Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-pjpqr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-02T05:34:31.341Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Nietzsche, the Muslim Falāsifa, and Leo Strauss's Avicennan Turn

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2024

Abstract

Impressed by Friedrich Nietzsche's critique of liberalism but alarmed by its consequences, Leo Strauss turned in the 1930s to the medieval Islamic philosophers (falāsifa). A review of a key cleavage in their political philosophy—reflected in the contrasting positions of Ibn Rushd and Ibn Sina—identifies the fundamental alternatives Strauss found available to him on the role of religion in politics, and on the necessity and efficacy of political activism more generally. It thus illuminates the trajectory of Strauss's thoughts on the relationship between reason and revelation: from an initial appreciation for the “golden mean” between Nietzsche and liberalism he believed he had found in the writings of al-Farabi and Ibn Rushd, to a more apolitical “Avicennan” stance after his arrival in America. This last, it is suggested, was a contingent stance requiring reconsideration in light of new circumstances in American politics today.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of University of Notre Dame

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I thank Ruth Abbey, the anonymous reviewers, Rob Devigne, and Vickie Sullivan for their helpful comments.

References

1 From his letter to Karl Löwith of June 23, 1935, trans. Tucker, George Elliott, Independent Journal of Philosophy 5/6 (1988): 183Google Scholar. Cited in Lampert, Laurence, Leo Strauss and Nietzsche (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996), 5Google Scholar.

2 Daniel Tanguay, Leo Strauss: An Intellectual Biography, trans. Christopher Nadon (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2007), 53, 68, 79–98; Brague, Rémi, “Athens, Jerusalem, Mecca: Leo Strauss's ‘Muslim’ Understanding of Greek Philosophy,” Poetics Today 19, no. 2 (Summer 1998): 235–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 Strauss, Leo, “Some Remarks on the Political Science of Maimonides and Farabi” (1936), trans. Robert Bartlett, Interpretation 18, no. 1 (Fall 1990): 6Google Scholar.

4 Ranieri, John, “Leo Strauss on Jerusalem and Athens: A Girardian Analysis,” Shofar 22, no. 2 (Winter 2004): 101Google Scholar; Batnitzky, Leora, “Leo Strauss and the ‘Theologico-Political Predicament,’” in The Cambridge Companion to Leo Strauss, ed. Smith, Steven B. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), 51Google Scholar; Zuckert, Catherine H., Postmodern Platos: Nietzsche, Heidegger, Gadamer, Strauss, Derrida (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996), 111–12Google Scholar.

5 Leo Strauss, letter to Karl Löwith, August 15, 1946, cited in Meier, Heinrich, Leo Strauss and the Theologico-Political Problem, trans. Brainard, Marcus (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), 29Google Scholar.

6 Strauss, Leo, “Liberal Education and Responsibility” (1962), in Liberalism Ancient and Modern (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995), 24Google Scholar. See Bloom, Allan, “Leo Strauss: September 20, 1899 – October 18, 1973,” Political Theory 2, no. 4 (November 1974): 374CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Pangle, Thomas L., Leo Strauss: An Introduction to His Thought and Intellectual Legacy (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2006), 75, 82CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Susan Shell, “‘To Spare the Vanquished and Crush the Arrogant’: Leo Strauss's Lecture on ‘German Nihilism,’” in Cambridge Companion to Strauss, 191.

7 Bloom, “Leo Strauss,” 389; Pangle, Leo Strauss, 46–56; Lenzner, Steven J., “Strauss's Fârâbî, Scholarly Prejudice, and Philosophic Politics,” Perspectives on Political Science 28, no. 4 (Fall 1999): 194–202CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Brague, “Athens, Jerusalem, Mecca,” 239.

9 Peter S. Groff, “Nietzsche and the Falāsifa,” in European/Supra-European: Cultural Encounters in Nietzsche's Philosophy, ed. Marco Brusotti et al. (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2020), 340. For an argument that unremitting hostility to “religious delusion” (169) characterized both Nietzsche's thought and Strauss's reading of the falāsifa, see Joel L. Kraemer, “The Medieval Arabic Enlightenment,” in Cambridge Companion to Strauss, 137–70.

