Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-m9pkr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T15:31:44.879Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

War Guilt in the History of Thucydides

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 July 2016

Peter J. Fliess*
Affiliation:
Louisiana State University

Extract

The fact that the question of war guilt has frequently followed in the wake of major wars has contributed little, if anything, to a clarification of the concept. The perplexing difficulties raised by it are amply illustrated by the unsuccessful attempts, made periodically at various ages and on various levels of civilization, to arrive at criteria permitting a differentiation between the bellum justum and the bellum injustum. States, unlike individuals, are not confronted with simple choices between obeying or violating the law. Determination of the initial violation of existing covenants sheds little, if any, light on the responsibility for commencing war. Nor is such responsibility necessarily incurred by launching the first attack. Nothing could be more futile than to equate this act with aggressive and unjust war. The initial attack may be a legitimate response to an existing situation, and a war of aggression, as St. Augustine already pointed out, a just war; nor is there any reason to assume that the party forced into the defensive is invariably innocent. If war guilt is to be more than a specious pretense for inflicting punishment upon the vanquished, it can be measured only in terms of the alternatives available to a state, and the choice has to be viewed in the light of historical, ethical, and political factors. The assessment of such guilt is a problem of extraordinary complexity. To confine it to formal legal considerations would result not only in gross injustice, but would tend to perpetuate international tensions.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Fordham University Press 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 For a differentiation of these concepts see Schmitt, Carl, Der Nomos der Erde im Völkerrecht des Jus Publicum Europaeum (Köln 1950) 248ff.Google Scholar

2 Cf. Wilhelm Roscher, Leben, Werk und Zeitalter des Thukydides (Göttingen 1842) 447.Google Scholar

3 1.118.2-3. Further evidence of the religious element in Spartan thinking was Archidamus’ invocation of the gods as witnesses that he was not the aggressor in the action against Plataea, 2.74.Google Scholar

4 1.125.Google Scholar

5 1.126.1. The qualms of conscience of the Spartans are also revealed in a speech of the Corinthians, 1.123.2.Google Scholar

7 Formally, the war was started by the Peloponnesian confederacy, and the first acts of war were the Theban attack on Plataea, 2.2ff., and the Spartan invasion of Attica, 2.12. In fact, the formal beginning of the war was marked by the Theban attack since only a direct attack on one's own territory created a state of war under Greek international law. Cf. 1.125; also Eduard Meyer, Geschichte des Altertums (2nd ed. Stuttgart, and Berlin, 1915) IV 288.Google Scholar

9 6.105.Google Scholar

10 1.44, 53.4, 144. Cf. Gomme, A. W., A Historical Commentary on Thucydides (Oxford 1945) I 177.Google Scholar

11 1.49.Google Scholar

12 1.145.Google Scholar

13 There existed, to some extent, a sense of a wider, though less binding, society than the Hellenic as reflected in Greek-Persian relations. Cf. Herodotus 1.4; 7.136. Perhaps, too, the mention of κατά τòν πάσι νόμον in 3.56.2 may be interpreted as a reference to universal law transcending Hellenic society. It has been so translated by Crawley, Heilmann, and Horneffer (as revised by Gisela Strasburger, Bremen 1957). Also see Gomme, , op. cit. I 175. However, the sense of a distinct and exclusive Hellenic society is brought out clearly in 1.82.1 and 8.44 as well as in Xenophon's Hellenica 1.6. and 2.1. Nevertheless, the conclusion of treaties with βάρβαροι was a frequent occurrence, see 2.8, 68; 3.34; 6.17, 18, 88; 7.27, 29, 42; 8.28, 31, 37, 56, 57. Xenophon, Hellenica 2.1. But there seems to have been occasional doubt as to the binding force of such treaties. See 8.43.Google Scholar

14 Thucydides’ account is replete with references to νόμοι, κοινά τῶν ‘Ελλήνων νόμιμα, κοινά δίκαια τής ‘Ελλάδος, τά πάτρια. Google Scholar

15 Busolt, Georg, Die Lakedaimonier und ihre Bundesgenossen: Bis zur Begründung der athenischen Seehegemonie (Leipzig 1878) I 143.Google Scholar

16 Cf. Wilhelm Schmid and Otto Staehlin, Geschichte der Griechischen Literatur V 2.2 (Munich 1948) 6970. Gomme, op. cit. I 172-3.Google Scholar

17 This is revealed with particular force in the Melian dialogue 5.84-114. Cf. Erik Wolf, Griechisches Rechtsdenken (Frankfurt a.M. 1956) III 2.118.Google Scholar

