Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-mwx4w Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-17T16:46:18.289Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Divided Publius: Democracy, Federalism, and the Cultivation of Public Sentiment

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 October 2007

Abstract

Alexander Hamilton and James Madison agreed in the Federalist that the Constitution authorizes both political and judicial processes to define and safeguard the boundaries of federalism, but disagreed on public opinion's role in a republic and how to cultivate public sentiment for the Constitution. Hamilton preferred resolving intergovernmental disputes via political and public processes because public endorsement would legitimize broad national powers. Madison favored building public sentiment for the Constitution through strict limits on the national government enforced in part by the judiciary. He thought resolving intergovernmental disputes via public processes would confirm widespread suspicions of imperium in imperio and might provoke a popular backlash that would upset the constitutional equilibrium and undermine even legitimate national powers. This difference foreshadows Hamilton and Madison's later constitutional disagreements, reveals fundamental ambiguities in America's federal system, and confirms the need to consider how institutions and policies affect public sentiment for the constitutional order.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © University of Notre Dame 2007

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 The Federalist is criticized as a legitimate source for understanding the founders' thinking on the Constitution for three reasons: 1) Hamilton, Madison, and Jay are only three of the founders; 2) few people read the Federalist when first published and, even then, its impact on the ratification debates was minimal or nonexistent; 3) the Federalist is propaganda not constitutional exegesis, because its purpose was to convince the public to support ratification of the Constitution. Despite the pseudonym of “Publius,” some knew who wrote the Federalist or that the authors were members of the Constitutional Convention, according to Mason, Alpheus Thomas, “The Federalist—A Split Personality,” American Historical Review 57 (1952): 630CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Consequently Hamilton, and Madison had a responsibility to represent the ideas of the convention fairly rather than their own personal biases. Only where ambiguity existed were they free to insert their own opinion. If they had misrepresented the ideas, logic and theory of the Constitutional Convention, then their reputations and credibility would have been tarnished. Also, years after the Constitution's ratification, a number of founders praised the Federalist as an excellent explication of the Constitution, as reported by Dietze, Gottfried, The Federalist: A Classic of Federalism and Free Government (Baltimore: The John Hopkins Press, 1960), 47Google Scholar. Finally, since scholars and justices often cite the Federalist to support their arguments, a thorough study of Publius's understanding of federalism should help to determine whether select quotes are used consistently or inconsistently with Publius's understanding. On this question, see also Banning, Lance, The Sacred Fire of Liberty: James Madison and the Founding of the Federal Republic (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 1995), 396402Google Scholar.

2 Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty, 396.

3 Adair, Douglas, William & Mary Quarterly, 3rd Ser (1944): 97122, 235–64CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Mason, “The Federalist—A Split Personality”; Dietze, The Federalist.

4 Rossiter, Clinton, Alexander Hamilton and the Constitution, (Harcourt, 1964)Google Scholar; Wills, Garry, Explaining America: The Federalist (New York: Doubleday & Company Inc, 1981)Google Scholar; Diamond, Martin, “The Federalist,” in History of Political Philosophy, 3rd ed., ed. Strauss, Leo and Cropsey, Joseph (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1987)Google Scholar; Elkins, Stanley and McKitrick, Eric, The Age of Federalism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993)Google Scholar; Carey, George W., In Defense of the Constitution (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1989)Google Scholar; Sheehan, Colleen A., “Madison v. Hamilton: The Battle over Republicanism and the Role of Public Opinion,” American Political Science Review 98, 3 (2004): 405–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Levy, Jacob T., “Beyond Publius: Montesquieu, Liberal Republicanism, and the Small-Republic Thesis,” History of Political Thought 27, 1 (2006): 50–90Google Scholar.

5 An excellent review of these ideas is Gibson, Alan, “The Madisonian Madison and the Question of Consistency: The Significance and Challenge of Recent Research,” Review of Politics 64, 2 (2002): 311–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar. McCoy, Drew, The Last of the Fathers: James Madison and the Republican Legacy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989)Google Scholar; Zuckert, Michael, “Federalism and the Founding,” Review of Politics (1986): 166210CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Rakove, Jack N., Original Meanings: Politics and Ideas in the Making of the Constitution (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1996)Google Scholar; Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty.

6 Sheehan, “Madison v. Hamilton,” 405–6.

7 This distinction between public opinion and public sentiment, although not obvious, can be found in Madison's writings; see his short brief “Public Opinion, 19 Dec. 1791” in James Madison: Writings (The Library of America, 1999), 500–501.