10 Timothy W. Burns, “Strauss on the Religious and Intellectual Situation of the Present,” in Reorientation: Leo Strauss in the 1930s, ed. Martin D. Yaffe and Richard S. Ruderman (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2014), 79–113.

11 Friedrich Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Vintage Books, 1989), §4.

12 Friedrich Nietzsche, The Genealogy of Morals, in The Birth of Tragedy and the Genealogy of Morals, trans. Francis Golffing (New York: Doubleday Anchor Books, 1956), 2.23; Beyond Good and Evil, §61. For an analysis tracing the importance of religion for political reform in both Farabi and Nietzsche back to Plato, see Groff, Peter S., “Wisdom and Violence: The Legacy of Platonic Political Philosophy in Al-Farabi and Nietzsche,” in Comparative Philosophy in Times of Terror, ed. Allen, Douglas (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2006), 72Google Scholar.

13 Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, §62. Whenever Nietzsche is quoted, all emphases are in the translated originals.

14 Friedrich Nietzsche, The Antichrist, in The Portable Nietzsche, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Penguin Books, 1976), §29. The few English-language studies of contemporary liberal Islamic responses to Nietzsche tend to neglect those aspects of religion he found so appealing. See, e.g., Roy Jackson, Nietzsche and Islam (London: Routledge, 2007).

15 Almond, Ian, “Nietzsche's Peace with Islam: My Enemy's Enemy Is My Friend,” German Life and Letters 56, no. 1 (Jan. 2003): 51, 55CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

16 Nietzsche, Antichrist, §59.

17 Friedrich Nietzsche, The Will to Power, trans. Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale (New York: Vintage Books, 1968), §952.

18 Nietzsche, Antichrist, §43.

19 Ibid., §22.

20 Nietzsche, Friedrich, Daybreak: Thoughts on the Prejudices of Morality, trans. Hollingdale, R. J. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1997), §496Google Scholar.

21 Nietzsche, Antichrist, §60.

22 Ibid., §21.

23 Leo Strauss to Karl Löwith, May 19, 1933, trans. Scott Horton, https://balkin.blogspot.com/2006/07/letter_16.html. The “shabby abomination” seems to refer to Nazism.

24 Strauss, Leo, “German Nihilism,” ed. David Janssens and Daniel Tanguay, Interpretation 26, no. 3 (Spring 1999): 360Google Scholar. This was a lecture delivered in New York on February 26, 1941.

25 Ibid., 359.

26 Ibid., 371.

27 Strauss, Leo, What Is Political Philosophy? and Other Studies (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1959), 5455Google Scholar.

28 Richard L. Velkley, ed., Leo Strauss on Nietzsche's “Thus Spoke Zarathustra” (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2017), 68. Lampert, Leo Strauss and Nietzsche, 7–10, criticized Strauss's published excoriation as an “irresponsible” (9) attack masking a more sympathetic understanding of Nietzsche.

29 Leo Strauss, “Note on the Plan of Nietzsche's Beyond Good and Evil” (1973), in Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy, with introduction by Thomas L. Pangle (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1986), 181.

30 Ibid., 176. On Nietzsche's need for “the language of religious mythology” for his own philosophical project, as Strauss read it, see Pippin, Robert B., “Leo Strauss's Nietzsche,” in Interanimations: Receiving Modern German Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2015), 208CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

31 Leo Strauss, “The Law of Reason in the Kuzari” (1943), in Persecution and the Art of Writing (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988), 130.

32 Ibid., 135.

33 Bloom, Allan, “Reply to Hall,” Political Theory 5, no. 3 (August 1977): 319CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

34 Ibid., 329.

35 Pangle, Leo Strauss, 51.

36 Ibid., 47. See also Pangle, introduction to Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy, 8–9, 17–18.

37 Lampert, Leo Strauss and Nietzsche, 59.

38 Ibid., 136–40.

39 Mahdi, Muhsin, Alfarabi and the Foundation of Islamic Political Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2001), 62CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

40 Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, §61.

