Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-cnmwb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-17T06:37:06.357Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Embracing the mystery: David Hume's playful religion of wonder

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 August 2023

Hannah Lingier*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Antwerp, Antwerp, Belgium

Abstract

In this article I show how David Hume's works provide the ingredients for a conception of religiosity understood as a feeling of wonder concerning nature or existence, accompanied by a playful attitude regarding the imaginative shapes that can be given to this emotion. Hume serves as an inspiration rather than an object of study: I respect the spirit and values of his work, while going beyond his own explicit points. My reading accounts for Hume's aversion to traditional religions (‘superstition’), and for his acknowledgement of the universal attraction of the idea of invisible intelligent power and his own fascination with it. I argue first that superstition is a natural reaction to existential uncertainty. Second, I argue that uncertainty fuels activity, creativity and morality, and thus may be left untended. Though it always involves a measure of pain, too, human happiness is found in challenge and activity. Traditional monotheist religions respond to this need by generating experiences of wonder, thus, however, stimulating passive devotion and dogmatism. Opposing this, the suggestion of Hume's works is to respect the mystery of nature rather than shrouding it in unfounded convictions. The fictional character Philo illustrates how the longing for an answer by is itself can already be a profoundly religious feeling. Hume's descriptions of ancient polytheism and Philo show how this can be accompanied by a playful, imaginative interaction with the world.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Costelloe, T (2004) ‘In every civilized community’: Hume on belief and the demise of religion. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 55, 171185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Costelloe, T (2018) The Imagination in Hume's Philosophy: The Canvas of the Mind. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cottrell, J (2019) The imagination in Hume's philosophy: the canvas of the mind by Timothy M. Costelloe. Journal of the History of Philosophy 57, 559560.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deckard, MF (2011) ‘Of curiosity, or the love of truth’: David Hume on wonder in A Treatise of Human Nature. In Losonczi, P and Deckard, MF (eds), Philosophy Begins in Wonder: An Introduction to Early Modern Philosophy, Theology, and Science. Cambridge: The Lutterworth Press, pp. 211233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deleuze, G (2001) Empiricism and Subjectivity: An Essay on Hume's Theory of Human Nature. Boundas CV (trans.). New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D (1983a) The History of England from the Invasion of Julius Caesar to the Revolution in 1688, vol. 3. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Hume, D (1983b) The History of England from the Invasion of Julius Caesar to the Revolution in 1688, vol. 5. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Hume, D (1987) Essays, Moral, Political, and Literary. Miller EF (ed.). Indianapolis: Liberty Classics.Google Scholar
Hume, D (2006a) An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals: A Critical Edition. Beauchamp TL (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D (2006b) An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding: A Critical Edition. Beauchamp TL (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D (2009) A Dissertation on the Passions; The Natural History of Religion. Beauchamp TL (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D (2011) A Treatise of Human Nature: Volume 1: Texts. Norton DF and Norton MJ (eds). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D (2012) Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. Popkin H (ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Jordan, WR (2002) Religion in the public square: a reconsideration of David Hume and religious establishment. The Review of Politics 64, 687713.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lemmens, W (2011) Beyond the calm sunshine of the mind: Hume on religion and morality. Aufklärung und Kritik: Zeitschrift für freies Denken und humanistische Philosophie 18, 214240.Google Scholar
Lingier, H (2021) Hume's dialogues: a natural explanation of natural religion? International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 82, 233248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, J (1824) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, 25th edn. London: William Baynes.Google Scholar
Plate, SB (2011) Religion is playing games: playing video gods, playing to play. Religious Studies and Theology 29, 215230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sabl, A (2012) Hume's Politics: Coordination and Crisis in the History of England, 1st edn. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Savage, R (2012) Philosophy and Religion in Enlightenment Britain: New Case Studies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Susato, R (2015) Hume's Sceptical Enlightenment. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Teismann, MW and Weber, L (2020) A Playful Spirit: Exploring the Theology, Philosophy, and Psychology of Play. Lanham: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Willis, A (2014) Toward a Humean True Religion: Genuine Theism, Moderate Hope, and Practical Morality, 1st edn. University Park: Penn State University Press.Google Scholar
Willis, A (2015) The potential use-value of Hume's ‘true religion’. Journal of Scottish Philosophy 13, 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yenor, S (2006) Revealed religion and the politics of humanity in Hume's philosophy of common life. Polity 38, 395415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar