Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-mwx4w Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-16T13:52:57.944Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Intellectual Virtue Signaling and (Non)Expert Credibility

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 May 2024

KEITH RAYMOND HARRIS*
Affiliation:
UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA keithraymondharris@gmail.com

Abstract

In light of the complexity of some important matters, the best epistemic strategy for laypersons is often to rely heavily on the judgments of subject matter experts. However, given the contentiousness of some issues and the existence of fake experts, determining who to trust from the lay perspective is no simple matter. One proposed approach is for laypersons to attend to displays of intellectual virtue as indicators of expertise. I argue that this strategy is likely to fail, as non-experts often display apparent intellectual virtues while legitimate experts often display apparent intellectual vices. Then, I argue that this challenge is difficult to overcome, as experts who attempt to better exhibit apparent intellectual virtues would likely compromise their own reliability in the process. Finally, I discuss two conclusions—one more optimistic and one more pessimistic—that one might draw concerning the role of intellectual virtue in the identification of experts.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The American Philosophical Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Altay, Sacha, Nera, Kenzo, Ejaz, Waqas, Schöpfer, Céline, and Tomas, Frédéric. 2023. “Conspiracy Believers Claim to Be Free Thinkers but (Under)Use Advice like Everyone Else.” British Journal of Social Psychology, May, bjso.12655. https://doi.org/10.1111/bjso.12655.Google ScholarPubMed
Anvari, Farid, and Lakens, Daniël. 2018. “The Replicability Crisis and Public Trust in Psychological Science.” Comprehensive Results in Social Psychology 3 (3): 266–86. https://doi.org/10.1080/23743603.2019.1684822.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ballantyne, Nathan, Celniker, Jared B., and Dunning, David. 2022. “‘Do Your Own Research.’” Social Epistemology 0 (0): 116. https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2022.2146469.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Battaly, Heather. 2018a. “Closed-Mindedness and Dogmatism.” Episteme 15 (3): 261–82. https://doi.org/10.1017/epi.2018.22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Battaly, Heather. 2018b. “Can Closed-Mindedness Be an Intellectual Virtue?” Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 84 (November): 2345. https://doi.org/10.1017/S135824611800053X.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Battaly, Heather. 2021. “Intellectual Autonomy and Intellectual Interdependence.” In Epistemic Autonomy, by Matheson, Jonathan and Lougheed, Kirk, 1st ed., 153–72. New York: Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781003003465-12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bland, Steven. 2022. “Interactionism, Debiasing, and the Division of Epistemic Labour.” In Social Virtue Epistemology, by Alfano, Mark, Klein, Colin, and Ridder, Jeroen De, 1st ed., 1538. New York: Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9780367808952-3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brooks, Patrick. forthcoming. “On the Origin of Conspiracy Theories.” Philosophical Studies. https://philarchive.org/rec/BROOTO-6.Google Scholar
Buzzell, Andrew, and Rini, Regina. 2023. “Doing Your Own Research and Other Impossible Acts of Epistemic Superheroism.” Philosophical Psychology 36 (5): 906–30. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2022.2138019.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Etchells, Pete. 2014. “Bill Nye v Ken Ham: Should Scientists Bother to Debate Creationism?” The Guardian, February 5, 2014, sec. Science. https://www.theguardian.com/science/head-quarters/2014/feb/05/bill-nye-vs-ken-ham-creationism-science-debate.Google Scholar
Fricker, Elizabeth. 2006. “Testimony and Epistemic Autonomy.” In The Epistemology of Testimony, edited by Lackey, Jennifer and Sosa, Ernest, 1st ed., 225–50. Oxford University Press: Oxford. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199276011.003.0011.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, Miranda. 2010. “Can There Be Institutional Virtues?” Oxford Studies in Epistemology 3: 235–52.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin I. 2001. “Experts: Which Ones Should You Trust?” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (1): 85110. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1933-1592.2001.tb00093.x.Google Scholar
Hardwig, John. 1985. “Epistemic Dependence.” The Journal of Philosophy 82 (7): 335. https://doi.org/10.2307/2026523.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harris, Keith Raymond. 2021. “Collective Intellectual Humility and Arrogance.” Synthese 199 (3): 6967–79. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03101-y.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hill, Jesse, and Fanciullo, James. 2023. “What's Wrong with Virtue Signaling?” Synthese 201 (4): 117. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04131-4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huemer, Michael. 2005. “Is Critical Thinking Epistemically Responsible?” Metaphilosophy 36 (4): 522–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keeley, Brian L. 1999. “Of Conspiracy Theories.” The Journal of Philosophy 96 (3): 109. https://doi.org/10.2307/2564659.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, Bruce Y. 2023. “Why Peter Hotez Should Not Debate RFK Jr. On The Joe Rogan Experience.” Forbes. 2023. https://www.forbes.com/sites/brucelee/2023/06/26/why-peter-hotez-should-not-debate-rfk-jr-on-the-joe-rogan-experience/.Google Scholar
Levy, Neil. 2022a. Bad Beliefs: Why They Happen to Good People. First edition. New York: Oxford University Press.Google ScholarPubMed
Levy, Neil. 2022b. “Narrowing the Scope of Virtue Epistemology.” In Social Virtue Epistemology, by Alfano, Mark, Klein, Colin, and Ridder, Jeroen De, 1st ed., 113–30. New York: Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9780367808952-15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levy, Neil. 2022c. “Do Your Own Research!” Synthese 200 (5): 356. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03793-w.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Levy, Neil. 2023. “Intellectual Virtue Signaling.” American Philosophical Quarterly 60 (3): 311–24. https://doi.org/10.5406/21521123.60.3.07.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matheson, David. 2005. “Conflicting Experts and Dialectical Performance: Adjudication Heuristics for the Layperson.” Argumentation 19 (2): 145–58. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-004-7041-0.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matheson, Jonathan. 2021. “The Virtue of Epistemic Autonomy.” In Epistemic Autonomy, 173–94. Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prooijen, Jan-Willem van, Douglas, Karen M., and De Inocencio, Clara. 2018. “Connecting the Dots: Illusory Pattern Perception Predicts Belief in Conspiracies and the Supernatural.” European Journal of Social Psychology 48 (3): 320–35. https://doi.org/10.1002/ejsp.2331.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Riggs, Wayne. 2010. “Open-Mindedness.” Metaphilosophy 41 (1–2): 172–88. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9973.2009.01625.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saint-Croix, Catharine. forthcoming. “Epistemic Virtue Signaling and the Double Bind of Testimonial Injustice.” Philosophers’ Imprint.Google Scholar
Smart, Paul R. 2018. “Mandevillian Intelligence.” Synthese 195 (9): 41694200. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1414-z.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Smith, Gary. 2023. Distrust: Big Data, Data-Torturing, and the Assault on Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swami, Viren, Voracek, Martin, Stieger, Stefan, Tran, Ulrich S., and Furnham, Adrian. 2014. “Analytic Thinking Reduces Belief in Conspiracy Theories.” Cognition 133 (3): 572–85. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2014.08.006.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tanesini, Alessandra. 2023. “Intellectual Arrogance: Individual, Group-Based, and Corporate.” Synthese 202 (1): 120. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04224-0.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tosi, Justin, and Warmke, Brandon. 2016. “Moral Grandstanding.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 44 (3): 197217. https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12075.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tosi, Justin, and Warmke, Brandon. 2020. Grandstanding: The Use and Abuse of Moral Talk. New York (N.Y.): Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Westra, Evan. 2021. “Virtue Signaling and Moral Progress.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 49 (2): 156–78. https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wingen, Tobias, Berkessel, Jana B., and Englich, Birte. 2020. “No Replication, No Trust? How Low Replicability Influences Trust in Psychology.” Social Psychological and Personality Science 11 (4): 454–63. https://doi.org/10.1177/1948550619877412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zagzebski, Linda Trinkaus. 1996. Virtues of the Mind: An Inquiry Into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar