Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-x4r87 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T15:42:24.529Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Propositional faith and trustworthiness

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 June 2022

Allan Hazlett*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Washington University in St. Louis, 1 Brookings Drive, St. Louis, MO 63130, USA

Abstract

I argue that propositional faith presupposes trustworthiness, in this sense: faith that p is fitting only if the one in whom you have faith to bring it about that p is trustworthy to bring it about that p. In defence of this, I argue that propositional faith is a species of interpersonal faith and that interpersonal faith presupposes trustworthiness. I also discuss some of the consequences of my thesis for theistic propositional faith.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, RM (1995) Moral faith. Journal of Philosophy 92, 7595.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alston, WP (1988) Divine and human action. In Morris, TV (ed.), Divine and Human Action. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, pp. 257280.Google Scholar
Alston, WP (1996) Belief, acceptance, and religious faith. In Jordan, J and Howard-Snyder, D (eds), Faith, Freedom, and Rationality: Essays in the Philosophy of Religion. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, pp. 327.Google Scholar
Anscombe, GEM (1979) What is it to believe someone? In Delaney, CF (ed.), Rationality and Religious Belief. South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 141151.Google Scholar
Baier, A (1986) Trust and antitrust. Ethics 96, 231260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bishop, J (1998) Can there be alternative conceptions of God? Noûs 32, 174188.10.1111/0029-4624.00095CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bishop, J (2009) Towards a religiously adequate alternative to omniGod theism. Sophia 48, 419433.10.1007/s11841-009-0130-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bishop, J and Perszyck, K (2014) Divine action beyond the personal omniGod. Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion 5, 121.Google Scholar
Bishop, J and Perszyck, K (2016a) Concepts of God and problems of evil. In Buckareff, AA and Nagasawa, Y (eds), Alternative Concepts of God: Essays on the Metaphysics of the Divine. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 106127.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198722250.003.0007CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bishop, J and Perszyck, K (2016b) God as person – religious psychology and metaphysical understanding. In Schärd, T, Tapp, C and Wegener, V (eds), Rethinking the Concept of a Personal God: Classical Theism, Personal Theism, and Alternative Conceptions of God. Münster: Aschendorrf Verlag, pp. 227241.Google Scholar
Bishop, J and Perszyck, K (2017) The divine attributes and non-personal conceptions of God. Topoi 36, 609621.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bratman, M (2014) Shared Agency: A Planning Theory of Acting Together. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, D (1989) Trinitarian personhood and individuality. In Feenstra, RJ and Plantinga, C (eds), Trinity, Incarnation, and Atonement: Philosophical and Theological Essays. South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 4878.Google Scholar
Cooper, JW (2006) Panentheism: The Other God of the Philosophers. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic.Google Scholar
Darwall, D (2006) The Second Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Davies, B (1987) Classical theism and the doctrine of divine simplicity. In Davies, B (ed.), Language, Meaning, and God: Essays in Honor of Herbert McCabe OP. London: Cassell Publishers, pp. 5174.Google Scholar
Davies, B (2003) Letter from America. New Blackfriars 84, 371384.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, B (2008) Is God a moral agent? In Phillips, DZ (ed.), Whose God? Which Tradition? The Nature of Belief in God. London: Routledge, pp. 97122.Google Scholar
Davies, B (2009) Simplicity. In Talliaferro, C and Meister, C (eds), The Cambridge Companion to Christian Philosophical Theology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 3145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dick, PK (1987) The Minority Report and Other Stories. New York: Citadel Press.Google Scholar
Hardin, R (2002) Trust and Trustworthiness. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.Google Scholar
Hasker, W (2010) Objections to social trinitarianism. Religious Studies 46, 421439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hasker, W (2013) Metaphysics and the Tri-Personal God. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199681518.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hewitt, S (2019) God is not a person (an argument via pantheism). International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 85, 281296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holton, R (1994) Deciding to trust, coming to believe. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72, 6376.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard-Snyder, D (2003) Trinity monotheism. Philosophia Christi 5, 375403.10.5840/pc20035245CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard-Snyder, D (2013) Propositional faith: what it is and what it is not. American Philosophical Quarterly 50, 357372.Google Scholar
Howard-Snyder, D (2015) Review of W. Hasker, Metaphysics and the Tri-Personal God (Oxford University Press, 2013). Faith and Philosophy 32, 1019.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard-Snyder, D (2016) Two peas in a single polytheistic pod: John Hick and Richard Swinburne. Journal of Philosophical Research 41, 1732.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnston, M (2009) Saving God: Religion after Idolatry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, K (1996) Trust as an affective attitude. Ethics 107, 425.10.1086/233694CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, K (2012) Trustworthiness. Ethics 123, 6185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahane, G (2011) Should we want God to exist? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82, 674696.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Layman, CS (1988) Tritheism and the Trinity. Faith and Philosophy 5, 291298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leftow, B (2009) Anti social trinitarianism. In McCall, T and Rea, M (eds), Philosophical and Theological Essays on the Trinity. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 5288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levine, M (1994) Pantheism: A Non-Theistic Conception of Deity. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
List, C and Pettit, P (2011) Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate Agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moreland, JP and Craig, WL (2017) Philosophical Foundations of a Christian Worldview, 2nd edn. Downer's Grove: InterVarsity Press.Google Scholar
Perszyck, K (2018) Motivating the search for alternatives to personal omniGod theism: the case from classical theism. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 10, 97118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, P (1995) The cunning of trust. Philosophy and Public Affairs 24, 202225.10.1111/j.1088-4963.1995.tb00029.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, C (1989) Social trinity and tritheism. In Feenstra, RJ and Plantinga, C (eds), Trinity, Incarnation, and Atonement: Philosophical and Theological Essays. South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 2147.Google Scholar
Roth, AS (2017) Shared agency. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/shared-agency/.Google Scholar
Schellenberg, JL (2014) How to make faith a virtue. In Callaghan, LF and O'Connor, T (eds), Religious Faith and Intellectual Virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 7496.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199672158.003.0004CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, R (1994) The Christian God. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B (1995) Internal reasons and the obscurity of blame. In Making Sense of Humanity and Other Philosophical Papers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 3545.CrossRefGoogle Scholar