18 Ibid. 87.Google Scholar

19 Ibid. 278.Google Scholar

20 1.38; 2.5; 3.11, 39, 56, 65; 7.77.Google Scholar

21 1.40, 44, 45, 53, 67, 68, 79, 87, 118, 146; 4.23; 7.18.Google Scholar

22 1.98-99.Google Scholar

23 1.28, 78; 4.118; 5.18, 31, 79.Google Scholar

24 1.37, 85.Google Scholar

25 This was the bitter fate the Plataeans had to suffer at the hands of the Spartans sitting in judgment over them after their defeat, and causing them to complain (3.53): ‘We have to submit to a trial the result of which is already decided.’ (All quotations from Thucydides are taken from the Crawley translation.) The Melians were subjected to an equally cruel, though less hypocritical, treatment by the Athenians, 5.84-114.Google Scholar

26 1.73.Google Scholar

27 Judicial settlement became even more problematical after the Athenian defeat at Aigospotamoi when Philocles bade Lysander not to play prosecutor where there is no judge. Plutarch, Lysander 13.Google Scholar

28 The unilateral decisions of the Spartan assembly meetings preceding the outbreak of the war that the Athenians had been guilty of sufficient provocations justifying resort to war are a reflection of that state of affairs. See also 1.118.Google Scholar

29 The uncertainty accompanying all wars is well brought out in a speech of Hermocrates 4.62.Google Scholar

30 1.44, 49.Google Scholar

31 1.35. See Gomme, , op. cit. I 169.Google Scholar

32 Cf. Gomme, , op. cit. I 174-5.Google Scholar

33 In preferring their charges the Corinthians complained of a violation of the spirit, rather than the letter, of the treaty, 1.40.Google Scholar

34 1.43.Google Scholar

35 1.40.Google Scholar

36 1.55.2. Thucydides states here that this was the first cause (αἰτία) of the war of the Corinthians against the Athenians without, however, evaluating the respective claims of the two sides.Google Scholar

37 1.66.Google Scholar

38 1.68.Google Scholar

39 1.75.Google Scholar

40 1.77.Google Scholar

41 1.76.Google Scholar

42 1.81.Google Scholar

43 1.85, 145.Google Scholar

44 Cf. Gomme, op. cit. I 447.Google Scholar

45 Cf. ibid. I 227; also Ernst Curtius, Griechische Geschichte (Berlin 1869) II 323-4.Google Scholar

46 Cf. Gomme, op. cit. I, 449.Google Scholar

47 1.145.Google Scholar

48 1.139.Google Scholar

49 1.96. The war of Athens against Naxos to prevent its secession from the confederacy ended in its subjugation. This indicates that a transition from the original hegemony to an imperial relationship had taken place. Thucydides terms this practice, followed later by the subjugation of most of the other allies, a breach of customary law: 1.98.4. However, he is quick to add that the allies had themselves to blame for the Athenian severity toward them; having contributed more than their fair share, the Athenians had acquired, in the process, more power than could be matched by the allies: 1.99. One may indeed be inclined to concede to the Athenians that measure of discipline, including the right to challenge secession, without which their unilateral task of protecting the Aegean Hellenes against the Persians could not be carried out.Google Scholar

50 1.76.Google Scholar

51 Cf. Hermann Bengtson, Griechische Geschichte von den Anfängen bis in die römische Kaiserzeit (Munich 1950) 209.Google Scholar

52 1.23.6, 88, 118-119.Google Scholar

53 Sealey, R., ‘Thucydides, Herodotos, and the Causes of War,’ Classical Quarterly N. S. 7 (1957) 911.Google Scholar

54 Schmid-Staehlin, op. cit. (n. 16 supra) 23.Google Scholar

55 Sealey, op. cit. 10-11.Google Scholar

56 Meyer, Eduard, op. cit. (n. 7 supra) IV 288-93. Similarly Bengtson, op. cit. 208.Google Scholar

57 1.71.4; 4.19; 5.26, 35; 6.10.Google Scholar

58 1.37.4, 86.3; 4.122.Google Scholar

60 Thucydides expresses that conviction in direct statements, 1.23.6, 88, 118. Moreover, he lets it appear repeatedly in speeches, 1.33, 36, 144.Google Scholar

61 1.75.Google Scholar

62 That the actual policy of the Spartans was containment is apparent from their promise to refrain from war if the Megarian decree were repealed. By contrast, the ultimatum to restore independence to all Hellenes cannot seriously be considered the expression of a definite policy. The ultimatum rather expressed the desire to commence war since it had become clear that no other containment of Athenian expansionism was possible.Google Scholar

63 Jaeger, Werner, Paideia: The Ideals of Greek Culture (New York 1945) I 394-5, sheds an interesting light on this point by calling attention to the fact that, in spite of subsequent ratification by the second congress of the plenum of the allies, the decision to go to war was taken by the first congress attended by only a few of the allies. He also remarks that the Spartan decision was not impelled by the allies but was her own motivated by the political situation confronting them.Google Scholar

64 See speech of Sthenelaidas, , 1.86.5; also 1.120.1-2.Google Scholar

65 The Spartan fear was aroused by the sudden realization that most of Hellas was already subject to Athens, 1.87-88.Google Scholar

