Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-m8qmq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T04:56:56.625Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Why Interpret? Political Justification and American Constitutionalism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2009

Extract

This article offers a new understanding of political justification and American constitutionalism. Previous scholarship relies on philosophical justifications of constitutionalism which regard the American Constitution as the blueprint of the good society. Such claims fail to explain why persons should interpret a constitution that does not conform to their conception of political justice. Scholars could offer better reasons for interpreting an imperfect constitution if they placed greater emphasis on two other models of political justification. Institutional justifications of constitutionalism regard Constitutions as standard operating procedures for allocating the resources available for achieving the good society. Social justifications of constitutionalism regard constitutions as compromises among people of fundamentally different views. By combining philosophical, institutional and social perspectives, scholars might strengthen the case for constitutional obedience and provide better foundations for a theory of constitutional interpretation.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © University of Notre Dame 1994

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. By comparison, the most prominent thinkers of the first half of the twentieth century, Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., Benjamin Cardozo, Roscoe Pound and Karl Llewellyn, were primarily interested in common or statutory law. See, e.g., Holmes, Oliver Wendell Jr., “The Path of the Law,” Harvard Law Review 10 (1897): 457Google Scholar; Holmes, , The Common Law, ed. by Howe, Mark Dewolfe (Boston: Little, Brown and Company, 1963)Google Scholar; Cardozo, Benjamin N., The Nature of the Judicial Process (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1921)Google Scholar; Llewellyn, Karl N., “A Realistic Jurisprudence—The Next Step,” Columbia Law Review 30 (1930): 431CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Pound, Roscoe, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Law (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1954)Google Scholar; Pound, , “The Scope and Purpose of Sociological Jurisprudence,” 24 Harvard Law Review 24 (1910): 591CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Harvard Law Review 25 (1911): 140, 489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

2. Shapiro, Martin, “Political Jurisprudence, Public Law, and Post Consequentialist Ethics: Comment on Professors Smith and Barber,” Studies in American Political Development: An Annual (Volume 3) (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989), p. 102.Google Scholar

3. Levinson, Sanford, Constitutional Faith (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1988)Google Scholar; Barber, Sotirios A., On What the Constitution Means (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1984).Google Scholar

4. These means of decision-making are not necessarily exclusive. Constitutional exegesis may require recourse to such devices as majority vote, moral philosophy, prayer and astrology, and such texts as the Bible, Plato's Republic, the American Political Science Review and Doonesbury.

5. Tushnet, Mark, Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1988)Google Scholar; Tushnet, , “The Dilemmas of Liberal Constitutionalism,” Ohio State Law Journal 42 (1981): 424–26.Google Scholar

6. Bork, Robert H., The Tempting of America: The Political Seduction of the Law (New York: The Free Press, 1990)Google Scholar; Ackerman, Bruce A., “Robert Bork's Grand Inquisition,” Yale Law Journal 99 (1990): 1419, 1434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7. Virtually every piece of contemporary constitutional theory could be cited for this proposition. The seminal work of this literature is Wechsler, Herbert, “Toward Neutral Principles of Constitutional Law,” Harvard Law Review 73 (1959).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

8. Powell, H. Jefferson, “Constitutional Law as Though the Constitution Mattered,” Duke Law Journal (1986): 925–27Google Scholar; Barber, , On What the Constitution Means, p. 13.Google Scholar

9. Garrison, William Lloyd, “The Great Crisis!” Documents of Upheaval: Selections from William Lloyd Garrison's The Liberator, 1831–1865, ed. Nelson, Truman (New York: Hill and Wang, 1966), pp. 5557.Google Scholar

10. By comparison, Americans who assert “the German Constitution requires/forbids/permits” are more often than not simply making factual assertions.

11. United States v. Butler, 297 U.S. 1 (1936); Jackson, Andrew, Andrew, , “Jackson's Veto of the Bank Bill,” Documents of American History, 2 vols., 7th ed., ed. Commanger, Henry Steele (New York: Appleton—Century—Crofts, 1963).Google Scholar

12. Barber, , On What the Constitution Means, pp. 3962Google Scholar; and Levinson, , Constitutional Faith, p. 91.Google Scholar

13. Many legal scholars do recognize that particular judicial interpretations of the Constitution do not so obligate other governmental officials. See Barber, , On What the Constitution Means, pp. 196220Google Scholar; Murphy, Walter F., “Who Shall Interpret? The Quest for the Ultimate Constitutional Interpreter,” Review of Politics 48 (1986)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Fisher, Louis, Constitutional Dialogues: Interpretation as Political Process (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1988)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Wellington, Harry N., Interpreting the Constitution: The Supreme Court and the Process of Adjudication (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1990), pp. 142–58Google Scholar; Levinson, , Constitutional Faith, pp. 953.Google Scholar

14. Barber, , On What the Constitution Means, pp.185–96Google Scholar; Murphy, Walter F., Fleming, James E., and Harris, William F., American Constitutional Interpretation (Mineola, NY: Foundation Press, Inc., 1986). pp. 11731212.Google Scholar

15. Allison, Graham T., Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis (Boston: Little, Brown and Company, 1971).Google Scholar

16. For similar reasons, one might argue that efforts to explain political behavior generally claim that decision makers have selected the most rational alternative available to them. Models of political explanation differ primarily in the constraints they believe inhibit efforts to choose the most rational means of achieving any particular end.

17. Needless to say, one cost of abandonment is that the parties remaining in the old coalition or community may adopt very unjust policies.

18. Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971)Google Scholar; and Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, Inc., 1974).Google Scholar

19. Bickel, Alexander M., The Morality of Consent (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1975), p. 29.Google Scholar

20. Mcllwain, Charles Howard, Constitutionalism: Ancient and Modern (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1957), p. 3.Google Scholar

21. Sartori, Giovanni, “Constitutionalism: A Preliminary Discussion,” American Political Science Review 58 (1962): 854.Google Scholar

22. Murphy, , Fleming, , and Harris, , Constitutional Interpretation, p. 27.Google Scholar

23. Marshall, John, McCulloch v. Maryland, 4 Wheaton 316 (1819): 415.Google Scholar

24. Dworkin, Ronald, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978), p. 180.Google Scholar

25. Schroeder, Theodore, Free Speech for Radicals (enlarged edition) (New York: The Free Speech League, 1916), p. 94.Google Scholar

26. Smith, Rogers M., Liberalism and American Constitutional Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985), p. 5.Google Scholar

27. Barber, , On What the Constitution Means, p. 57.Google Scholar

28. Fiss, Owai M., “Objectivity and Interpretation,” Stanford Law Review 34 (1982): 763.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

29. Brest, Paul, “The Misconceived Quest for the Original Understanding,” Boston University Law Review 60 (1980): 238.Google Scholar

30. Wolfe, Christopher, The Rise of Modern Judicial Review: From Constitutional Interpretation to Judge-Made Law (New York: Basic Books, Inc., 1986), p. 215.Google Scholar

31. Bork, , Tempting of America, pp. 139-41.Google Scholar As Bruce Ackerman (“Robert Bork's Grand Inquisition”) points out, there is hardly any area of law in which Bork's interpretation of the Constitution fails to support the political preferences of contemporary conservative politicians.

32. Ely, John Hart, Democracy and Distrust: A Theory of Judicial Review (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1980)Google Scholar; Graglia, Lino, “How the Constitution Disappeared,” Commentary 81 (1986): 19.Google Scholar

33. Shapiro, Martin, “Recent Developments in Political Jurisprudence,” Western Political Quarterly 36 (1984): 543.Google Scholar

34. Perry, Michael J., The Constitution, the Courts, and Human Rights (New Haven: Yale University Press,1982), p. 115.Google Scholar

35. Levinson, , Constitutional Faith, p. 192.Google Scholar

36. Cover, Robert M., Justice Accused: Antisalvery and the Judicial Process (New Haven: Yale University Press,1975), p. 257.Google Scholar

37. Jurists of all different schools of constitutional thought routinely accuse their rivals of adhering to the interpretive principles following by Chief Justice Taney in Dred Scott v. Sanford (1857).

38. Murphy, , Fleming, , and Harris, , Constitutional Interpretation, p. 9.Google Scholar

39. Barber, , On What the Constitution Means, pp. 1112.Google Scholar

40. Ibid., p. 12.

41. Walzer, Michael, Radical Principles: Reflections of an Unreconstructed Democrat (New York: Basic Books, Inc., 1980), pp. 128–38Google Scholar; Ackerman, Bruce A., “The Storrs Lectures: Discovering the Constitution,” Yale Law journal 93 (1984): 1032–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

42. Levinson, , Constitutional Faith, pp. 191–92Google Scholar

43. Holmes, Oliver Wendell Jr., Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905) (dissenting opinion), p. 76.Google Scholar

44. Hartz, Louis, The Liberal Tradition in America (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1955)Google Scholar; and Sunstein, Cass R., “Beyond the Republican Revival,” Yale Law Journal 97 (1988): 15661571.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

45. Luker, Kristin, Abortion & the Politics of Motherhood (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984)Google Scholar; and Ginsburg, Faye, Contested Lives: The Abortion Debate in an American Community (Berkeley: University of California Press,1989).Google Scholar

46. Huntington, Samuel P., American Politics: The Promise of Disharmony (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981), pp. 3941).Google Scholar

47. Like it or not, persons who believe that each race should know its proper place are advancing a theory of justice.

48. Murphy, Walter F., Elements of Judicial Strategy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1964)Google Scholar; O'brien, David M., Storm Center: The Supreme Court in American Politics, 2nd ed. (New York: W. W. Norton and Company, 1990)Google Scholar; and Danelski, David J. and Danelski, Jeanne C., “Leadership in the Warren Court,” in American Court Systems: Readings in Judicial Process and Behavior, 2nd ed., ed. Goldman, Sheldo and Sarat, Austin (New York: Longman, 1989).Google Scholar

49. Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.S. 483 (1954); see, Kluger, Richard, Simple Justice: The History of Brown v. Board of Education and Black America's Struggle for Equality (New York: Vintage Books, 1975)Google Scholar; and Ulmer, S. Sidney, “Earl Warren and the Brown Decision,” Journal of Politics 33 (1971).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

50. Mansbridge, Jane J., Why We Lost the ERA (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1986).Google Scholar

51. Robinson, Donald, ed., Reforming American Government: The Bicentennial Papers of the Committee on the Constitutional System (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1985)Google Scholar; Goldwin, Robert A. and Kaufman, Art, eds., Separation of Powers—Does It Still Work? (Washington, D. C.: American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 1986).Google Scholar

52. Neustadt, Richard E., Presidential Power and the Modern Presidents: The Politics of Leadership from Roosevelt to Reagan (New York: The Free Press, 1990).Google Scholar

53. Levinson, , Constitutional Faith, pp. 107111.Google Scholar

54. This is not to deny that one element of a perfect ordering of constitutional values would be that all reasoning creatures would desire to live according to such principles.

55. Dahl, Robert A., A Preface to Democratic Theory (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1956), p. 98.Google Scholar

56. That American society is tolerably just is, of course, a matter which scholars can debate.