Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-fwgfc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-13T22:38:54.787Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Specter of Liberal Egalitarianism - Katrina Forrester: In the Shadow of Justice: Postwar Liberalism and the Remaking of Political Philosophy. (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2019. Pp. 432.)

Review products

Katrina Forrester: In the Shadow of Justice: Postwar Liberalism and the Remaking of Political Philosophy. (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2019. Pp. 432.)

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 July 2022

Jason Frank*
Affiliation:
Cornell University Ithaca, New York, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
A Symposium on Katrina Forrester's In the Shadow of Justice: Postwar Liberalism and the Remaking of Political Philosophy
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the originalwork is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of University of Notre Dame

In the Shadow of Justice explains how a particular approach to political philosophy—“liberal egalitarianism”—emerged in postwar England and the United States, consolidated over four decades as a coherent philosophical paradigm, and ultimately triumphed as a nearly hegemonic conception of political philosophy itself: a vision of how political philosophy “works” and “what it aims to do” (ix). Forrester meticulously attends to the broader political and economic contexts framing the problem spaces of liberal egalitarianism—from postwar antitotalitarianism to the civil rights movement, from global inequality to the market fundamentalism of the rising New Right—while also rigorously reconstructing the internal philosophical debates that animated this paradigm and propelled it forward into ever new areas of “public affairs.” One of the most provocative theses of this brilliant and provocative book proposes that as the political and economic contexts that gave birth to liberal egalitarianism disappeared—especially the postwar conditions of affluence and consensus liberalism—the paradigm itself continued to develop, but now disembedded from the historical conditions that gave it life. This is what Forrester means when she describes the book as a “ghost story”: a story about a theory that lives on and even triumphs as “a spectral presence long after the historical conditions that gave it life have disappeared” (xi).

At the heart of the argument is Rawls's A Theory of Justice (1971), which Forrester describes as an “encyclopedia of postwar Anglophone thought, in which the ideas and techniques that came into prominence in those years—welfare economics, choice theory, game theory, theories of public finance, analytic jurisprudence, ethics, democratic theory, and the history of ideas—were deployed and tamed in the service of grand theory of justice” (106). In returning A Theory of Justice to its postwar context, Forrester dispels several still-prevalent assumptions about that work. One of these is the Rawls and the rebirth of political philosophy narrative. Another is the Great Society story, which reads A Theory of Justice as a retrospective philosophical justification of an expanded New Deal welfare state. On a more philosophically specific level, and focused on the development of Rawls's own thinking, Forrester demonstrates the profound continuities between A Theory of Justice and Political Liberalism (published in 1993), showing that what is often taken to be the more historical and contextual focus of the latter was actually a central concern of Rawls's from the start. Rawls's philosophical trajectory goes from Wittgenstein and Hume to Kant rather than the other way around.

As Forrester situates the development and extensions of Rawls's work in a dynamic and overlapping set of contexts, important continuities within the broader paradigm of liberal egalitarianism come clearly into view, most importantly its unwavering commitment to the idea that, deep down, democratic social life rests on the possibility of consensus and normative agreement. From Rawls's early engagement with Wittgenstein's account of rules and forms of life to his later idea of an overlapping consensus of reasonable comprehensive doctrines, at the heart of his thinking, and of liberal egalitarianism more broadly, was the commitment to a normative consensus underwriting social practices, and the idea that it was the task of political philosophy to bring these latent norms to a principled articulation that could guide constitutional disagreements and adjudicate conflicts over questions of justice. The consensual core of Rawls's theory, Forrester demonstrates, was born from the idealization of midcentury American society as a coherent system of rule-governed practices or games. In developing this argument, Forrester follows critics of Rawls from the Left and Right—from Sheldon Wolin and Charles Mills, say, to Allan Bloom—who identified the ideological commitments animating the project of political liberalism itself, although nobody has demonstrated the source and persistence of these animating ideological commitments with the historical depth and detail found in In the Shadow.

There is so much to admire about this book, and I learned from every chapter and perhaps page. What I admire most is how In the Shadow models a way of doing intellectual history that is simultaneously a work of political theory in its own right. I do not mean only the impressive conceptual rigor of the book, the way it fluently reconstructs the central postwar debates in analytic political philosophy and the broader political contexts that animated them, from Rawls to Ronald Dworkin, from Brian Barry to Charles Beitz, from Thomas Scanlon to Thomas Nagel, and back again. Instead, I also mean the critical interrogation of liberal egalitarianism that hums through every chapter, and the broader questions this critique raises regarding the kind of politics and spheres of political contention enabled by liberal egalitarianism, and those it foreclosed.