41 Sina, Ibn, The Metaphysics of “The Healing”: A Parallel English-Arabic Text, trans. Marmura, Michael E. (Provo, UT: Brigham Young University Press, 2005), 366Google Scholar.

42 See Mufti, Malik, The Art of Jihad: Realism in Islamic Political Thought (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2019), 6287Google Scholar, which also reviews the scholarship on Ibn Rushd's critique of Ibn Sina. For the Arabic-language scholarship, see Mufti, Malik, “Ibn Rushd's Political Philosophy in Contemporary Arab Scholarship: A Transient Revival?,” Journal of Islamic and Muslim Studies 2, no. 1 (May 2017): 17–35Google Scholar.

43 Ibn Rushd, Averroes on Aristotle's “Metaphysics”: An Annotated Translation of the So-Called “Epitome, ed. Rüdiger Arnzen (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2010), 172.

44 Ibn Rushd, Middle Commentary on Aristotle's “De Anima, trans. Alfred L. Ivry (Provo, UT: Brigham Young University Press, 2002), 116; Ibn Rushd, Long Commentary on the “De Anima” of Aristotle, trans. Richard C. Taylor (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2009), 351–52.

45 Ibn Rushd, Averroes’ Tahafut al-Tahafut, trans. Simon Van Den Bergh (Cambridge: Gibb Memorial Trust, 1987), discussion 10, section 421 (254). See also Ibn Rushd, Averroes’ De Substantia Orbis, trans. Arthur Hyman (Cambridge: Medieval Academy Books, 1986), 131; Carlos Steel and Guy Guldentops, “An Unknown Treatise of Averroes against the Avicennians on the First Cause,” Recherches de théologie et philosophie médiévales 64, no. 1 (1997): 99; Gutas, Dimitri, Avicenna and the Aristotelian Tradition: Introduction to Reading Avicenna's Philosophical Works (Leiden: Brill, 1988), 118–19CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Mufti, Art of Jihad, 70–72.

46 Ibn Rushd, Tahafut 3.246 (146).

47 Ibn Rushd, Long Commentary on the “De Anima, 346. On Ibn Rushd's view of Ibn Sina's political shortcomings, see Mufti, Art of Jihad, 73–74.

48 Farabi, The Attainment of Happiness, §54, in Alfarabi's Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, trans. Muhsin Mahdi (Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1962), 43.

49 Ibn Rushd, Tahafut 4.581–82 (359–60).

50 Ibn Rushd, Decisive Treatise and Epistle Dedicatory, trans. Charles E. Butterworth (Provo, UT: Brigham Young University Press, 2001), 6.

51 Ibn Rushd, Talkhis al-Khataba, ed. Muhammad Salim Salem (Cairo: Dar al-Tahrir li-l-Tabʿ wa-l-Nashr, 1967), 137–38. Passages translated by Charles E. Butterworth, “The Political Teaching of Averroes,” Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 2 (1992): 189–90.

52 Ibn Rushd, Talkhis al-Khataba, 138. For my explication of Ibn Rushd's regime of good dominion, see Mufti, Art of Jihad, 78–81.

53 Ibn Rushd, Averroes on Plato's “Republic, trans. Ralph Lerner (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1974), 127.

54 Ibid., 127–28. See Mufti, Art of Jihad, 81–82.

55 Ibn Rushd, Faith and Reason in Islam: Averroes’ Exposition of Religious Arguments (Al-Kashf ʿan Manahij al-Adilla fi ʿAqa'id al-Milla), trans. Ibrahim Najjar (Oxford: Oneworld, 2001), 77.

56 Ibn Rushd, Decisive Treatise and Epistle Dedicatory, 9.

57 Ibn Rushd, Kashf, 59, 66. On the inadequacies of dogmatic theologians as interpreters of the Law according to Ibn Rushd, see Mufti, Art of Jihad, 75–77.

