1984. “Critical Notice: Saul Kripke: Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language,” Philosophy of Science 51 (1): 163171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horwich, Paul. 1990. Truth. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Horwich, Paul. 1995. “Meaning, Use and Truth,” Mind 104 (414): 355368. Reprinted in Alexander Miller and Crispin Wright, eds., Rule-Following and Meaning (2002). Acumen Publishing: 260–273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horwich, Paul. 1998. Meaning. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horwich, Paul. 2010. “Wittgenstein’s Definition of ‘Meaning’ as ‘Use’,” in Whiting, Daniel, ed., The Later Wittgenstein on Language. Palgrave Macmillan: 1725.Google Scholar
Hurka, Thomas. 2014. British Ethical Theorists from Sidgwick to Ewing. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackman, Henry. 2003a, “Charity, Self-Interpretation, and Belief,” Journal of Philosophical Research 28: 145170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackman, Henry. 2003b, “Foundationalism, Coherentism and Rule-Following Skepticism,” International Journal of Philosophical Studies 11 (1): 2541.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackman, Henry. 2005. “Descriptive Atomism and Foundational Holism: Semantics between the Old Testament and the New,” ProtoSociology 21: 519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1982. “Epiphenomenal Qualia,” Philosophical Quarterly 32 (127): 127136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1986. “What Mary Didn’t Know,” Journal of Philosophy 83 (5): 291295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1998. From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defence of Conceptual Analysis. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Janeway, Charles A. Jr. 2001. “How the Immune System Works to Protect the Host from Infection. A Personal View.” PNAS 98 (13): 74617468. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.131202998.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Janssen-Lauret, Frederique and MacBride, Fraser. 2020. “Lewis’s Global Descriptivism and Reference Magnetism,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 98 (1): 192198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, Matthew. 2015. “The Normativity of Meaning: Guidance and Justification,” International Journal of Philosophical Studies 23 (3): 425443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1785. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by Mary Gregor. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kaplan, David. 1989. “Afterthoughts,” in Almog, Josph, Perry, John, and Wettstein, Howard, eds., Themes from Kaplan. Oxford University Press: 565614.Google Scholar
Kearns, Stephen and Magidor, Ofra. 2012. “Semantic Sovereignty,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85 (2): 322350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keefe, Rosanna. 2007. Theories of Vagueness. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Körding, Konrad P. and Wolpert, Daniel M.. 2004. “Bayesian Integration in Sensorimotor Learning,” Nature 427: 244247.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kotatko, Petr, Pagin, Peter, and Segal, Gabriel (eds.). 2001. Interpreting Davidson. Center for the Study of Language and Information.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul. 1972. Naming and Necessity. Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, Saul. 1982. Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language: An Elementary Exposition. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kusch, Martin. 2006. A Sceptical Guide to Meaning and Rules: Defending Kripke’s Wittgenstein. Routledge.Google Scholar
Lance, Mark and O’Leary-Hawthorne, John. 1997. The Grammar of Meaning: Normativity and Semantic Discourse. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leuenberger, Stephan. 2014. “Grounding and Necessity,” Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 57 (2): 151174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lepore, Ernie (ed.). 1986. Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lepore, Ernie and McLaughlin, Brian (eds.). 1985. Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1970. “General Semantics,” Synthese 22 (1/2): 1867.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. 1974. “Radical Interpretation,” Synthese 27 (3/4): 331344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. 1975. “Languages and Language,” in Gunderson, Keith, ed., Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. University of Minnesota Press: 335.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1983. “New Work for a Theory of Universals,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61 (4): 343377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. 1984. “Putnam’s Paradox,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62 (3): 221236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. 1986. On the Plurality of Worlds. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1992. “Meaning without Use: Reply to Hawthorne,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 70 (1): 106110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. 1994. “Reduction of Mind,” in Guttenplan, Samuel, ed., Companion to the Philosophy of Mind. Blackwell: 412431.Google Scholar
Loar, Brian. 2003. “Phenomenal Intentionality as the Basis of Mental Content,” in Hahn, Martin and Ramberg, Bjorn, eds., Reflections and Replies: Essays on the Philosophy of Tyler Burge. MIT Press: 229258.Google Scholar
