Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-rkxrd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-17T09:52:27.388Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Are Hobbesian States as Passionate as Hobbesian Individuals?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 May 2023

Abstract

This article deals with the possibility of ascribing passions to states in Thomas Hobbes's political theory. According to Hobbes, the condition of sovereign states vis-à-vis one another is comparable to that of individuals in the state of nature, namely, a state of war. Consequently, the three causes of war (competition, diffidence, and glory) identified in chapter 13 of Leviathan could also be relevant to interstate relations. Since these war triggers are mainly passions, one could presume that state action is motivated by passions as well. Some argue that it is just a figurative way of speaking. Others claim that the passions of war affect only sovereign rulers. I explore an alternative answer based on the ability of sovereigns to direct the preexisting passions of their people.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of University of Notre Dame

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

My special thanks go to Ruth Abbey and four anonymous reviewers for their careful reading and their helpful criticism. I am also very grateful to Luciano Venezia, Gonzalo Bustamante, Leiser Madanes, Kajo Kubala, and the participants of the Princeton-Bucharest seminar and the Hobbes seminar at the University Adolfo Ibáñez for their insightful comments.

References

1 Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan, ed. Malcolm, Noel (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012)Google Scholar. Henceforth referred to as L and LL. The citation indicates chapter, paragraph number, and page number.

2 Hobbes, Thomas, On the Citizen, ed. Tuck, Richard (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998)Google Scholar. Henceforth DCv. The citation indicates chapter, paragraph number, and page number.

3 Gauthier, David, The Logic of Leviathan (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969), 207Google Scholar; Newey, Glen, Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Hobbes and “Leviathan” (London: Routledge, 2008), 208CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4 Bull, Hedley, “Hobbes and the International Anarchy,” Social Research 48, no. 4 (1981): 720–21Google Scholar.

5 Newey, Guidebook to Hobbes and “Leviathan, 166.

6 Armitage, David, Foundations of Modern International Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), 64Google Scholar.

7 Kavka, Gregory, Hobbesian Moral and Political Theory (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986), xiiGoogle Scholar.

8 The scholarship of the Hobbesian legacy in International Relations is huge. For an outline of the “Hobbesian tradition,” see Michael Williams, “Recasting the Hobbesian Legacy in International Political Theory,” in International Political Theory after Hobbes, ed. Raia Prokhovnik et al. (London: Palgrave, 2010), 147–67. Also, Christov, Theodore, Before Anarchy: Hobbes and His Critics in Modern International Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015), 624Google Scholar, glosses the interpretations of Hobbes's international thought during the twentieth century and the present.

9 Kateb, George, “Hobbes and the Irrationality of Politics,” Political Theory 17, no. 3 (1989): 381CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 Thomas Hobbes, Thomas White's “De Mundo” Examined, ed. Harold Jones (London: Bradford University Press, 1976), 12.4, 190. This contention is reiterated in the De Corpore, 11.7, in The English Works of Thomas Hobbes, ed. William Molesworth, vol. 1 (London: Bohn, 1839), 137. Henceforth DCo.

11 Crignon, Philippe, De l'incarnation à la représentation (Paris: Garnier, 2012), 109Google Scholar.

12 Brett, Annabel, “‘The Matter, Forme, and Power of a Common-Wealth’: Thomas Hobbes and Late Renaissance Commentary on Aristotle's Politics,” Hobbes Studies 23, no. 1 (2010): 96CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 Hobbes, Thomas White's “De Mundo” Examined, 12.4, 191.

14 Fleming, Sean, Leviathan on a Leash (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2020), 117Google Scholar.

15 Mikko Jakonen, “Multitude in Motion: Re-readings on the Political Philosophy of Thomas Hobbes” (PhD diss., University of Jyväskylä, 2013), 116.

16 Bardin, Andrea, “Liberty and Representation in Hobbes: A Materialist Theory of Conatus,” History of European Ideas 48, no. 6 (2022): 705CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Jesseph, Douglass, “Hobbes on ‘Conatus’: A Study in the Foundations of Hobbesian Philosophy,” Hobbes Studies 29, no. 1 (2016): 83CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 Field, Sandra, “Hobbes and the Question of Power,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 52, no. 1 (2014): 79–80CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

18 Newey, Guidebook to Hobbes and “Leviathan, 162.

19 Patapan, Haig, “The Glorious Sovereign: Thomas Hobbes’ Understanding of Leadership and International Relations,” in British International Thinkers from Hobbes to Namier, ed. Hall, Ian and Hill, Lisa (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2009), 12Google Scholar.

20 Gierke, Otto von, Natural Law and the Theory of Society, 1500 to 1800, ed. Barker, Ernest (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1934), 84Google Scholar.

