Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-jbqgn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-23T22:54:57.159Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Logic and Faith

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 February 2009

Extract

“He who tries to rise above reason, falls outside of it,” said Plotinus. If this be so; if, as Plotinus said also, “ Nous is King,” reason must cover more than inferential reasoning. The methods of inference are not sovereign, but manifestly instrumental; they furnish the scaffolding for the mind's ascent, but not the goal of its endeavour. This distinction between the wider and the narrower use of reason is familiar in every age of thought; it appears in the Platonic and Aristotelian doctrines of Nous, in Aquinas's discrimination of discursive and intuitive knowledge, in Spinoza's of ratio and scientia intuiliva, and in that of the understanding and the reason in post–Kantian idealism. At times, as in the case last mentioned, it has been pressed to an extreme, with the result that reason was set in sharp contrast to the understanding, which came to be regarded as a separate faculty and even as a source of error. Wordsworth, to whom the antithesis passed through Coleridge, wrote of “that false secondary power, by which we multiply distinctions.” In face of such excesses, it behoves us to be on our guard, and to remember that thought is one amid the diversity of its operations, and that faith is at least as fallible as logic. It is only by co-operating in the service of reason that either can point the way to truth.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1926

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 421 note 1 In his Inaugural Lecture on Immediate Experience and Mediation, Oxford, 1919.Google Scholar

page 424 note 1 Inge, , Christian Mysticism, pp. 225–6.Google Scholar

page 428 note 1 Cf. Whitehead, , Science and the Modern World, p. 26Google Scholar: “ The faith in the order of nature which has made possible the growth of science is a particular example of a deeper faith. This faith cannot be justified by any inductive generalization. It springs from direct inspection of the nature of things as disclosed in our own immediate experience.”

page 430 note 1 In Science and the Modern World, Lowell Lectures, 1925.

page 430 note 2 If any reader questions this, he may be referred to Otto's Das Heilige.

page 431 note 1 Inge, , Christian Mysticism, p. 205.Google Scholar

page 432 note 1 See Otto's book, passim.

page 434 note 1 The reader who desires to follow out this question is referred to Professor A. E. Taylor's article on “ Theism “ in the Encyclopœdia of Religion and Ethics,

page 435 note 1 The restriction of the term “ rational” to conceptual thinking, and the description of non-logical apprehension as “non-rational” seems to me a serious defect in Otto's notable work. He is led, for instance, in his twelfth chapter, to regard Platonism, on its religious side, as “ non-rational.”