8 Corwin, Edward S., “The Passing of Dual Federalism,” Virginia Law Review 36 (1950): 1CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Zuckert “Federalism and the Founding”; Rakove, Jack N., “The Origins of Judicial Review: A Plea for New Contexts,” Stanford Law Review 49, 5 (1997): 1031–64CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Scheiber, Harry N., “Federalism and the Constitution: The Original Understanding,” in American Law and the Constitutional Order: Historical Perspectives, ed. Friedman, Lawrence M. and Scheiber, Harry N. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1988), 8598Google Scholar; Derthick, Martha, “Congress, the States, and the Supreme Court,” in Keeping the Compound Republic (Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press, 2001), 6465Google Scholar.

9 Wechsler, Herbert, “The Political Safeguards of Federalism: The Role of the States in the Composition and Selection of the National Government,” Columbia Law Review 54, 4 (1954): 543–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Choper, Jesse H., Judicial Review and the National Political Process: A Functional Reconsideration of the Role of the Supreme Court (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980)Google Scholar; Kramer, Larry D., “Putting the Politics Back into the Political Safeguards of Federalism,” Columbia Law Review 100, 1 (2000): 215–93CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For a good introduction to the political and judicial safeguards theories of federalism and their influence on contemporary government, politics, and policy, see Mitchell J. Pickerill and Clayton, Cornell W., “The Rehnquist Court and the Political Dynamics of Federalism,” Perspectives on Politics 2, 2 (2004): 233–48Google Scholar.

10 All references to the Federalist are from Hamilton, Alexander, Jay, John, and Madison, James, The Federalist Papers, ed. Rossiter, Clinton (New York: Mentor Book, 1999)Google Scholar.

11 Maintaining a viable federalism requires a “culture of federalism”; see Duchacek, Ivo D., Comparative Federalism: The Territorial Dimension of Politics (New York: University Press of America, 1987), 343–44Google Scholar; Livingston, William A., “A Note on the Nature of Federalism,” Political Science Quarterly 67 (1952): 84CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Elazar, Daniel J., Exploring Federalism (Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press, 1987), 192Google Scholar.

12 The Oxford English Dictionary defines magistrate as “A civil officer exercising local judicial power; a justice of the peace, a judge.”

13 Dietze, The Federalist, 260–64, 269, 271; Scheiber, “Federalism and the Constitution,” 91; Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty, 398–99; Rakove, Original Meanings.

14 Calhoun, John C., A Disquisition on Government, ed. Cralle, Richard K. (reprint, New York: Peter Smith, 1853)Google Scholar; McDonald, Forrest, States' Rights and the Union: Imperium in Imperio (Kansas: University Press of Kansas, 2000)Google Scholar.

15 Hamilton refers to states' “pre-existing right of sovereignty” that cannot be alienated or extinguished by implication (no. 32:169).

16 Consistent with the argument of this paper, Karl-Friedrich Walling argues Hamilton “supported a strong, central government not an omnipotent and omnipresent central administration … not unlimited but effective government” where the division between national and state responsibilities is dependent on “time and circumstances,” Republican Empire: Alexander Hamilton on War and Free Government (Kansas: University Press of Kansas, 1999), 170–71.

17 Walling, Republican Empire, 15.

18 Hamilton, Alexander, “An Opinion on the Constitutionality of an Act to Establish a Bank, Feb. 23, 1791,” in The Papers of Alexander Hamilton (New York: Columbia University Press, 1964), 8: 100106Google Scholar.

19 Hamilton, “Letter to Jonathan Dayton, Oct.–Nov. 1799,” Papers, 23:603; McDonald, Forrest, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Kansas: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 265Google Scholar. See also, Rosen, Gary, American Compact: James Madison and the Problem of Founding (Kansas: University Press of Kansas, 1999), 148–49Google Scholar; Walling, Republican Empire, 162–67.

20 Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty, 332.

21 Brant, Irving, James Madison, 6 volumes (Indianapolis, IN, 19411961)Google Scholar; Beard, Charles, An Economic Interpretation of the Constitution (New York, 1913)Google Scholar; Diamond, Martin, “What the Framers Meant by Federalism,” in As Far As Republican Principles Will Admit (Washington, DC: AEI Press, 1992), 108–43Google Scholar.

22 Diamond, “What the Framers Meant by Federalism,” 34.

23 Diamond, “What the Framers Meant by Federalism,” 38.

24 Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty, 204–14.

25 Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty, 191, 210.

26 Madison acknowledges the difficulty of clearly and specifically defining the powers that belong to the national and state governments in his article “Government of the United States, 6 February 1792,” James Madison: Writings, 508–9.

27 On this point, consider also Madison's speech in Congress against authorizing the creation of a national bank because “he took notice of the peculiar manner in which the federal government is limited. It is not a general grant, out of which particular powers are excepted—it is a grant of particular powers only, leaving the general mass in other hands. So it had been understood by its friends and its foes, and so it was to be interpreted.” From “Speech in Congress Opposing the National Bank, 2 Feb. 1791,” James Madison: Writings, 480–90.

28 Madison noted similar natural limitations to increasing the size of the House of Representatives. In no. 55, he explained that as more members are added to the House, the quality of legislation increases until at some point the chamber becomes unmanageable and the quality of legislation declines.

29 James Madison, “Consolidation, 5 December 1791,” James Madison: Writings, 498–500. Derthick uses Madison's argument to explain the growth of judicial power in “Up-to-Date in Kansas City,” Keeping the Compound Republic, 77.

30 For references to the problems of distant democracy, see Yarbrough, Jean, “Republicanism Reconsidered: Some Thoughts on the Foundation and Preservation of the American Republic,” Review of Politics 41 (1979): 6195CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Zuckert, Michael P., “A System without Precedent: Federalism in the American Constitution,” in The Framing and Ratification of the Constitution, ed. Levy, Leonard W. and Mahoney, Dennis J. (Macmillan Publishing Company, 1987), 132–50Google Scholar.

31 Sheehan, “Madison v. Hamilton,” 421.

32 I think that identity rather than proximity may more accurately describe what Hamilton was trying to explain with this variable. If one's identity is most closely tied to one's state, as it was at the time of the founding, then proximity would include one's identity. In an increasingly mobile society, however, one's identity may be more closely related to one's nation than the state where one resides. Thus, individual identity would more accurately explain where one's loyalty will fall in an intergovernmental dispute than proximity.

33 The four reasons mentioned by Hamilton are as follows:

  1. 1)

    1) national elections will provide more choices to the people;

  2. 2)

    2) state legislatures will likely select the best people to serve in the U.S. Senate;

  3. 3)

    3) national councils will likely have more knowledge and information than state councils;

  4. 4)

    4) the spirit of faction will likely be reduced on the national level.

34 Scheiber, “Federalism and the Constitution,” 95, notes that Hamilton thinks public loyalty may be turned to the national government due to effective administration, but he does not recognize how important that idea is to Hamilton's thinking.

35 Hamilton, “Letter to Jonathan Dayton, Oct.–Nov., 1799,” Papers, 23:601.

36 Kramer, “Putting the Politics Back Into the Political Safeguards of Federalism,” 265, quotes Hamilton at the New York Ratifying Convention as saying the states will have a natural superiority over the national government, but Kramer misses that this comment is conditioned by Hamilton's later comment at the convention that the “true touchstone” of “public confidence” is “good administration” (271). There, as in no. 17, Hamilton is being subtle. He acknowledges that the states possess certain advantages over the federal government, but then carefully slips in the proviso that any such advantage may be undermined by the national government's better administration.

37 Banning, Sacred Fire of Liberty, 398, suggests that Madison was probably uneasy with certain of Hamilton's passages in no. 27 that implied the “central government should intrude increasingly and comprehensively into ‘matters of internal concern.’”

38 Madison's localism bias does not accurately reflect modern politics. Constitutional amendments and operating conventions have undermined the role of state government in these electoral processes.

39 For example, Levy, “Beyond Publius,” cites no. 17 as evidence that “at several points in the work, Publius's argument depends upon the greater affection or sympathy the people will naturally feel for the states than for the federal government … The Federalist builds loyalty to the states into the constitutional structure.”

40 Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty, 332.

41 Carey, In Defense of the Constitution, 2.

42 Walling, Republican Empire, 15.

43 Walling, Republican Empire, 172.

44 In a 1790 letter, John Jay advised his good friend Hamilton to pursue this course of action. Jay wrote: “The national Govt. has only to do what is right and if possible be silent. If compelled to speake, it shd be in few words strongly evincive of Temper, Dignity and self Respect. Conversation and desultory paragraphs will do the rest,” Papers of Alexander Hamilton, 28 Nov. 1790, 7:167.

45 Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty; Wills, Explaining America.