21 List, Christian and Pettit, Philip, Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate Agents (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 76CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

23 Frost, Samantha, Lessons from a Materialist Thinker (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2008), 172CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24 Abizadeh, Arash, “Hobbes on the Causes of War: A Disagreement Theory,” American Political Science Review 105, no. 2 (2011): 310CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

25 I reconstruct the problem of diffidence and anticipatory violence without resorting to the distinction between dominators and moderate agents. For an alternative reading, see Eggers, Daniel, “Hobbes and Game Theory Revisited: Zero-Sum Games in the State of Nature,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 49, no. 3 (2011): 201–6CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

26 Hobbes, Thomas, The Elements of Law Natural and Politic, ed. Gaskin, John (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 9.9, 53Google Scholar. Henceforth EL. As Richard Tuck explains, while diffidence is defined as “constant despair” in L, 6.20, 84, this formulation does not quite convey the nature of the feeling. Tuck, “Hobbes's Moral Philosophy,” in The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes, ed. Tom Sorell (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 161.

27 Thomas Hobbes, Thomae Hobbes Malmesburiensis Vita Carmine Expressa, in Opera Philosophica Quae Latine Scripsit, ed. William Molesworth, vol. 1 (London: Bohn, 1849), line 86, my translation and emphasis.

28 On the topic of negative association as key to the formation and maintenance of Hobbesian political corporations, see Evrigenis, Ioannis, Fear of Enemies and Collective Action (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 121–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar and 126–28; Andrés Rosler, “El enemigo de la república,” in Elementos filosóficos: Del ciudadano, by Thomas Hobbes (Buenos Aires: Hydra, 2011), 42; and Christov, Before Anarchy, 73.

29 Ionut Untea, “External Authority or External Threat? Thomas Hobbes and the Politically Troubled Times of Early Modern England,” in The Representation of External Threats, ed. Eberhard Crailsheim and María Dolores Elizalde (Leiden: Brill, 2019), 230, regards the pope's intromissions and the creation of an internal Catholic enemy in this way.

30 As Lechner, Silviya, Hobbesian Internationalism: Anarchy, Authority and the Fate of Political Philosophy (Cham: Springer, 2019), 4950CrossRefGoogle Scholar, asserts: “Hobbes connects the premise of diffidence to a premise of incomplete knowledge. . . . Prior to interaction the identity of agents remains opaque.”

31 Hobbes, Thomas, A Dialogue between a Philosopher and a Student, of the Common Laws of England (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), 12Google Scholar. Hereafter D.

32 Jakonen, Multitude, 96.

33 Kapust, Daniel, “The Problem of Flattery and Hobbes's Institutional Defense of Monarchy,” Journal of Politics 73, no. 3 (2011): 686CrossRefGoogle Scholar and 690.

34 On the comparative and subjective aspects of power, see Gabriella Slomp, Thomas Hobbes and the Political Philosophy of Glory (New York: St. Martin's, 2000), 39–40; and Yves Zarka, Hobbes and Modern Political Thought (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2016), 75.

35 There is no consensus on this issue. Kavka, Hobbesian Moral and Political Theory, 116, distinguishes “dominators,” or those “who possess . . . the desire of power over other people,” from “moderates,” whose “considerations of safety [are] their primary motives.” Pärtel Piirimäe, “The Explanation of Conflict in Hobbes's Leviathan,” TRAMES 10 (60/55) (2006): 7, and Ioannis Evrigenis, “The State of Nature,” in The Oxford Handbook of Hobbes, ed. Kinch Hoekstra and Aloysius Martinich (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016), 230, understate this distinction.

36 Gauthier, Logic of Leviathan, 16.

37 This view was held to one extent or another by Hampton, Jean, Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), 3839Google Scholar; Oakeshott, Michael, Hobbes on Civil Association (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 2000), 127–28Google Scholar; Thivet, Delphine, “Thomas Hobbes: A Philosopher of War or Peace?,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 16, no. 4 (2008): 714CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Cooper, Julie, “Vainglory, Modesty, and Political Agency in the Political Theory of Thomas Hobbes,” Review of Politics 72, no. 2 (2010): 248CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

38 Thomas Hobbes, De Homine, in Opera Philosophica Quae Latine Scripsit, ed. William Molesworth, vol. 2 (London: Bohn, 1849), 11.6, 98. Henceforth DH.

39 On reputation as a positional good, see Barbara Carnevali, “Glory: La lutte pour la réputation dans le modèle hobbesien,” Communications, no. 93 (2013) : 54.

40 Slomp, Political Philosophy of Glory, 52, maintains that “for Hobbes, as for Thucydides, ambition and pride characterise not only the behaviour of single individuals, but also the actions of entire peoples and nations.”

41 Hobbes, Thomas, Behemoth, ed. Seaward, Paul (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 253Google Scholar. Henceforth B.

42 As explained by Gerald Gaus, “Hobbes's Idea of Public Judgment: A Social Coordination Analysis,” http://www.gaus.biz/Gaus-HobbesJudgment.pdf, 18, in the context of a battle, the commander in chief should refrain from “making judgments that the subordinates consider fantastic.”

43 The concept of popularity is pejorative in the Elements (EL, 9.7, 175–76) and De Cive (DCv, 13.13, 149), where it is associated with subjects who, on account of their popularity, can form factions and rebel against the sovereign power.