58 Translation of a passage in Ibn Rushd's Commentary on the “Nicomachean Ethics” by Lawrence V. Berman, review of Averroes’ Commentary on Plato's “Republic” by E. I. J. Rosenthal, Oriens, no. 1 (1969): 439.

59 Ibn Rushd, Averroes on Plato's “Republic, 45–46. On Ibn Rushd's differences with Plato, see Mufti, Art of Jihad, 85–86.

60 Leo Strauss, Spinoza's Critique of Religion, trans. E. M. Sinclair (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1965), 47–48. For a discussion of the differences Strauss saw between Western “Averroism” and the real Ibn Rushd, see Charles E. Butterworth, “What Is Political Averroism?,” in Averroismus in Mittelalter und in der Renaissance, ed. Friedrich Niewöhner and Loris Sturlese (Zurich: Spur Verlag, 1994), 239–50, esp. 247.

61 Strauss, “German Nihilism,” 372 (“of all philosophers . . . nihilism,” Strauss's emphasis), 357 (“clear positive conception”).

62 Ibid., 360.

63 Ibid., 361.

64 Strauss to Löwith, May 19, 1933.

65 Strauss, Leo, “A Giving of Accounts,” The College 22, no. 1 (April 1970): 3Google Scholar. See Heinrich Meier, “How Strauss Became Strauss,” trans. Marcus Brainard, in Enlightening Revolutions: Essays in Honor of Ralph Lerner, ed. Svetozar Minkov (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2006), 367.

66 Leo Strauss, Philosophy and Law: Contributions to the Understanding of Maimonides and His Predecessors, trans. Eve Adler (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1995 [1935]), 69 (“the philosophers,” Strauss's emphasis), 84 (“identical” end).

67 Leo Strauss, draft of unsent letter to Gerhard Krüger (December 25, 1935), trans. Jerome Veith, Anna Schmidt, and Susan M. Shell, in The Strauss-Krüger Correspondence: Returning to Plato through Kant, ed. Susan Meld Shell (Cham: Palgrave Macmillan, 2018), 78–79.

68 That Strauss turned to the Muslim falāsifa owing to his dissatisfaction with Christian Scholasticism is a central theme of Joshua Parens, Leo Strauss and the Recovery of Medieval Political Philosophy (Rochester, NY: University of Rochester Press, 2016). See also Christopher Nadon, “Philosophic Politics and Theology: Strauss's ‘Restatement,’” in Leo Strauss's Defense of the Philosophic Life: Reading “What Is Political Philosophy?, ed. Rafael Major (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2013), 87.

69 Strauss, Philosophy and Law, 128, Strauss's emphases.

70 Strauss, “Some Remarks,” 27n15. For a parallel contrast between the falāsifa and Plato in their emphasis on rhetoric, see also 29n20.

71 Ibid., 6. For Strauss's consideration of Nietzsche on cruelty, see “Note on the Plan of Nietzsche's Beyond Good and Evil,” esp. 185.

72 Leo Strauss, “Course Transcript: Plato's Laws (St. John's College, 1970–1971),” ed. Lorraine Pangle, session 4, 86; available at the website of the Leo Strauss Center, University of Chicago, https://wslamp70.s3.amazonaws.com/leostrauss/s3fs-public/Laws%201971-72.pdf. Plato in this reading thus “compels” (Strauss's emphasis) philosophers to return to the cave and care for others: Leo Strauss, “Cohen and Maimonides” (1931), trans. Martin D. Yaffe and Ian Alexander Moore, in Leo Strauss on Maimonides: The Complete Writings, ed. Kenneth Hart Green (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2013), 218–19.

73 Leo Strauss, “How Fārābī Read Plato's Laws” (1957), in What Is Political Philosophy?, 153. See also Brague, “Athens, Jerusalem, Mecca.”