66 1.118.Google Scholar

67 This was the charge of the Corinthians, 1.124.3.Google Scholar

68 2.61.Google Scholar

69 1.127.3, 140.1, 144.3.Google Scholar

70 1.141.2.Google Scholar

71 Under the unfavorable and frustrating conditions imposed upon Athens by the treaty of 446, the logic of the argument with which the Corcyraeans were trying to lure them into an alliance must have appeared compelling to the Athenians: ‘Remember that there are but three considerable naval powers in Hellas, Athens, Corcyra, and Corinth, and that if you allow two of these three to become one, and Corinth to secure us for herself, you will have to hold the sea against the united fleets of Corcyra and Peloponnese. But if you receive us, you will have our ships to reinforce you in the struggle’ (1.36). — Surely, acceptance or rejection of the alliance no longer seemed a matter of free choice as war appeared imminent.Google Scholar

72 Cf. Alcibiades’ speech to the Athenians, 6.18. The same thought was expressed earlier by Pericles, 2.64.Google Scholar

73 1.75.Google Scholar

74 1.75; 2.63. A similar view is expressed by Lysander after the Athenian defeat at Aigospotamoi, Plutarch, Lysander 22.Google Scholar

75 There can be little doubt that Thucydides’ purpose in injecting the excursus on the Pentekontaetia between the first and the second Peloponnesian congress is to show up the dilemma confronting the two contestants.Google Scholar

76 Diodotus remarks that interest rather than justice governs inter-polity relations, 3.47. In the same vein Hermocrates, 4.60, and the Corcyraean envoys, 1.28.3.Google Scholar

77 3.45.Google Scholar

78 1.24; 3.82.Google Scholar

79 1.24; 2.61; 3.82, 2; 4.62; 5.111; 6.12.Google Scholar

81 1.24.Google Scholar

82 1.78, 80.2, 122, 140.1; 2.11; 3.42; 4.62, 63, 64; 7.61.Google Scholar

83 1.124.2; 2.64; 4.59.2.Google Scholar

84 Cf. Thucydides’ Archeology 1.2-19; also 7.75.Google Scholar

85 1.82.1, 121.5; 5.101; 6.78.Google Scholar

86 1.76; 2.62, 63; 3.45.6; 4.61; 5.105.Google Scholar

87 It is often contended — based primarily on 3.82.8 — that in Thucydides’ view the ultimate driving forces of politics anchored in human nature are greed (πλεονεξία) and ambition (φιλοτιμία). If that were so, any concern with moral questions in the study of Thucydides’ political views would be worse than futile. However, even the casual reader cannot fail to be struck by Thucydides’ deep moral concern in unfolding the course of the Athenian tragedy even though he fails to indulge in explicit moral judgments. No one studying his anthropology can, in fact, remain unaware of the derogatory connotation, attaching to his use of the term πλεονεξία with only one exception. Cf. 3.45.4, 82.8; 4.17.4, 21.2, 41.4, 92.2. The one exception occurs in Hermocrates’ speech, 4.61.5, who finds the πλεονεκτεῖν of the Athenians excusable. The reason for this merciful judgment may lie in the recognition by that wise statesman that in the eighth year of the war the demo-realization of the entire Hellenic world had progressed too far to permit a discussion of politics in moral terms. Although all powerful political structures are driven by a natural tendency to conquer, this phenomenon is not to be explained by πλεονεξία alone. Perhaps more basic is the natural desire to be free and independent. Independence can be assured only through the development and exercise of power over others. However, that power must be used with moderation lest it become ὓβριی (Cf. Erik Wolf, op. cit. [n. 17 supra] III 2.82). Hence, human action based on nothing but πλεονεξία seems to appear to Thucydides as a perversion of human nature and as something to be distinguished from empire (ὓρχἠ ἅΛΛων) pure and simple. Empire, like all rule, involves problems of protection and concern for the welfare of subjects. That Thucydides does, in fact, make such a distinction is suggested by the repeated references to Athens — even by Athenian leaders — as tyrannical (especially in 2.63.2 and 3.37.2), implying that ὰρχἡ is not necessarily or even normally identical with tyrannical rule. The mere grabbing of land and dominion to be exploited for one's own benefit without concern for the welfare of the subjects, that is, tyrannical rule, seems an expression of πλεονεξία, an aberration rather than a universal and irrepressible human trait.Google Scholar

88 An exhaustive treatment of Thucydides’ basic philosophical categories would exceed the scope of this paper. For an excellent treatment see Wolf, Erik, op. cit. especially 57-68.Google Scholar

89 1.78, 140.1; 3.45; 4.12.3, 18, 20, 62, 64; 5.75; 6.23; 7.61.Google Scholar

90 For example Nicias, 6.23, and Hermocrates at Camarina, 6.78.Google Scholar

91 1.71.3; 2.64.3; 5.105; 6.78.Google Scholar

92 1.144.3.Google Scholar

93 Cf. Strasburger, Hermann, ‘Die Entdeckung der politischen Geschichte durch Thucydides, Saeculum 6 (1955) 416.Google Scholar

94 1.23.6.Google Scholar