Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-tn8tq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-26T16:37:24.106Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Conceptual plausibility and the rationality of theistic belief

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 May 2023

Ricardo Sousa Silvestre*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Federal University of Campina Grande, Campina Grande-PB, Brazil

Abstract

In this article, I present a defence of conceptual plausibility, understood as an epistemic way to qualify concepts that situates them between the merely possible and the actual. To show that there is such a thing as conceptual plausibility, I rely on what seems to lie at the heart of many uses of the phrase ‘plausible concept’: explanatory fruitfulness. To make an effective case for the claim that conceptual plausibility is of philosophical interest, I present an argument based on the debate over the rationality of theistic belief and the concept of God. To show that conceptual plausibility is philosophically feasible, I first show that it cannot be reduced to propositional plausibility. Next, I offer a minimally precise characterization of conceptual plausibility; I approach this from a qualitative and comparative perspective as well. Finally, I show how these qualitative and comparative criteria of conceptual plausibility might be applied to the debate over the rationality of theistic belief and the concept of God.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Avena, N, Rada, P and Hoebel, B (2008) Evidence for sugar addiction: behavioral and neurochemical effects of intermittent, excessive sugar intake. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews 32, 2039.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Boudreaux, D and Crampton, E (2003) Truth and consequences: some economics of false consciousness. The Independent Review 8, 2745.Google Scholar
Carnap, R (1946) Remarks on induction and truth. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 6, 590602.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, R (1962) Logical Foundations of Probability, 2nd edn. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Edwards, S (2003) Three concepts of suffering. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 6, 5966.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Göcke, B (2017) Concepts of God and models of the God–world relation. Philosophy Compass 12, e12402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Habermas, J (1997) Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Ivani, S (2019) What we (should) talk about when we talk about fruitfulness. European Journal for Philosophy of Science 9, 318.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
King, J (2019) Structured propositions. In Zalta E (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 Edition). Available at https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/propositions-structured/.Google Scholar
Koch, S (2019) Carnapian explications, experimental philosophy, and fruitful concepts. Inquiry: A Journal of Medical Care Organization, Provision and Financing 62, 700717.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T (1977) The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Larson, G (2013) Hindu theology: materialism, dualism, and the philosophy of yoga. International Journal of Hindu Studies 17, 181219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Margolis, E and Laurence, S (2019) Concepts. In Zalta E (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 Edition). Available at https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/concepts/.Google Scholar
Murphy, G (2002) The Big Book of Concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owen, H (1971) Concepts of Deity. London: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Post, J (1980) Infinite regresses of justification and of explanation. Philosophical Studies 38, 3152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quinn, P (2002) Value and the good life. Faith and Philosophy 19, 385390.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, B (1903) Principles of Mathematics, 2nd edn. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Schlecker, M (2021) The Architectures of Planetary Systems: Population Synthesis Meets Observations (doctoral dissertation). Heidelberg: Max Planck Institute for Astronomy.Google Scholar
Shults, FL (2014) Theology after the Birth of God. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silvestre, R (2021) Inductive plausibility and certainty. In Trepczyński, M (ed.), Philosophical Approaches to the Foundations of Logics and Mathematics. Leiden: Brill, pp. 194210.Google Scholar
Slater, M (2007) Ethical naturalism and religious belief in ‘the moral philosopher and the moral life’. William James Studies 2, 147.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R (2004) The Existence of God, 2nd edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, R (2010) Is there a God?, rev. edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weiss, F (2013) Food and Addiction: A Comprehensive Handbook, by Brownell, K. & Gold, M. (eds.), book review. American Journal of Psychotherapy 67, 302307.Google Scholar