74 Tanguay, Leo Strauss, 81.

75 Strauss, “Law of Reason in the Kuzari,” 125–26.

76 Ibid., 126n98, 140. See Mufti, Art of Jihad, 72–73.

77 Strauss, “Law of Reason in the Kuzari,” 135.

78 Batnitzky, Leora, Leo Strauss and Emmanuel Levinas: Philosophy and the Politics of Revelation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 211CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

79 Lampert, Leo Strauss and Nietzsche, 140.

80 Ibid., 175n8, quoting Strauss's introduction to Persecution and the Art of Writing (19). While criticizing Strauss's failure to be more outspoken about “the idiocies of revealed religion” (184), Lampert added that “Nietzsche did not oppose religion, a universal and necessary phenomenon; he opposed our religion both sacred and secular” (182, emphasis in original).

81 Strauss, “Law of Reason in the Kuzari,” 136–37.

82 Ibid., 137.

83 Ibid., 139.

84 Leo Strauss, “Farabi's Plato,” in Louis Ginzberg: Jubilee Volume, ed. Saul Lieberman et al. (New York: American Academy for Jewish Research, 1945), 383–84.

85 Ibid., 370.

86 Ibid., 381. See also Strauss's 1952 introduction to Persecution and the Art of Writing, 15–16.

87 Leo Strauss, “Progress or Return?” (1952), in The Rebirth of Classical Political Rationalism: An Introduction to the Thought of Leo Strauss, ed. Thomas L. Pangle (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989), 270.

88 Tanguay, Leo Strauss, 208. See also Batnitzky, Leo Strauss and Emmanuel Levinas, 135.

89 Galston, Miriam, “Realism and Idealism in Avicenna's Political Philosophy,” Review of Politics 41, no. 4 (October 1979): 576–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

90 Zuckert, Michael P. and Zuckert, Catherine H., Leo Strauss and the Problem of Political Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2014), 136, 142CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Indeed, although he cited neither Farabi nor Ibn Rushd in this, his final monograph, Strauss opened it with an epigraph from Ibn Sina: Leo Strauss, The Argument and the Action of Plato's “Laws” (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1975), 1.

91 Leo Strauss, “Reason and Revelation” (1948), in Meier, Leo Strauss and the Theologico-Political Problem, 149.

92 Ibid., 150.

93 Farabi, Kitab al-Huruf, ed. Muhsin Mahdi (Beirut: Dar al-Mashreq, 1970), part 2, 131.

94 Ibid., 155–56.

95 Strauss, “Reason and Revelation,” 177. See also Strauss, “Some Remarks,” 4–5; Brague, “Athens, Jerusalem, Mecca,” 252.

96 Leo Strauss, “Why We Remain Jews: Can Jewish Faith and History Still Speak to Us?” (1962), in Leo Strauss: Political Philosopher and Jewish Thinker, ed. Kenneth L. Deutsch and Walter Nicgorski (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1994), 46–47.

97 Ibid., 49.

98 On Strauss's cautiousness, see George Anastaplo, “Leo Strauss at the University of Chicago,” in Leo Strauss, the Straussians, and the American Regime, ed. Kenneth L. Deutsch and John A. Murley (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1999), 10, 25n10; Seth Benardete's comments in Encounters and Reflections: Conversations with Seth Benardete, ed. Ronna Burger (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002), 36.

99 Strauss, “How Fārābī Read Plato's Laws,” 146.

100 Strauss, “Law of Reason in the Kuzari,” 110.

101 For a range of views relating to this debate see Pangle, introduction to Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy, 11–12; Jaffa, Harry V., “The Legacy of Leo Strauss,” Claremont Review of Books 3, no. 3 (Fall 1984): 14–21Google Scholar; Rosen, Stanley, Hermeneutics as Politics (New York: Oxford University Press, 1987), 107–40Google Scholar; Bartlett, Robert C., The Idea of Enlightenment: A Postmortem Study (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2001), 5463CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Devigne, Robert, “Strauss and ‘Straussianism’: From the Ancients to the Moderns?,” Political Studies 57, no. 3 (October 2009): 592–616CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

102 Mounk, Yascha, The People vs. Democracy: Why Our Freedom Is in Danger and How to Save It (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2018), 105CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

103 Ibid., 5.