Lowe, Edward Johnathan. 2012. “What Is the Source of Our Knowledge of Modal Truths?,” Mind 121 (484): 919950.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lycan, William G. 1971. “Noninductive Evidence: Recent Work on Wittgenstein’s ‘Criteria’,” American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (2): 109125.Google Scholar
Lynch, Michael. 2004. True to Life. Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacBride, Fraser. 2003. “Speaking with Shadows: A Study of Neo-Logicism,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54 (1): 103163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mallozzi, Antonella. 2018a. “Putting Modal Metaphysics First,” Synthese 198 (Suppl 8): 19371956.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mallozzi, Antonella. 2018b. “Two Notions of Metaphysical Modality,” Synthese 198 (Suppl 6): 13871408.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mancosu, Paolo. 2016. Abstraction and Infinity. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, John. 1980. “Meaning, Communication, and Knowledge,” in McDowell, John, ed., Meaning, Knowledge, and Reality (1998). Harvard University Press: 2950.Google Scholar
McDowell, John. 1981. “Anti-realism and the Epistemology of Understanding,” in McDowell, John, ed., Meaning, Knowledge, and Reality (1998). Harvard University Press: 314343.Google Scholar
McDowell, John. 1984. “Wittgenstein on Following a Rule,” Synthese 58 (3): 325363. Reprinted in John McDowell, ed., Mind, Value, and Reality (1998). Harvard University Press: 221–262.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, John. 1992. “Meaning and Intentionality in Wittgenstein’s Later Philosophy,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 17: 4052. Reprinted in John McDowell, ed., Mind, Value, and Reality (1998). Harvard University Press: 263–278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, John. 1998a. “Intentionality and Interiority in Wittgenstein,” in McDowell, John, ed., Mind, Value, and Reality. Harvard University Press: 297321.Google Scholar
McDowell, John. 1998b. Meaning, Knowledge, and Reality. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, John. 2009a. Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, John. 2009b. “Wittgensteinian Quietism,” Common Knowledge 15 (3): 365372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, John. 2010. “Are Meaning, Understanding, etc. Definite States?,” in Ahmed, Arif, ed., Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations: A Critical Guide. Cambridge University Press: 162177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGinn, Colin. 1977. “Charity, Interpretation, and Belief,” The Journal of Philosophy 74 (9): 521535.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGinn, Colin. 1984. Wittgenstein on Meaning: An Interpretation and Evaluation. Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
McGinn, Colin. 2002. “Wittgenstein, Kripke and Non-reductionism about Meaning,” in Miller, Alexander and Wright, Crispin, eds., Rule-Following and Meaning. Acumen Publishing: 8191.Google Scholar
McGinn, Marie. 2013. The Routledge Guidebook to Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. 2nd ed. Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McPherson, Tristram. 2018. “Authoritatively Normative Concepts,” Oxford Studies in Metaethics 13: 253277.Google Scholar
Mendelovici, Angela A. 2018. The Phenomenal Basis of Intentionality. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millar, Alan. 2002. “The Normativity of Meaning,” Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 77 (Suppl 51): 5773.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millar, Alan. 2004. Understanding People. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millar, Alan. 2014. “How Meaning Might Be Normative,” in Dutant, Julien, Fassio, Davide, and Meylan, Anne, eds., Liber Amicorum Pascal Engel. University of Geneva: 798817.Google Scholar
Miller, Alexander. 2006. “Meaning Scepticism,” in Devitt, Michael and Hanley, Richard, eds., Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Language. Blackwell: 91113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Alexander. 2010a. “Kripke’s Wittgenstein, Factualism, and Meaning,” in Whiting, Daniel, ed., The Later Wittgenstein on Language. Palgrave Macmillan: 167190.Google Scholar
Miller, Alexander. 2010b. “The Argument from Queerness and the Normativity of Meaning,” in Grajner, Martin and Rami, Dolf, eds., Wahrheit, Bedeutung, Existenz. Ontos: 107124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Alexander. 2012. “Semantic Realism and the Argument from Motivational Internalism,” in Schantz, Richard, ed., Prospects for Meaning. De Gruyter: 345362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Alexander. 2015. “Blind Rule-Following and the ‘Antinomy of Pure Reason’,” The Philosophical Quarterly 65 (260): 396416.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Alexander. 2018. Philosophy of Language. 3rd ed. Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Alexander. 2019. “Rule-Following, Meaning, and Primitive Normativity,” Mind 128 (511): 735760.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Alexander. 2020. “What Is the Sceptical Solution?,” Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 8 (2): 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Alexander and Wright, Crispin (eds.). 2002. Rule-Following and Meaning. Acumen Publishing.Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth. 1990. “Truth-Rules, Hoverflies, and the Kripke-Wittgenstein Paradox,” in Miller, Alexander and Wright, Crispin, eds., Rule-Following and Meaning (2002). Acumen Publishing: 209233.Google Scholar