Forrester's alternative conception of political theory is largely achieved negatively; it comes into view primarily through her sustained critique of liberal egalitarianism's limitations and blindspots, rather than being developed as a positively articulated counter paradigm. That said, the outlines of a coherent alternative can be reconstructed in the consistency of the critiques Forrester elaborates across the book's eight chapters, which revolve around the forms of political action and conflict precluded or obscured by liberal egalitarianism. In the Shadow points toward a political theory that engages more openly with those precluded dimensions—a political theory focused on group interest and collective action, for example, over reasoned debate and individual choice, one that prioritizes problems of control and legitimacy over legality and distribution, social conflict and crisis over reasonable pluralism and moral justification. Although it is not made wholly explicit, there is a pervasive affinity with the critiques of liberal egalitarianism generated by a more historically situated democratic realism and agonistic radicalism. It would be interesting to have Forrester elaborate on these affinities more explicitly than she is able to do in its epilogue.

At the heart of many of Forrester's critiques is the idea that liberal egalitarianism remains problematically committed to strategies of depoliticization and is insufficiently attentive to questions of history, domination, and power. Liberal egalitarianism consistently converts the political conflicts it confronts at every stage of its intellectual development into juridical problems. The political dilemmas that liberal egalitarianism was best suited to handle, Forrester argues, with its focus on the justice of the basic structure, were preeminently constitutional, which contributed to a legal fetishism in political philosophy. In contrast, Forrester envisions a more political practice of political philosophy. The strategies of depoliticization she finds so prevalent in liberal egalitarianism are rooted in its basic premises and conceptual building blocks, and especially its commitment to the normative consensus animating the rule-based practices structuring social life. They determine how liberal egalitarians frame political conflicts and the philosophical path they set forth for resolving them: questions of economic inequality and injustice are approached ahistorically as questions of distribution and distributive justice rather than ownership and production. Questions of the legitimacy and the scope of political dissent are framed as questions of civil liberties. Investigations of the moral limits of war focus on individual agency rather than collective or corporate agents like the army, the bureaucracy, or the state. And questions of class and racial conflict are construed as reasonable disagreements between comprehensive moral doctrines.

The most powerful example of this broader dynamic is found in Forrester's discussion of Rawls's engagements with the civil rights movement, and his constitutionalization of the problem of civil disobedience. The book's second chapter investigates how the civil disobedience seemingly exemplified by the civil rights struggle of the fifties and sixties, as well as the antiwar movement, were interpreted by liberal egalitarians to make both movements expressive of the very consensus liberalism that was arguably shattered by them. Through Rawls's influence and that of other prominent members of the Society for Ethical and Legal Philosophy (SELF), a particular—and particularly problematic—understanding of the civil rights movement and of civil disobedience took shape, a civil libertarian approach that united the civil rights protester and the antiwar conscientious objector. It is an interpretation that figures legitimate civil disobedience as that which makes an appeal to the shared moral basis of public life. It was “disobedience to law within the limits of fidelity to the law,” as Forrester succinctly describes it (53). This approach to civil disobedience gave philosophical articulation to a romantic understanding of the civil rights movement and contained it within the premises of American exceptionalism; it celebrated the Black freedom struggle as a reconfirmation and extension of the American creed. Forrester provides a lucid account of the principled restrictions placed around legitimate dissent in this chapter, and doing so contributes to a broader reconsideration in contemporary political theory of the more explicitly political and radical dimensions of the civil rights movement and of civil disobedience than those articulated by Rawls and other liberal egalitarians.Footnote 1

In the Shadow ultimately makes a compelling case for getting out from under that shadow. Forrester does not share Rawls's faith that “indigenous liberal traditions provide a reasoned basis for radical criticism of our existing institutions,” nor that “objections raised against present policies by radical critics can be defended on essentially liberal grounds” (126). It may be that the owl of Minerva flies at dusk, and as a constellation of thought comes into clear conceptual focus in the historian's eyes, it has already begun to rigidify and grow cold, hardening as a relic more than a living body of thought. In historicizing a once-hegemonic paradigm of political philosophy, In the Shadow clears a space for thinking that allows us to more clearly delineate alternative paths forward. As postwar liberalism came undone as a political movement—first from the Left and then much more successfully and enduringly from the Right—its preeminent philosophical articulation marched along ghostlike into new arenas of “public affairs.” What is living and what is dead in liberal egalitarianism is an important philosophical and political question for our time, not only for philosophers and political theorists, but for those who seek a more egalitarian and emancipatory politics in a time of political crisis and resurgent authoritarianism. In the Shadow is an intellectual history of postwar philosophical liberalism written amid the ruins of liberalism. As such, it is a provocation to undertake once again the remaking of political philosophy, one more responsive to the full scope of the political crisis of our present.

References

1 See, for example, Pineda, Erin, Seeing Like an Activist: Civil Disobedience and the Civil Rights Movement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2021)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.