46 James Madison, “Public Opinion, 19 Dec. 1791,” James Madison: Writings, 500–501.

47 Gary Rosen, American Compact, 113, disagrees with this perspective. After a brilliant discussion of Madison's ideas on the need for founders with prudence, Rosen claims Madison discounts the need for elites with political prudence after the founding because representatives should take direction from public opinion. This claim suggests that Madison considered the constitutional order to be self-sustaining, requiring neither maintenance nor protection from factional interests or nonprudential do-gooders. Extrapolating from Rosen, Madison would support political safeguards of federalism and the public's role in those safeguards (Kramer develops just this idea in “Putting the Politics Back into the Political Safeguards of Federalism”).

48 In a letter to Jefferson on 4 Feb. 1790, Madison addresses Jefferson's argument that laws should not be binding on future generations. Madison strongly disagrees with this claim if by “law” Jefferson includes constitutions, but is less opposed if “law” refers to legislative acts. In other words, a popular majority should not alter the Constitution. James Madison, “Letter to Jefferson, 4 Feb. 1790,” James Madison: Writings, 473–77.

49 Some might see no. 10's republican remedy for the republican disease as a counterargument. However, the Constitution's remedy of an extended republic requires a federal system of government where the national government is limited to issues that concern the entire nation. This is because if the national government handles local issues unfavorably then the Constitution's localism bias would eventually prevail over national institutions and impair national power and authority. Madison's best hope to minimize the localism bias was to have the general government deal with general issues and the local government deal with local issues (39:213).

50 Sheehan, “Madison v. Hamilton,” emphasizes Madison's interest in making government policy reflect public opinion. I think much of her evidence regarding Madison's concern with public opinion refers to cultivating positive public sentiment for the constitutional order and maintaining that order against unconstitutional majority desires. Madison's elites are not always about educating the people; on fundamental constitutional questions, they are to decide without involving the public but in accordance with the Constitution and with an eye to sustaining public sentiment for the constitutional order. Madison's opposition to popular participation is particularly evident in the Federalist, nos. 49 and 50.

51 No. 51: “The different governments [national and state] will control each other, at the same time that each will be controlled by itself.” James Madison, “Government of the United States, 6 Feb. 1792,” James Madison: Writings, 508–9: “And as in a single government these departments [legislative, executive, and judicial] are to be kept separate and safe, by a defensive armour for each; so, it is to be hoped, do the [national and state] governments possess each the means of preventing or correcting unconstitutional encroachments of the other.”

52 Walling, Republican Empire, 156–61, suggests that John Jay, the third author of the Federalist, also must have supported judicial review.

53 Keith Whittington, “Judicial Review of Congress before the Civil War,” paper delivered at the Western Political Association Conference in Las Vegas, Nevada, March, 8–10, 2007.

54 Stewart Jay, Most Humble Servants: The Advisory Role of Early Judges (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1997), 60, 70, 76, 111–12.

55 This proposal was made by Charles Pinckney of South Carolina who had originally proposed giving the national government a veto of state laws, which Madison seconded, see Farrand, Max, ed., The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, vol. 2, (Massachusetts: The Murray Printing Co., 1966), 334, 342Google Scholar.

56 Jay, Most Humble Servants, 227.

57 Jay, Most Humble Servants, 111–48

58 In no. 73, Hamilton favorably mentions that the veto in New York is vested in a council of the governor, chancellor and judges of the Supreme Court, “or any two of them.” However, in the next paragraph he provides two “strong reasons” against involving the justices in a veto council. This passage is often used to suggest Hamilton opposed advisory opinions. Such a conclusion is suspect for three reasons. First, that Hamilton may have preferred some advisory role for justices is indicated by the preceding paragraph's positive view of New York's provision involving the state's highest court in veto decisions. Second, the passage refers to a veto council that unites the governor and Supreme Court and whose decisions have more weight than simple judicial advisory opinions. Third, Hamilton does not claim he agrees with these two reasons only that they bear consideration.

59 No. 16 refers specifically to the Supreme Court declaring state laws unconstitutional. This is consistent with Hamilton's desire to read the Constitution broadly, enhance the national government's powers, and limit the states. I think it wrong to imply from this that Hamilton limits judicial review to state laws as no. 78, which follows the same logic as no. 16, justifies judicial review of state and national laws.

60 Wechsler, “The Political Safeguards of Federalism”; Kramer, “Putting the Politics Back Into the Politics of Federalism.”

61 Diamond, Martin, The Founding of the Democratic Republic (Illinois: F. E. Peacock Publishers, Inc., 1981), 137Google Scholar.