Montero, Barbara. 2013. “Must Physicalism Imply the Supervenience of the Mental on the Physical?,” Journal of Philosophy 110 (2): 93110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, George Edward. 1954. “Wittgenstein’s Lectures in 1930–1933,” Mind 63 (249): 289316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moran, Alex. 2021. “Living without Microphysical Supervenience,” Philosophical Studies 179 (2): 405428.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moran, Richard. 2001. Authority and Estrangement. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Moyal-Sharrock, Danièle. 2017. “The Myth of the Quietist Wittgenstein,” in Beale, Johnathan and James Kidd, Ian, eds., Wittgenstein and Scientism. Routledge: 152174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Myers, Robert and Verheggen, Claudine. 2016. Donald Davidson’s Triangulation Argument: A Philosophical Inquiry. Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. 1974. “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?,” Philosophical Review 83: 435450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Papineau, David. 1999. “Normativity and Judgement,” Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 73 (1): 1743.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, Derek. 2001. “Rationality and Reasons,” in Egonsson, Dan, Josefsson, Jonas, and Rønnow-Rasmussen, Toni, eds., Exploring Practical Philosophy. Ashgate: 1739.Google Scholar
Parfit, Derek. 2011. On What Matters, Volume I. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Peano, Giuseppe. 1894. Notations De Logique Mathématique. Introduction Au Formulaire De Mathématique. Bocca.Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 1990. “The Reality of Rule-Following,” in Miller, Alexander and Wright, Crispin, eds., Rule-Following and Meaning (2002). Acumen Publishing: 188208.Google Scholar
Pollock, John. 1967. “Criteria and Our Knowledge of the Material World,” Philosophical Review 76 (1): 2860.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Price, Huw, Blackburn, Simon, Brandom, Robert, Horwich, Paul, and Williams, Michael. 2013. Expressivism, Pragmatism and Representationalism. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1975. “The Meaning of ‘Meaning’,” in Putnam, Hilary, ed., Mind, Language and Reality. Philosophical Papers, Volume 2. Cambridge University Press: 215271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1980. “Models and Reality,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 45 (3): 464482. Reprinted in Paul Benacerraf and Hilary Putnam, eds., Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings, 2nd ed. (1983). Cambridge University Press: 421–444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1981. Reason, Truth and History. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1943. “Notes on Existence and Necessity,” Journal of Philosophy 40 (5): 113127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1951. “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” in Quine, W. V., ed., From a Logical Point of View (1953). Harvard University Press: 2046.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. 1960. Word and Object. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Rabinowicz, Wlodek. 2002. “Preference Logic and Radical Interpretation: Kanger Meets Davidson,” in Gärdenfors, Peter ed., 11th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science 2. Springer: 213233.Google Scholar
Reiland, Indrek. 2023a. “Linguistic Mistakes,” Erkenntnis 88 (5): 21912206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reiland, Indrek. 2023b. “Rules of Use,” Mind and Language 38 (2): 566583.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosen, Gideon. 2020. “What Is Normative Necessity?,” in Dumitru, Mircea, ed., Metaphysics, Meaning, and Modality: Themes from Kit Fine. Oxford University Press: 205233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, David. 1930. The Right and the Good. Edited by Stratton-Lake, Philip. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand. 1903. The Principles of Mathematics. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schiffer, Stephen. 1986. “Kripkenstein Meets the Remnants of Meaning,” Philosophical Studies 49 (2): 147162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, Mark. 2008. “Expression for Expressivists,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (1): 86116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, Mark. 2009. “Means-End Coherence, Stringency, and Subjective Reasons,” Philosophical Studies 143 (2): 223248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, Mark. 2018. “Believing Well,” in McHugh, Conor, Way, Jonathan, and Whiting, Daniel, eds., Metaepistemology. Oxford University Press: 196212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwarz, Wolfgang. 2014. “Against Magnetism,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 92 (1): 1736.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, John. 1980. “Minds, Brains, and Programs,” The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3): 417424.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, John. 1992. The Rediscovery of the Mind. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Setiya, Kieran. 2007. “Cognitivism about Instrumental Reasoning,” Ethics 117 (4): 649673.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shaw, James R. 2023. Wittgenstein on Rules: Justification, Grammar, and Agreement. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sider, Theodore. 2009. “Ontological Realism,” in Chalmers, David, Manley, David, and Wasserman, Ryan, eds., Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Oxford University Press: 384423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, Brian. 2010. Signals. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soames, Scott. 1998. “Skepticism about Meaning, Indeterminacy, Normativity, and the Rule-Following Paradox,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supp 23 (Suppl 1): 211250.Google Scholar
Sorensen, Roy. 2001. Vagueness and Contradiction. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sorgiovanni, Ben. 2018. “Rule-Following and Primitive Normativity,” Dialectica 72 (1): 141510.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Speaks, Jeff. 2009. “The Normativity of Content and ‘the Frege Point’,” European Journal of Philosophy 17 (3): 405415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Speaks, Jeff. 2019. “Theories of Meaning,” in Zalta, Edward N., ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2021 ed. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/meaning/Google Scholar
Stalnaker, Robert. 1997. “Reference and Necessity,” in Hale, Bob and Wright, Crispin, eds., A Companion to the Philosophy of Language. Basil Blackwell: 534554.Google Scholar
Stroud, Barry. 1965. “Wittgenstein and Logical Necessity,” The Philosophical Review 74 (4): 504518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stroud, Barry. 1996. “Mind, Meaning and Practice,” in Sluga, Hans and Stern, David, eds., Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein. Cambridge University Press: 296319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stroud, Barry. 2000. Meaning, Understanding, and Practice: Philosophical Essays. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stroud, Barry. 2012. “Meaning and Understanding,” in Ellis, Jonathan and Guevara, Daniel, eds., Wittgenstein and the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford University Press: 1936.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stroud, Barry. 2017. “Davidson and Wittgenstein on Meaning and Understanding,” in Verheggen, Claudine, ed., Wittgenstein and Davidson on Language, Thought, and Action. Cambridge University Press: 97122.Google Scholar
Sultanescu, Olivia. 2021. “Meaning Scepticism and Primitive Normativity,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 102 (2): 357376.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sultanescu, Olivia. 2023. “Meaning, Rationality, and Guidance.” The Philosophical Quarterly 73 (1): 227247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sultanescu, Olivia and Verheggen, Claudine. 2019. “Davidson’s Answer to Kripke’s Sceptic,” Journal for the History of Analytic Philosophy 7 (2): 828.Google Scholar
Sylvan, Kurt. 2015. “What Apparent Reasons Appear to Be,” Philosophical Studies 172 (3): 587606.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tait, William W. 1986. “Wittgenstein and the ‘Skeptical Paradoxes’,” Journal of Philosophy 83 (9): 475488.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tenenbaum, Joshua B., Kemp, Charles, Griffiths, Thomas L., and Goodman, Noah D.. 2011. “How to Grow a Mind: Statistics, Structure, and Abstraction,” Science 331 (6022): 12791285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thornton, Tim. 1998. Wittgenstein on Thought and Language: The Philosophy of Content. University of Edinburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tracy, Eric V. 2020. “Unfollowed Rules and the Normativity of Content,” Analytic Philosophy 61 (4): 323344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vaidya, Anand J. 2018. “Analytic Essentialist Approaches to the Epistemology of Modality,” in Fred-Rivera, Ivette and Leech, Jessica, eds., Being Necessary: Themes of Ontology and Modality from the Work of Bob Hale. Oxford University Press: 224244.Google Scholar
Vaidya, Anand J. and Wallner, Michael. 2021. “The Epistemology of Modality and the Problem of Modal Epistemic Friction,” Synthese 198 (Suppl 8): 19091935.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Verheggen, Claudine. 2000. “The Meaningfulness of Meaning Questions,” Synthese 123 (2): 195216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Verheggen, Claudine. 2003. “Wittgenstein’s Rule-Following Paradox and the Objectivity of Meaning,” Philosophical Investigations 26 (4): 285310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Verheggen, Claudine. 2006. “How Social Must Language Be?,” Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior 36 (2): 203219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Verheggen, Claudine. 2007. “The Community View Revisited,” Metaphilosophy 38 (5): 612631.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Verheggen, Claudine. 2011. “Semantic Normativity and Naturalism,” Logique et Analyse 54 (216): 553567.Google Scholar
Verheggen, Claudine. 2015. “Towards a New Kind of Semantic Normativity,” International Journal of Philosophical Studies 23 (3): 410424.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Verheggen, Claudine. 2017. “Davidson’s Treatment of Wittgenstein’s Rule-Following Paradox,” in Verheggen, Claudine, ed., Wittgenstein and Davidson on Language, Thought, and Action. Cambridge University Press: 97122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Verheggen, Claudine. 2021. “The Continuity of Davidson’s Thought: Non-reductionism without Quietism,” in Myers, Robert H. and Chin-Mu Yang, Syraya, eds., Donald Davidson on Action, Mind and Value. Springer: 129144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Verheggen, Claudine. 2023. “Linguistic Luck and the Publicness of Language,” in Fairweather, Abrol and Montemayor, Carlos, eds., Linguistic Luck. Oxford University Press: 222–240.Google Scholar