62 Farrand, The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, 3: 424.

63 Farrand, Records of the Federal Convention, 2: 76–80.

64 Kramer misses Madison's clear reference to judicial review in no. 39 and hence misunderstands Madison's reference to judicial review in no. 44, which, he suggests, is to Blackstone's tenth rule of statutory construction (see Kramer, “Putting the Political Safeguards Back …” ns. 92 and 167). Acknowledging that Madison may be referring to judicial review in no. 44, he trivializes it by claiming that Madison gives it “little emphasis” (n. 167). Madison references the judiciary's responsibility again at the beginning of no. 45 when he writes, “Several important considerations have been touched in the course of these papers, which discountenance the supposition that the operation of the federal government will by degrees prove fatal to the State governments.” One concern is the judiciary. Rather than covering the same ground in this essay, he is moving on to the subject of the political safeguards of federalism.

65 James Madison, “Letter to Jefferson, 27 June 1823,” James Madison: Writings, 798–802.

66 Lenner, Andrew C., “John Taylor and the Origins of American Federalism,” Journal of the Early Republic (1997), 404Google Scholar.

67 James Madison, “Letter to Edward Everett, 28 August 1830,” James Madison: Writings, 842–52. Wechsler, “The Political Safeguards of Federalism,” 558–59, claims the 1830 letter to Everett proves Madison did not favor judicial review, but the letter actually shows Madison's strong support for judicial and political safeguards of federalism.

68 Walling, Republican Empire, 14–15.

69 This is consistent with how Madison explained the Virginia Resolve in his 28 Aug. 1830 letter to Edward Everett, James Madison: Writings, 842–52; of note in that letter is Madison's effort to distinguish the Virginia Resolve from the Kentucky Resolve, which supported nullification.

70 James Madison, “Report on the Alien and Sedition Acts, January 7, 1800,” James Madison: Writings, 608–62. See Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty, 389–93.

71 Derthick, Martha, “The Paradox of the Middle Tier,” in Keeping the Compound Republic: Essays on American Federalism (Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press, 2001), 4955Google Scholar; Walker, David B., The Rebirth of American Federalism (New York: Chatham House Publishers, 2000), 325Google Scholar.

72 Troy E. Smith, “Intergovernmental Lobbying in the 21st Century,” Intergovernmental Management for the 21st Century, ed. Paul L. Posner and Timothy J. Conlan (Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press, forthcoming). In Madison's 1830 letter to Everett, Madison appears to have realized the ineffectiveness of state governments collective actions and uses this as a reason to justify judicial review of the boundary between the national and state governments, James Madison: Writings, 842–52.

73 Eugene, C., Gramlich, Edward M., Heclo, Hugh, and Nightingale, Demetra Smith, The Government We Deserve: Responsive Democracy and Changing Expectations (Washington, DC: Urban Institute Press, 1998), 9596Google Scholar.

74 Ann O'M. Bowman and George A. Krause, “Power Shift: Measuring Policy Centralization in U.S. Intergovernmental Relations, 1947–1998,” American Politics Research 31, 3 (2003).

75 Martha Derthick, “The Paradox of the Middle Tier,” 46–49.

76 Elazar, Daniel J., “Federalism,” in Federalism in America: An Encyclopedia, ed. Marbach, Joseph R., Katz, Ellis, and Smith, Troy E. (Connecticut: Greenwood Press, 2006), 230–34Google Scholar.

77 Elazar, “Federalism.”

78 Lance Banning, The Sacred Fire of Liberty, 134–35, 398, notes that Madison's concerns with judicial review were less about judicial review and more about judicial supremacy.

79 Rogers, James R. and Vanberg, Georg, “Judicial Advisory Opinions and Legislative Outcomes in Comparative Perspective,” American Journal of Political Science 46, 2 (2002): 394CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

80 Ehrenhalt, Alan, The United States of Ambition: Politicians, Power and the Pursuit of Office (New York: Times Books, 1991)Google Scholar.

81 Nathan, Richard, “Federalism—The Great ‘Composition,’” in The New American Political System, ed. by King, Anthony, (Washington, DC: American Enterprise Institute, 1990), 231–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Rockefeller Institute Bulletin, “Devolution in the Polls: Long-Term Shift in Public Opinion/chapter-title>,” (Albany, New York: The Nelson A. Rockefeller Institute of Government, 1996), 14–16.

82 Cole, Richard L., Kincaid, John, and Rodriguez, Alejandro, “Public Opinion on Federalism and Federal Political Culture in Canada, Mexico, and the United States, 2004,” Publius 34, 4 (2004), 201–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

83 See Pietro S. Nivola, “Making Sense of Subsidiarity: Why Federalism Matters,” presented at the 2005 American Political Science Association Conference, (Washington, DC, Sept. 2).