Verheggen, Claudine. In Press. “Semantic Non-reductionism,” in Lepore, Ernest and Stojnic, Una, eds., The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy of Language. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Vogelstein, Eric. 2012. “Subjective Reasons,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 15 (2): 239257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Von Humboldt, Wilhem. 1836. Über die Verschiedenheit des Menschlichen Sprachbaues. 2009 ed., Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wallace, R. Jay. 2006. Normativity and the Will: Selected Essays on Moral Psychology and Practical Reason. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Warren, Jared. 2020. “Killing Kripkenstein’s Monster,” Noûs 54 (2): 257289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Way, Jonathan. 2009. “Two Accounts of the Normativity of Rationality,” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 4 (1): 19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Way, Jonathan. 2010. “Defending the Wide-Scope Approach to Instrumental Reason,” Philosophical Studies 147 (2): 213233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weatherson, Brian. 2003. “What Good Are Counterexamples?,” Philosophical Studies 115 (1): 131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, Daniel. 2007. “The Normativity of Meaning Defended,” Analysis 67 (2): 133140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, Daniel. 2009a. “Is Meaning Fraught with Ought?,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90 (4): 535555.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, Daniel. 2009b. “On Epistemic Conceptions of Meaning: Use, Meaning and Normativity,” European Journal of Philosophy 17 (3): 416434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, Daniel. 2010. “Should I Believe the Truth?,” Dialectica 64 (2): 213224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, Daniel. 2014. “Keep Things in Perspective: Reasons, Rationality, and the A Priori,” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 8 (1): 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, Daniel. 2015. “Review of Allan Gibbard’s Meaning and Normativity,” European Journal of Philosophy 23 (S1): 1418.Google Scholar
Whiting, Daniel. 2016. “What Is the Normativity of Meaning?,” Inquiry 59 (3): 219238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, Daniel. 2017. “Against Second-Order Reasons,” Noûs 51 (2): 398420.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, Daniel. 2021. The Range of Reasons in Ethics and Epistemology. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wikforss, Åsa. 2001. “Semantic Normativity,” Philosophical Studies 102 (2): 203226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 1973. “A Critique of Utilitarianism,” in Smart, J. J. C. and Williams, Bernard, eds., Utilitarianism: For and Against. Cambridge University Press: 77150.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 1981. “Wittgenstein and Idealism,” in Williams, Bernard, ed., Moral Luck. Cambridge University Press: 144163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, J. Robert G. 2007. “Eligibility and Inscrutability,” The Philosophical Review 116 (3): 361399.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, J. Robert G. 2019. The Metaphysics of Representation. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, Meredith. 1999. Wittgenstein, Mind and Meaning: Toward a Social Conception of Mind. Routledge.Google Scholar
Williams, Meredith. 2000. “Wittgenstein and Davidson on the Sociality of Language,” Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 30 (3): 299318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, Timothy. 1996. Vagueness. Routledge.Google Scholar
Williamson, Timothy. 2000. Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, George. 1994. “Kripke on Wittgenstein on Normativity,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 19: 366390. Reprinted in Alexander Miller and Crispin Wright, eds., Rule-Following and Meaning (2002). Acumen Publishing: 234–259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, George. 1998. “Semantic Realism and Kripke’s Wittgenstein,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (1): 99122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, N. L. 1959. “Substance without Substrata,” Review of Metaphysics 12 (4): 521539.Google Scholar
Wiseman, Rachael. 2016. The Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Anscombe’s Intention. Routledge.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1953a. Philosophical Investigations. Translated by G. E. M. Anscombe, 3rd ed. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1953b. Philosophical Investigations. Edited by Hacker, P. M. S. and Schulte, J., translated by G. E. M. Anscombe, P. M. S. Hacker and J. Schulte, revised 4th ed. (2009). Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1958. The Blue and Brown Books. Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1974. Philosophical Grammar. Edited by Rhees, Rush, translated by Anthony Kenny. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1977. On Certainty. Edited by Anscombe, G. E. M. and von Wright, G. H., translated by Denis Paul and G. E. M. Anscombe. Wiley Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1978. Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics. Edited by von Wright, G. H., Rhees, Rush, and Anscombe, G. E. M.. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Wodak, Daniel. 2019. “Mere Formalities: Fictional Normativity and Normative Authority,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 49 (6): 828850.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woods, Jack. 2018. “The Authority of Formality,” Oxford Studies in Metaethics 13: 207229.Google Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 1982. “Anti-realist Semantics: The Role of Criteria,” Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 13: 225248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 1983. Frege’s Conception of Numbers as Objects. Aberdeen University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 1984a. “Kripke’s Account of the Argument against Private Language,” Journal of Philosophy 81 (12): 759778. Reprinted in Crispin Wright, ed., Rails to Infinity: Essays on Themes from Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations (2001). Harvard University Press: 91–115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 1984b. “Second Thoughts about Criteria,” Synthese 58: 383405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 1987. “On Making Up One’s Mind: Wittgenstein on Intention,” in Wright, Crispin (ed.), Rails to Infinity (2001). Harvard University Press: 116142.Google Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 1989a. “Critical Notice of Colin McGinn’s Wittgenstein on Meaning,” Mind 98 (390): 289305. Reprinted in Alexander Miller and Crispin Wright, eds., Rule-Following and Meaning (2002). Acumen Publishing: 108–128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 1989b. “Wittgenstein’s Rule-Following Considerations and the Central Project of Theoretical Linguistics,” in Wright, Crispin, ed., Rails to Infinity: Essays on Themes from Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations (2001). Harvard University Press: 170213.Google Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 1992. Truth and Objectivity. Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 2001a. Rails to Infinity: Essays on Themes from Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 2001b. “Rule Following, Meaning and Constructivism,” in Wright, Crispin, ed., Rails to Infinity: Essays on Themes from Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. Harvard University Press: 5380.Google Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 2001c. “Wittgenstein’s Argument as It Struck Kripke,” in Wright, Crispin, ed., Rails to Infinity: Essays on Themes from Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. Harvard University Press: 116142.Google Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 2001d. “Wittgenstein’s Later Philosophy of Mind: Sensation, Privacy and Intention,” in Wright, Crisping, ed., Rails to Infinity: Essays on Themes from Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. Harvard University Press: 291318.Google Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 2007. “Rule-Following without Reasons: Wittgenstein’s Quietism and the Constitutive Question,” Ratio 20 (4): 481502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, Crispin. 2012. “Replies Part I: The Rule-Following Considerations and the Normativity of Meaning,” in Coliva, Annalisa, ed., Mind, Meaning, and Knowledge: Themes from the Philosophy of Crispin Wright. Oxford University Press: 379401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yablo, Stephen. 1993. “Is Conceivability a Guide to Possibility?,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (1): 142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yuille, Alan and Kersten, Daniel. 2006. “Vision as Bayesian Inference: Analysis by Synthesis?,” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 10 (7): 301308.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Zalabardo, José L. 1997. “Kripke’s Normativity Argument,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (4): 467468. Reprinted in Alexander Miller and Crispin Wright, eds., Rule-Following and Meaning (2020). Acumen Publishing: 274–293.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zalabardo, José L. 2009. “One Strand in the Rule-Following Considerations,” Synthese 171 (3): 509519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zalabardo, José L. 2019. “Belief, Desire and the Prediction of Behaviour,” Philosophical Issues 29 (1): 295310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zalabardo, José L. 2023. Pragmatist Semantics: A Use-Based Account of Linguistic Representation. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zalabardo, José L. In Press. “What Is Linguistic Interpretation?,” in Gert, Joshua, ed., Neopragmatism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Zhong, Lei. 2017. “Semantic Normativity and Semantic Causality,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 94 (3): 626645.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zimmerman, Michael. 2008. Living with Uncertainty. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by Claudine Verheggen, York University, Toronto
  • Book: Kripke's <i>Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language</i> at 40
  • Online publication: 22 February 2024
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009099103.015
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by Claudine Verheggen, York University, Toronto
  • Book: Kripke's <i>Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language</i> at 40
  • Online publication: 22 February 2024
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009099103.015
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by Claudine Verheggen, York University, Toronto
  • Book: Kripke's <i>Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language</i> at 40
  • Online publication: 22 February 2024
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009099103.015
Available formats
×